Sigmund Freud Dream Theory

Saul McLeod, PhD

Editor-in-Chief for Simply Psychology

BSc (Hons) Psychology, MRes, PhD, University of Manchester

Saul McLeod, PhD., is a qualified psychology teacher with over 18 years of experience in further and higher education. He has been published in peer-reviewed journals, including the Journal of Clinical Psychology.

Learn about our Editorial Process

Olivia Guy-Evans, MSc

Associate Editor for Simply Psychology

BSc (Hons) Psychology, MSc Psychology of Education

Olivia Guy-Evans is a writer and associate editor for Simply Psychology. She has previously worked in healthcare and educational sectors.

Ioanna Stavraki

Community Wellbeing Professional, Educator

BSc (Hons) Psychology, MSc, Neuropsychology, MBPsS

Ioanna Stavraki is a healthcare professional leading NHS Berkshire's Wellbeing Network Team and serving as a Teaching Assistant at The University of Malawi for the "Organisation Psychology" MSc course. With previous experience at Frontiers' "Computational Neuroscience" journal and startup "Advances in Clinical Medical Research," she contributes significantly to neuroscience and psychology research. Early career experience with Alzheimer's patients and published works, including an upcoming IET book chapter, underscore her dedication to advancing healthcare and neuroscience understanding.

On This Page:

Freud (1900) considered dreams to be the royal road to the unconscious as it is in dreams that the ego’s defenses are lowered so that some of the repressed material comes through to awareness, albeit in distorted form.

dream

Dreams perform important functions for the unconscious mind and serve as valuable clues to how the unconscious mind operates.

On 24 July 1895, Freud had his own dream to form the basis of his theory. He had been worried about a patient, Irma, who was not doing as well in treatment as he had hoped. Freud, in fact, blamed himself for this and was feeling guilty.

Freud dreamed that he met Irma at a party and examined her.  He then saw a chemical formula for a drug that another doctor had given Irma flash before his eyes and realized that her condition was caused by a dirty syringe used by the other doctor. Freud’s guilt was thus relieved.

Freud interpreted this dream as wish fulfillment. He had wished that Irma’s poor condition was not his fault and the dream had fulfilled this wish by informing him that another doctor was at fault. Based on this dream, Freud (1900) proposed that a major function of dreams was the fulfillment of wishes.

Freud’s Interpretation of Dreams

The Interpretation of Dreams is a seminal work by Sigmund Freud, published in 1899, that introduced his theory of psychoanalysis and dream interpretation. Here’s a summary of its key points:
  • Introduction of Psychoanalysis : This book is where Freud first introduced his theory of psychoanalysis . This was a revolutionary approach to understanding the human mind and behavior, focusing on the role of the unconscious mind, which was largely ignored or underestimated by other theories of the time. The Interpretation of Dreams introduced key concepts of psychoanalysis such as the Oedipus complex , and free association.
  • Dreams as Psychological Insight : Freud proposed that dreams could provide valuable insight into an individual’s unconscious desires and conflicts. This was a novel idea, as dreams were often dismissed as meaningless or were interpreted in a more mystical or religious context.
  • Dreams as Wish Fulfillment : Freud proposed that dreams are a form of “wish fulfillment”. They represent the unconscious desires, thoughts, and motivations that our conscious mind represses. This concept has influenced not only the field of psychology but also literature, art, and popular culture.
  • Manifest and Latent Content : Freud distinguished between the manifest content of a dream (what we remember upon waking) and the latent content (the hidden psychological meaning). The manifest content is often a distorted version of the wish that the dreamer’s mind tries to fulfill, while the latent content is the underlying wish itself.
  • Dream Work : The process by which the unconscious mind alters the true meaning of a dream into something less disturbing is known as “dream work”. This includes mechanisms like displacement (shifting emotional significance from one object to another), condensation (combining several ideas into one), and symbolization (representing an action or idea through symbols).
  • Free Association : Freud used a technique called free association to uncover the latent content of dreams. In this process, a person says whatever comes to mind to a dream’s elements, leading to insights about the unconscious wishes the dream represents.

Latent Content as the Hidden Meaning of Your Dreams

Latent content in dreams, a concept introduced by Sigmund Freud in his psychoanalytic theory, refers to the hidden, symbolic, and unconscious meanings or themes behind the events of a dream.

This contrasts the manifest content, which is the actual storyline or events that occur in the dream as the dreamer remembers them.

Freud believed that the latent content of a dream is often related to unconscious desires, wishes, and conflicts. These are thoughts and feelings that are so troubling or unacceptable that the conscious mind represses them. However, they can emerge in a disguised form in our dreams.

The latent content is not directly observable because it is often coded or symbolized in the dream’s manifest content. For example, a dream about losing teeth might have a latent content related to anxiety about aging or fear of losing power or control (though interpretations can vary greatly depending on the individual).

How the Mind Censors Latent Content

Sigmund Freud proposed that the mind uses a process called “dream work” to censor or disguise the latent content of a dream. The latent content, which represents our unconscious wishes and desires, is often disturbing or socially unacceptable.

The purpose of dreamwork is to transform the forbidden wish into a non-threatening form, thus reducing anxiety and allowing us to continue sleeping.

Dreamwork involves the process of condensation, displacement, and secondary elaboration:

  • Displacement : This involves shifting the emotional significance from an important object to a less important one. Displacement takes place when we transform the person or object we are really concerned about to someone else. For example, one of Freud’s patients was extremely resentful of his sister-in-law and used to refer to her as a dog, dreaming of strangling a small white dog. Freud interpreted this as representing his wish to kill his sister-in-law.  If the patient would have really dreamed of killing his sister-in-law, he would have felt guilty. The unconscious mind transformed her into a dog to protect him.
  • Condensation : This is the process of combining several ideas or people into a single dream object or event. For example, a dream about a man may be a dream about both one’s father and one’s lover. A dream about a house might be the condensation of worries about security as well as worries about one’s appearance to the rest of the world.
  • Symbolization : This is the representation of a repressed idea or wish through symbols. For example, a dream about climbing a ladder might symbolize ambition or a desire for success.
  • Secondary Elaboration : Secondary elaboration occurs when the unconscious mind strings together wish-fulfilling images in a logical order of events, further obscuring the latent content.  It can involve adding details or creating a storyline that connects the different elements of the dream. According to Freud, this is why the manifest content of dreams can be in the form of believable events.

These mechanisms work together to transform the latent content into the manifest content, allowing the dreamer to remain asleep and unaware of the disturbing or unacceptable thoughts and desires expressed in the dream.

However, through techniques like free association and dream analysis, Freud believed that it was possible to uncover the latent content and gain insight into the unconscious mind .

Psychoanalytic Dream Interpretation

Sigmund Freud developed several techniques to uncover the latent content of dreams, which he believed represented the unconscious desires and conflicts of the dreamer. Here are the main techniques:

Free-Association

Freud used a technique called free association to uncover the latent content of dreams. In this process, a person says whatever comes to mind in relation to each element of the dream, without censoring or judging their thoughts.

In free association, the individual is encouraged to share any thoughts that come to mind about each element of the dream, no matter how random or unconnected they may seem.

The idea is that these associations can lead to insights into the unconscious wishes or conflicts that the dream represents.

Transference

Transference is a process where the feelings and desires that the individual has towards significant people in their life are transferred onto the therapist.

Observing these transference patterns can provide clues about the latent content of the individual’s dreams.

Dream Analysis

This involves a detailed examination of the dream’s content. The analyst and the individual work together to explore the dream’s manifest content (the actual events of the dream) and try to understand what these might symbolize in terms of the dreamer’s unconscious desires or conflicts (the latent content).

Symbol Interpretation

In Freud’s later work on dreams, he explored the possibility of universal symbols in dreams . Some of these were sexual, including poles, guns, and swords representing the penis and horse riding and dancing representing sexual intercourse.

For example, Freud suggested that dreams of flying might represent sexual desire, while dreams of losing teeth might represent anxiety about aging.

However, he also emphasized that the meaning of symbols can vary greatly between individuals, and that the individual’s associations are the most important factor in interpretation.

However, Freud was cautious about symbols and stated that general symbols are more personal rather than universal. A person cannot interpret what the manifest content of a dream symbolizes without knowing about the person’s circumstances.

“Dream dictionaries”, which are still popular now, were a source of irritation to Freud. In an amusing example of the limitations of universal symbols, one of Freud’s patients, after dreaming about holding a wriggling fish, said to him “that’s a Freudian symbol – it must be a penis!”

Freud explored further, and it turned out that the woman’s mother, who was a passionate astrologer and a Pisces, was on the patient’s mind because she disapproved of her daughter being in analysis. It seems more plausible, as Freud suggested, that the fish represented the patient’s mother rather than a penis!

Consideration of Repression

Freud believed that repressed desires and conflicts often emerge in dreams, so understanding what the individual might be repressing can help to interpret the dream’s latent content.

Freud, S., & Strachey, J. (1900).  The interpretation of dreams  (Vol. 4, p. 5). Allen & Unwin.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Therapy Center
  • When To See a Therapist
  • Types of Therapy
  • Best Online Therapy
  • Best Couples Therapy
  • Best Family Therapy
  • Managing Stress
  • Sleep and Dreaming
  • Understanding Emotions
  • Self-Improvement
  • Healthy Relationships
  • Student Resources
  • Personality Types
  • Sweepstakes
  • Guided Meditations
  • Verywell Mind Insights
  • 2024 Verywell Mind 25
  • Mental Health in the Classroom
  • Editorial Process
  • Meet Our Review Board
  • Crisis Support

Why Do We Dream?

There's no single consensus about which dream theory best explains why we dream

Verywell / Madelyn Goodnight

What Is a Dream Theory?

  • The Role of Dreams
  • Reflect the Unconscious
  • Process Information
  • Aid In Memory
  • Spur Creativity
  • Reflect Your Life
  • Prepare and Protect
  • Process Emotions
  • Other Theories

Lucid Dreaming

Stress dreams.

A dream theory is a proposed explanation for why people dream that is backed by scientific evidence. Despite scientific inquiry, we still don't have a solid answer for why people dream. Some of the most notable theories are that dreaming helps us process memories and better understand our emotions , also providing a way to express what we want or to practice facing our challenges.

At a Glance

There is no single dream theory that fully explains all of the aspects of why we dream. The most prominent theory is that dreams help us to process and consolidate information from the previous day. However, other theories have suggested that dreams are critical for emotional processing, creativity, and self-knowledge.

Some theories suggest that dreams also have symbolic meanings that offer a glimpse into the unconscious mind. Keep reading to learn more about some of the best-known theories about why we dream.

7 Theories on Why We Dream

A dream theory focuses on understanding the nature and purpose of dreams. Studying dreams can be challenging since they can vary greatly in how they are remembered and what they are about.

Dreams include the images, thoughts, and emotions that are experienced during sleep. They can range from extraordinarily intense or emotional to very vague, fleeting, confusing, or even boring.

Some dreams are joyful, while others are frightening or sad. Sometimes dreams seem to have a clear narrative, while many others appear to make no sense at all.

There are many unknowns about dreaming and sleep, but what scientists do know is that just about everyone dreams every time they sleep, for a total of around two hours per night, whether they remember it upon waking or not .

Beyond what's in a particular dream, there is the question of why we dream at all. Below, we detail the most prominent theories on the purpose of dreaming and how these explanations can be applied to specific dreams.

How Do Scientists Study Dreams?

The question of why we dream has fascinated philosophers and scientists for thousands of years. Traditionally, dream content is measured by the subjective recollections of the dreamer upon waking. However, observation is also accomplished through objective evaluation in a lab.

In one study, researchers even created a rudimentary dream content map that was able to track what people dreamed about in real time using magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) patterns. The map was then backed up by the dreamers' reports upon waking.

What Dream Theory Suggests About the Role of Dreams

Some of the more prominent dream theories suggest that the reason we dream is to:

  • Consolidate memories
  • Process emotions
  • Express our deepest desires
  • Gain practice confronting potential dangers

Many experts believe that we dream due to a combination of these reasons rather than any one particular theory. Additionally, while many researchers believe that dreaming is essential to mental, emotional, and physical well-being, some scientists suggest that dreams serve no real purpose at all.

The bottom line is that while many theories have been proposed, no single consensus has emerged about which dream theory best explains why we dream.

Dreaming during different phases of sleep may also serve unique purposes. The most vivid dreams happen during rapid eye movement (REM) sleep , and these are the dreams that we're most likely to recall. We also dream during non-rapid eye movement (non-REM) sleep, but those dreams are known to be remembered less often and have more mundane content.

Sigmund Freud's Dream Theory

Sigmund Freud’s theory of dreams suggests that dreams represent  unconscious desires, thoughts, wish fulfillment, and motivations. According to Freud, people are driven by repressed and unconscious longings, such as aggressive and sexual instincts .

While many of Freud's assertions have been debunked, research suggests there is a dream rebound effect, also known as dream rebound theory, in which suppression of a thought tends to result in dreaming about it.

What Causes Dreams to Happen?

In " The Interpretation of Dreams ," Freud wrote that dreams are "disguised fulfillments of repressed wishes." He also described two different components of dreams: manifest content (actual images) and latent content (hidden meaning).

Freud’s theory contributed to the rise and popularity of dream interpretation . While research has failed to demonstrate that the manifest content disguises the psychological significance of a dream, some experts believe that dreams play an important role in processing emotions and stressful experiences.

Activation-Synthesis Dream Theory

According to the activation-synthesis model of dreaming , which was first proposed by J. Allan Hobson and Robert McCarley, circuits in the brain become activated during REM sleep, which triggers the amygdala and hippocampus to create an array of electrical impulses. This results in a compilation of random thoughts, images, and memories that appear while dreaming.

When we wake, our active minds pull together the dream's various images and memory fragments to create a cohesive narrative.  

In the activation-synthesis hypothesis, dreams are a compilation of randomness that appear to the sleeping mind and are brought together in a meaningful way when we wake. In this sense, dreams may provoke the dreamer to make new connections, inspire useful ideas, or have creative epiphanies in their waking lives.

Self-Organization Dream Theory

According to the information-processing theory, sleep allows us to consolidate and process all of the information and memories that we have collected during the previous day. Some dream experts suggest that dreaming is a byproduct, or even an active part, of this experience processing.  

This model, known as the self-organization theory of dreaming , explains that dreaming is a side effect of brain neural activity as memories are consolidated during sleep.

During this process of unconscious information redistribution, it is suggested that memories are either strengthened or weakened. According to the self-organization theory of dreaming, while we dream, helpful memories are made stronger, while less useful ones fade away.

Research supports this theory, finding improvement in complex tasks when a person dreams about doing them. Studies also show that during REM sleep, low-frequency theta waves were more active in the frontal lobe, just like they are when people are learning, storing, and remembering information when awake.

Creativity and Problem-Solving Dream Theory

Another theory about dreams says that their purpose is to help us solve problems. In this creativity theory of dreaming, the unconstrained, unconscious mind is free to wander its limitless potential while unburdened by the often stifling realities of the conscious world. In fact, research has shown dreaming to be an effective promoter of creative thinking.

Scientific research and anecdotal evidence back up the fact that many people do successfully mine their dreams for inspiration and credit their dreams for their big "aha" moments.

The ability to make unexpected connections between memories and ideas that appear in your dreams often proves to be an especially fertile ground for creativity.

Continuity Hypothesis Dream Theory

Under the continuity hypothesis, dreams function as a reflection of a person's real life, incorporating conscious experiences into their dreams. Rather than a straightforward replay of waking life, dreams show up as a patchwork of memory fragments.

Still, studies show that non-REM sleep may be more involved with declarative memory (the more routine stuff), while REM dreams include more emotional and instructive memories.

In general, REM dreams tend to be easier to recall compared to non-REM dreams.

Under the continuity hypothesis, memories may be fragmented purposefully in our dreams as part of incorporating new learning and experiences into long-term memory . Still, there are many unanswered questions as to why some aspects of memories are featured more or less prominently in our dreams.

Rehearsal and Adaptation Dream Theory

The primitive instinct rehearsal and adaptive strategy theories of dreaming propose that we dream to better prepare ourselves to confront dangers in the real world. The dream as a social simulation function or threat simulation provides the dreamer a safe environment to practice important survival skills.

While dreaming, we hone our fight-or-flight instincts and build mental capability for handling threatening scenarios. Under the threat simulation theory, our sleeping brains focus on the fight-or-flight mechanism to prep us for life-threatening and/or emotionally intense scenarios including:

  • Running away from a pursuer
  • Falling over a cliff
  • Showing up somewhere naked
  • Going to the bathroom in public
  • Forgetting to study for a final exam

This theory suggests that practicing or rehearsing these skills in our dreams gives us an evolutionary advantage in that we can better cope with or avoid threatening scenarios in the real world. This helps explain why so many dreams contain scary, dramatic, or intense content.

Emotional Regulation Dream Theory

The emotional regulation dream theory says that the function of dreams is to help us process and cope with our emotions or trauma in the safe space of slumber.

Research shows that the amygdala , which is involved in processing emotions, and the hippocampus , which plays a vital role in condensing information and moving it from short-term to long-term memory storage, are active during vivid, intense dreaming.

This illustrates a strong link between dreaming, memory storage, and emotional processing.

This theory suggests that REM sleep plays a vital role in emotional brain regulation. It also helps explain why so many dreams are emotionally vivid and why emotional or traumatic experiences tend to show up on repeat. Research has shown a connection between the ability to process emotions and the amount of REM sleep a person gets.

Sharing Dreams Promotes Connection

Talking about content similarities and common dreams with others may help promote belongingness and connection. Research notes heightened empathy among people who share their dreams with others, pointing to another way dreams can help us cope by promoting community and interpersonal support.

Other Theories About Why We Dream

Many other theories have been suggested to account for why we dream.

  • One dream theory contends that dreams are the result of our brains trying to interpret external stimuli (such as a dog's bark, music, or a baby's cry) during sleep.
  • Another theory uses a computer metaphor to account for dreams, noting that dreams serve to "clean up" clutter from the mind, refreshing the brain for the next day.
  • The reverse-learning theory suggests that we dream to forget. Our brains have thousands of neural connections between memories—too many to remember them all—and that dreaming is part of "pruning" those connections.
  • In the continual-activation theory, we dream to keep the brain active while we sleep, in order to keep it functioning properly.

Overfitted Dream Hypothesis

One recently introduced dream theory, known as the overfitted dream hypothesis, suggests that dreams are the brain's way of introducing random, disruptive data to help break up repetitive daily tasks and information. Researcher Erik Hoel suggests that such disruptions helps to keep the brain fit.

Lucid dreams are relatively rare dreams where the dreamer has awareness of being in their dream and often has some control over the dream content. Research indicates that around 50% of people recall having had at least one lucid dream in their lifetime and just over 10% report having them two or more times per month.

It is unknown why certain people experience lucid dreams more frequently than others. While experts are unclear as to why or how lucid dreaming occurs, preliminary research signals that the prefrontal and parietal regions of the brain play a significant role.

How to Lucid Dream

Many people covet lucid dreaming and seek to experience it more often. Lucid dreaming has been compared to virtual reality and hyper-realistic video games, giving lucid dreamers the ultimate self-directed dreamscape experience.

Potential training methods for inducing lucid dreaming include cognitive training, external stimulation during sleep, and medications. While these methods may show some promise, none have been rigorously tested or shown to be effective.

A strong link has been found between lucid dreaming and highly imaginative thinking and creative output. Research has shown that lucid dreamers perform better on creative tasks than those who do not experience lucid dreaming.

Stressful experiences tend to show up with great frequency in our dreams. Stress dreams may be described as sad, scary, and nightmarish .

Experts do not fully understand how or why specific stressful content ends up in our dreams, but many point to a variety of theories, including the continuity hypothesis, adaptive strategy, and emotional regulation dream theories to explain these occurrences. Stress dreams and mental health seem to go hand-in-hand.

  • Daily stress shows up in dreams : Research has shown that those who experience greater levels of worry in their waking lives and people diagnosed with post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) report higher frequency and intensity of nightmares.
  • Mental health disorders may contribute to stress dreams : Those with mental health disorders such as anxiety, bipolar disorder , and depression tend to have more distressing dreams, as well as more difficulty sleeping in general.
  • Anxiety is linked to stress dreams : Research indicates a strong connection between anxiety and stressful dream content. These dreams may be the brain's attempt to help us cope with and make sense of these stressful experiences.

While many theories exist about why we dream, more research is needed to fully understand their purpose. Rather than assuming only one dream theory is correct, dreams likely serve various purposes. In reality, many of these dream theories may be useful for explaining different aspects of the dreaming process.

If you are concerned about your dreams and/or are having frequent nightmares , consider speaking to your doctor or consulting a sleep specialist.

National Institute of Neurological Disorders and Stroke. Brain basics: Understanding sleep .

Horikawa T, Tamaki M, Miyawaki Y, Kamitani Y. Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep . Science . 2013;340(6132):639-42. doi:10.1126/science.1234330

De Gennaro L, Cipolli C, Cherubini A, et al. Amygdala and hippocampus volumetry and diffusivity in relation to dreaming . Hum Brain Mapp . 2011;32(9):1458-70. doi:10.1002/hbm.21120

Zhang W, Guo B. Freud's dream interpretation: A different perspective based on the self-organization theory of dreaming . Front Psychol . 2018;9:1553. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2018.01553

Malinowski J, Carr M, Edwards C, Ingarfill A, Pinto A. The effects of dream rebound: evidence for emotion-processing theories of dreaming .  J Sleep Res . 2019;28(5):e12827. doi:10.1111/jsr.12827

Boag S. On dreams and motivation: Comparison of Freud's and Hobson's views .  Front Psychol . 2017;7:2001. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.02001

Eichenlaub JB, Van Rijn E, Gaskell MG, et al. Incorporation of recent waking-life experiences in dreams correlates with frontal theta activity in REM sleep . Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci . 2018;13(6):637-647. doi:10.1093/scan/nsy041

Zhang W. A supplement to self-organization theory of dreaming .  Front Psychol . 2016;7. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00332

Luongo A, Lukowski A, Protho T, Van Vorce H, Pisani L, Edgin J. Sleep's role in memory consolidation: What can we learn from atypical development ?  Adv Child Dev Behav . 2021;60:229-260. doi:10.1016/bs.acdb.2020.08.001

Scarpelli S, D'Atri A, Gorgoni M, Ferrara M, De Gennaro L. EEG oscillations during sleep and dream recall: state- or trait-like individual differences ?  Front Psychol . 2015;6:605. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00605

Llewellyn S, Desseilles M. Editorial: Do both psychopathology and creativity result from a labile wake-sleep-dream cycle? . Front Psychol . 2017;8:1824. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01824

Revonsuo A. The reinterpretation of dreams: An evolutionary hypothesis of the function of dreaming .  Behav Brain Sci . 2000;23(6):877-901. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00004015

Ruby PM. Experimental research on dreaming: State of the art and neuropsychoanalytic perspectives . Front Psychol . 2011;2:286. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00286

Gujar N, McDonald SA, Nishida M, Walker MP. A role for REM sleep in recalibrating the sensitivity of the human brain to specific emotions . Cereb Cortex . 2011;21(1):115-23. doi:10.1093/cercor/bhq064

Blagrove M, Hale S, Lockheart J, Carr M, Jones A, Valli K. Testing the empathy theory of dreaming: The relationships between dream sharing and trait and state empathy . Front Psychol . 2019;10:1351. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01351

Poe GR. Sleep is for forgetting .  J Neurosci . 2017;37(3):464-473. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0820-16.2017

Zhang J. Continual-activation theory of dreaming .  Dynamical Psychology .

Hoel E. The Overfitted Brain: Dreams evolved to assist generalization . Published online 2020.doi:10.48550/arXiv.2007.09560

Vallat R, Ruby PM. Is it a good idea to cultivate lucid dreaming? Front Psychol . 2019;10:2585. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02585

Baird B, Mota-Rolim SA, Dresler M. The cognitive neuroscience of lucid dreaming . Neurosci Biobehav Rev . 2019;100:305-323. doi:10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.03.008

Stumbrys T, Daunytė V. Visiting the land of dream muses: The relationship between lucid dreaming and creativity . 2018;11(2). doi:10.11588/ijodr.2018.2.48667

Rek S, Sheaves B, Freeman D. Nightmares in the general population: Identifying potential causal factors . Soc Psychiatry Psychiatr Epidemiol . 2017;52(9):1123-1133. doi:10.1007/s00127-017-1408-7

Sikka P, Pesonen H, Revonsuo A. Peace of mind and anxiety in the waking state are related to the affective content of dreams . Sci Rep . 2018;8(1):12762. doi:10.1038/s41598-018-30721-1

By Kendra Cherry, MSEd Kendra Cherry, MS, is a psychosocial rehabilitation specialist, psychology educator, and author of the "Everything Psychology Book."

  • Wish Fulfilment

Freud argues that our dreams are wish-fulfilments.

Freud argues that a dream is the fulfilment of a wish..

This starting point has been criticised as reductionist, but it is also the part of his theory that is closest to common-sense and popular ideas about dreams.

We all recognise that in our dreams we often make the world a better place for ourselves where our wishes are fulfilled.

This is even a part of our everyday speech: we use sayings like “I wouldn’t dream of it!” and “not in my wildest dreams!”

In this sense, dreams have much in common with stories or daydreams in which the hero wins out in the end and achieves his or her heart’s desire.

A wish involves a prohibition.

Wish Fulfilment Sigmund Freud Dreams Stop

So, to create a wish implies something like this:

1. I want an ice cream

3. I wish I had an ice cream

There is a ‘want’ and a prohibition. A wish is the result.

Children’s dreams display the wish-fulfilling character of dreams most clearly.

Here is Freud’s account of a dream his daughter Anna had when she was very small:

dream fulfillment essay

“Anna Freud, stwawbewwies, wild stwawbewwies, omblet, pudden!”

At that time she was in the habit of using her name to express the idea of taking possession of something. The menu must have seemed to her to make up a desirable meal.

Anna’s dream of strawberries shows the wishful character of dreams. She goes to bed hungry and dreams of food.

But not just any food! Why does she specifically dream of strawberries? In fact, she mentioned two different kinds of strawberries in the dream (in German, ‘strawberries’ and ‘wild strawberries’ are different words). Freud makes an interesting observation:

The fact that two kinds of strawberries appeared in it was a demonstration against the domestic health police: her nanny had attributed her sickness to an excess of strawberries. She was thus retaliating in her dream against this unwelcome verdict.

In other words, the wish lingers on the very thing that has been forbidden. Anna’s strict nanny blamed her sickness not on strawberries as such, but on the  excess of them, on eating  too many strawberries. In doing so, she introduces  rules of strawberry-eating.

Strawberries became subject to a kind of prohibition, and as a result became the forbidden fruit!

Discover more:

dream fulfillment essay

Previous chapter

  • Freud’s Method for Interpreting Dreams

Freud invited his patients to say whatever came to mind in relation to each element of the dream.

dream fulfillment essay

Next chapter

  • Dream Distortion

A censor is at work! Freud argues that dreams are disguised to get around censorship.

dream fulfillment essay

Help keep this valuable resource free

The Freud Museum London is a charity and receives no direct public funding.

Please donate and help keep our learning resources free for all.

From our shop

Get the book.

The Interpretation of Dreams is one of Freud’s most fascinating and accessible works.

Cover of book which details book title and a black and white photograph of Sigmund Freud - Interpretation of Dreams

In This Section

  • The Interpretation of Dreams
  • The Dream-Work
  • The Infantile Sources of Dreams

Related resource

The Wolf Man's Dream - Painting of five white wolves in a tree.

The Wolf Man’s Dream

Analyse one of the most famous dreams in the history of psychoanalysis.

Photograph of front door and garden at Freud Museum

Plan your visit to the Freud Museum: opening times, directions and admission fees.

Please support us

Sigmund and Anna Freud Donate

Make a Donation

Please donate and help us to preserve the legacy of Sigmund and Anna Freud. Every gift, large or small, will help us build a bright future.

Freud and Latin America - Grete Stern, Sueño Nro 35, 1949, The Estate of Grete Stern, Courtesy of Galeria Jorge Mara

What’s On

Online. On Demand. Events, courses and conferences. All available worldwide.

The Realgoalgetter

The Self Help Library

Creating Health And Wealth, Living Your Best Life.

Dream Fulfillment: Lessons From Inspiring Individuals

Table Of Contents

Imagine a world where dreams are not just wishful thinking, but tangible realities waiting to be seized. In this captivating article, you will explore the awe-inspiring journeys of remarkable individuals who have turned their dreams into vibrant and meaningful lives. Prepare to be inspired and motivated as you delve into the lessons learned from these extraordinary souls, each with their own unique stories of triumph, resilience, and unwavering determination. Get ready to embrace the power within you to fulfill your wildest dreams and embark on a life-changing adventure of self-discovery.

The Power of Dreaming Big

Overcoming self-limiting beliefs.

When it comes to achieving our dreams, one of the biggest hurdles we face is our own self-limiting beliefs. These beliefs are the negative thoughts and doubts that hold us back from pursuing our goals. However, it is important to recognize that these beliefs are often unfounded and do not reflect our true potential. By challenging and overcoming these self-limiting beliefs, we open ourselves up to a world of possibilities and pave the way for success.

Embracing Ambition

Ambition is what fuels our dreams and propels us forward. It is the driving force that pushes us to pursue our goals relentlessly. When we embrace ambition, we give ourselves permission to dream big and aim for the stars. It is through ambition that we tap into our full potential and discover what we are truly capable of achieving. So, don’t be afraid to dream big and let your ambition guide you towards turning those dreams into reality.

Setting Audacious Goals

Setting audacious goals is a vital part of achieving our dreams. When we set goals that are challenging and stretch us beyond our comfort zones, we invite growth and transformation into our lives. These goals ignite a fire within us and serve as a constant reminder of what we are working towards. By setting audacious goals, we not only push ourselves to perform at our best but also unleash our untapped potential and unlock doors that we never knew existed.

The Role of Perseverance and Hard Work

Staying committed to the dream.

Perseverance is the key to overcoming obstacles and staying committed to our dreams. It is the unwavering determination and resilience that allows us to weather any storm that comes our way. When faced with challenges, it is important to remember why we started and stay focused on our end goal. By maintaining our commitment to our dreams, we set ourselves up for long-term success and fulfillment.

Embracing Failure as a Stepping Stone

Failure is not the end of the road, but rather a stepping stone towards success. It is through failure that we learn valuable lessons and gain the knowledge and experience necessary for growth. By embracing failure as a natural part of the journey, we can view setbacks as opportunities for growth and improvement. Don’t let failure discourage you; instead, let it inspire you to try again, but with a newfound wisdom and determination.

Cultivating a Strong Work Ethic

Hard work is a fundamental ingredient in the recipe for success. Without a strong work ethic, dreams remain just that – dreams. It is through consistent effort, dedication, and discipline that we turn our dreams into reality. By cultivating a strong work ethic, we develop a habit of putting in the necessary time and effort required to achieve our goals. Remember, success is not handed to you on a silver platter; it is earned through hard work and perseverance.

Overcoming Challenges and Adversity

Developing resilience.

Resilience is the ability to bounce back and recover from setbacks and challenges. It is the inner strength that allows us to face adversity head-on and emerge stronger than before. Developing resilience is crucial in the pursuit of our dreams because challenges and obstacles are inevitable. By building resilience, we cultivate the mindset and attitude needed to overcome any adversity that comes our way.

Navigating Obstacles

Obstacles are a natural part of any journey towards success. They test our determination and commitment to our dreams. When faced with obstacles, it is important to approach them with a problem-solving mindset and view them as opportunities for growth. By navigating obstacles, we develop the skills and resilience needed to overcome future challenges, bringing us one step closer to achieving our dreams.

Finding Solutions

Instead of dwelling on problems, successful individuals focus on finding solutions. They understand that there is always a way to overcome any challenge. By adopting a proactive mindset and seeking out solutions, we empower ourselves to take control of our circumstances. Whether it’s through seeking advice, brainstorming ideas, or learning new skills, finding solutions allows us to overcome obstacles and continue progressing towards our dreams.

Building a Supportive Network

Surrounding oneself with like-minded individuals.

The people we surround ourselves with play a significant role in our personal and professional development. When pursuing our dreams, it is crucial to surround ourselves with like-minded individuals who share our ambition and vision. These individuals provide support, motivation, and valuable feedback, making the journey towards our dreams more enjoyable and fulfilling. By building a supportive network, we create a community of individuals who lift each other up and celebrate each other’s successes.

Seeking Mentors and Role Models

Mentors and role models are invaluable assets on the path to success. They offer guidance, wisdom, and insights gained from their own experiences. Seeking out mentors and role models allows us to learn from their successes and failures, providing us with guidance and inspiration. These individuals can offer valuable advice, help us navigate challenges, and provide accountability, ultimately propelling us closer to our dreams.

Collaborating and Networking

Collaboration and networking are powerful tools that can open doors to new opportunities and possibilities. By collaborating with others in our field or industry, we tap into a collective pool of knowledge and skills, enhancing our own capabilities. Networking allows us to expand our professional connections, gain new insights, and discover potential partnerships. By building a collaborative and supportive network, we harness the power of collective effort and increase our chances of success.

Embracing Creativity and Innovation

Thinking outside the box.

Creativity is the key to unlocking innovative solutions and approaching challenges from a fresh perspective. It encourages us to think outside the box and consider alternative possibilities. By embracing creativity, we invite innovation into our lives and foster an environment that allows for groundbreaking ideas. Remember, some of the most successful individuals are those who dared to think differently and challenge the status quo.

Embracing Change and Adapting

Change is inevitable, and those who can adapt are more likely to succeed. Embracing change allows us to stay ahead of the curve and seize new opportunities as they arise. By remaining open-minded and adaptable, we can navigate through shifting landscapes and adjust our strategies accordingly. Embracing change is not only necessary for success but also a catalyst for personal and professional growth.

Putting Ideas into Action

An idea is just a dream until we take action. Successful individuals understand the importance of converting ideas into tangible actions. By taking the first step and putting our ideas into motion, we set the wheels in motion towards realizing our dreams. It is through consistent action that dreams are transformed into tangible outcomes. So, don’t just dream – take action and turn those dreams into reality.

Wellness and Personal Development

The importance of self-care.

Taking care of our physical, mental, and emotional well-being is crucial on the journey towards dream fulfillment. Self-care allows us to recharge, stay focused, and operate at our best. It involves prioritizing activities that promote our overall well-being, such as exercise, adequate sleep, healthy eating, and engaging in activities that bring us joy. By prioritizing self-care, we establish a strong foundation for success and ensure that we are equipped to handle the challenges that may come our way.

Continuous Learning and Growth

The pursuit of our dreams involves continuous learning and personal growth. Successful individuals understand the importance of expanding their knowledge and skills to adapt to evolving circumstances. By seeking out learning opportunities, such as books, courses, workshops, or mentorships, we continually enhance our capabilities and stay on the cutting edge of our field. Committing to lifelong learning ensures that we are equipped with the tools and knowledge needed to achieve our dreams.

Managing Stress and Achieving Balance

The path towards dream fulfillment can be demanding and overwhelming at times. It is important to prioritize stress management and strive for a healthy work-life balance. By implementing strategies such as meditation, exercise, and time management techniques, we can effectively manage stress and prevent burnout. Achieving balance allows us to maintain our overall well-being and sustain the energy and motivation needed to pursue our dreams.

Overcoming Fear and Taking Calculated Risks

Embracing uncertainty.

Fear of the unknown can hold us back from pursuing our dreams. However, successful individuals understand that growth and success lie outside of our comfort zones. By embracing uncertainty, we open ourselves up to new opportunities and possibilities. Embracing uncertainty allows us to break free from the limitations of fear and take bold steps towards our dreams.

Stepping Outside of Comfort Zones

Progress is not achieved by staying within the confines of our comfort zones. To achieve our dreams, we must be willing to step outside of our comfort zones and embrace new challenges. It is through these experiences that we expand our horizons, develop new skills, and grow as individuals. Stepping outside of comfort zones is a necessary step towards unlocking our full potential and achieving our wildest dreams.

Learning from Failures

Failure is not a reflection of our abilities but rather an opportunity for growth. Successful individuals embrace failure as a learning experience and use it as a stepping stone towards success. By analyzing our failures, identifying the lessons learned, and applying those lessons to future endeavors, we turn failure into a catalyst for improvement. Remember, each failure brings us one step closer to success if we approach it with the right mindset and determination.

Finding Passion and Purpose

Discovering personal interests and passions.

Passion and purpose are the driving forces behind our dreams. To discover our true passions, we need to explore different areas and activities, pushing ourselves to try new things. By paying attention to what ignites excitement and enthusiasm within us, we can uncover our deepest interests and align our dreams with our passions.

Aligning Dreams with Values

When our dreams align with our core values, we experience a deep sense of fulfillment and purpose. Our values represent our fundamental beliefs and what is truly important to us. By aligning our dreams with these values, we ensure that our pursuits are meaningful and impactful. When our dreams and values are in harmony, we are motivated to overcome challenges and achieve success that is true to who we are.

Making a Difference

Dream fulfillment goes beyond personal success; it is also about making a difference in the lives of others and leaving a positive impact on the world. Successful individuals understand the importance of using their talents, resources, and influence to contribute to the greater good. By making a difference, whether through charitable endeavors, environmental initiatives, or advocacy work, we create a legacy that extends far beyond our own accomplishments.

The Importance of Visualization and Affirmation

Creating a clear vision.

Visualization is a powerful tool that allows us to clearly see the future we aspire to create. By creating a clear vision of our dreams, we give ourselves a roadmap towards success. Visualization involves imagining ourselves already living our dreams, feeling the emotions associated with that success, and visualizing every detail of what that success looks like. Through visualization, we cultivate a strong belief in our ability to achieve our dreams and attract the necessary resources and opportunities.

Practicing Daily Affirmations

Affirmations are positive statements that help rewire our subconscious mind and reinforce empowering beliefs. By practicing daily affirmations, we shift our mindset from self-doubt to self-confidence. Affirmations help us eliminate self-limiting beliefs and replace them with empowering thoughts and beliefs that support our dreams. Incorporating affirmations into our daily routine helps establish a positive and empowering mindset, setting us up for success.

Manifesting Dreams into Reality

The combination of visualization and affirmation is a powerful manifestation technique. By consistently visualizing our dreams and affirming our ability to achieve them, we align our thoughts, emotions, and actions with our goals. This alignment sends a powerful message to the universe and attracts the necessary people, resources, and opportunities to manifest our dreams into reality. Manifestation is the result of our focused intention and belief in our ability to achieve our dreams.

Giving Back and Paying It Forward

Empowering others.

One of the greatest acts of success is empowering and supporting others on their own journey towards their dreams. Successful individuals understand the importance of lifting others up and offering a helping hand. By sharing our knowledge, resources, and experiences, we contribute to the success and growth of those around us. Empowering others not only makes a positive impact on their lives but also creates a ripple effect that extends far beyond what we can imagine.

Philanthropy and Social Responsibility

Successful individuals recognize their social responsibility and actively give back to their communities and causes they believe in. Philanthropy involves charitable giving and using one’s resources to make a positive impact on society. By supporting causes close to our hearts, we can create meaningful change and leave a lasting legacy that goes beyond personal success.

Sharing Knowledge and Experiences

Sharing knowledge and experiences is a way to inspire and empower others. We all have unique insights and lessons learned from our own journeys. By sharing these experiences, we provide guidance and support to those who may be on a similar path. Sharing knowledge fosters a sense of community and collaboration, and it allows us to leave a lasting impact on the world by helping others realize their own dreams.

Dream Fulfillment: Lessons from Inspiring Individuals

In the pursuit of our dreams, there are valuable lessons we can learn from inspiring individuals who have successfully achieved their own dreams. From overcoming self-limiting beliefs and embracing ambition to building a supportive network and embracing creativity, the journey towards dream fulfillment is paved with key principles and actions.

By overcoming self-limiting beliefs and embracing ambition, we give ourselves permission to dream big and aim for the stars. Setting audacious goals propels us towards growth and unlocks our untapped potential. However, success requires perseverance and hard work. Staying committed to our dreams, embracing failure as a stepping stone, and cultivating a strong work ethic are crucial components of the process.

Challenges and adversity are inevitable on the path to success. Developing resilience, navigating obstacles, and finding solutions are essential skills to overcome the hurdles we encounter. Building a supportive network by surrounding ourselves with like-minded individuals, seeking mentors and role models, and collaborating and networking allows us to tap into collective knowledge and support.

Embracing creativity and innovation, thinking outside the box, embracing change and adaptation, and putting ideas into action fuel progress and bring our dreams to life. However, maintaining wellness and personal development is equally important. Prioritizing self-care, continuous learning and growth, and managing stress and achieving balance ensure we have the physical and mental fortitude to persevere.

Overcoming fear and taking calculated risks are inevitable steps towards dream fulfillment. Embracing uncertainty, stepping outside of comfort zones, and learning from failures are essential in propelling us towards success. It is also crucial to align our dreams with our passions and values, allowing us to derive deep fulfillment. By creating a clear vision, practicing daily affirmations, and manifesting our dreams into reality, we set ourselves up for success.

Lastly, giving back and paying it forward is the ultimate act of success. Empowering others, practicing philanthropy and social responsibility, and sharing knowledge and experiences create a positive impact that extends beyond our individual accomplishments.

In conclusion, the power of dreaming big lies within each of us, and the path to dream fulfillment requires perseverance, hard work, resilience, support, creativity, wellness, fearlessness, passion, visualization, and giving back. By embracing these principles and actions, we can unlock our fullest potential and turn our dreams into reality. So, go forth, dream big, and embrace the journey towards your wildest dreams.

Related posts:

  • The Role Of Self-Belief In Dream Fulfillment
  • Vision Plus Goal Setting — Dream Your Life Now, Impossible Is Just A Word
  • Finding Purpose In Adversity: Lessons From Challenges
  • Visualizing Your Dream Life: Vision Boarding
  • Mentorship And Guidance On Your Dream Journey

dream fulfillment essay

  • Pricing Plans
  • Page Feedback
  • Articles & Blog

. Unraveling Freud's Interpretation of Dreams & Wish Fulfillment

A deep dive into freud’s wish fulfillment theory in interpretation of dreams.

Embark on an enlightening journey into Freud's revolutionary Interpretation of Dreams.

dream fulfillment essay

Key Insights

  • Sigmund Freud's “wish fulfillment” theory suggests that our dreams are not random but expressions of our deepest, often suppressed desires.
  • Freud's innovative approach to dream analysis involves understanding two types of content in dreams - the manifest (what we remember upon waking) and the latent (the hidden, symbolic meaning).
  • According to Freud, our dreams are shaped by our unconscious desires, which often find escape in our dreams when suppressed in our conscious state.

Ever woken up from a dream that felt so real you could still taste the fear or excitement? Or perhaps a dream so bizarre it left you scratching your head in confusion? Dreaming is a universal human experience, one that has intrigued us for centuries. Dreams have been seen as divine messages, prophetic visions, and even gateways to alternate realities.

Yet, it was the groundbreaking work of Sigmund Freud , a pioneer in the field of psychoanalysis, that revolutionized our understanding of dreams. In his seminal book, called the Interpretation of Dreams, Freud proposed a fascinating theory.

Freud suggested that our dreams are not merely random, fleeting images playing out in our sleep. Instead, they are profound expressions of our deepest desires and wishes, often ones we suppress or deny. This theory, known as “wish fulfillment” has significantly shaped our comprehension of dreams. So, let's dive deep into this captivating concept.

Sigmund Freud and His Revolutionary Dream Theory

When we think of psychoanalysis, one name invariably comes to mind - Sigmund Freud. His theories have profoundly influenced psychology, and among them, his Wish Fulfillment Theory stands out as particularly intriguing.

Freud believed that our dreams are the playground of our unconscious mind. It's where our suppressed desires, those we might find unacceptable or uncomfortable, come out to play. In other words, our dreams fulfill the wishes that we can't or won't satisfy in our waking life.

For instance, if you've been dieting and denying yourself your favorite chocolate cake, you might find yourself dreaming about indulging in a decadent piece of that cake. According to Freud, this dream is fulfilling your repressed desire to enjoy the cake without any guilt or consequences.

Freud's Logic Behind the Wish Fulfillment Theory

Freud's approach to analyzing dreams was innovative and insightful. He proposed that each dream has two types of content — manifest and latent content.

The manifest content is the part of the dream that we remember upon waking. It's the storyline, the characters, the images. Think of it as the surface of an ocean, visible and tangible. However, it's beneath this surface, in the depths of the ocean, where the true meaning of the dream lies. This hidden, underlying meaning is the latent content.

To illustrate, let's say you dream about missing a train. The manifest content is the act of missing the train. But what does that symbolize? According to Freud, it could represent a fear of missing out or failing to achieve a goal, which would be the latent content.

A simpler way to explain this concept is to think of a dream as a metaphor. The manifest content of the dream serves as the vehicle for conveying its true meaning, which is contained in the latent content.

Unraveling Hidden Desires through Freudian Dream Analysis

Freud was convinced that our unconscious desires play a pivotal role in shaping our dreams. These desires, often suppressed due to societal norms or personal fears, find an outlet in our dreams. That's why dreams can sometimes feel strange or illogical - they're a reflection of our raw, unfiltered desires.

For example, a dream of drinking alcohol in an office might actually be expressing the desire to let loose and relax in a professional setting. In this case, the act of drinking alcohol is symbolic - it's not about consuming booze but finding liberation from the pressures of a job.

To reveal these hidden meanings, Freud developed several techniques like free association, where patients express their thoughts without censorship. He believed that this method could help uncover the latent content of dreams and provide valuable insights into our unconscious desires. More about that in the next section.

Decoding Dreams with Freud's Dream Interpretation Techniques

Indeed, Freud devised several techniques to uncover concealed desires hidden in dreams. One such technique is free association, where you speak freely about your thoughts and feelings associated with different elements of your dream.

Imagine you dreamt about a red rose. Freud would encourage you to express all the thoughts and emotions that the red rose evokes in you. This process, he believed, could reveal the latent content of your dream, bringing your unconscious desires into the light.

For instance, a red rose could evoke feelings of love or passion. This could be indicative of a desire to experience the thrill and excitement of romantic love in your waking life instead of the boredom and familiarity that might have become commonplace.

Freud's theories laid the groundwork for the psychoanalysis of dreams. He proposed that by dissecting our dreams, we can delve into our subconscious mind and understand our deepest desires and fears. This approach has become a valuable tool in psychotherapy, helping individuals unravel their inner conflicts.

Harnessing the Power of AI in Dream Analysis

In the realm of dream interpretation, technology has started to play an increasingly significant role. One such innovation is SeventhSIGHT. Leveraging patented machine learning artificial intelligence, it takes the psychoanalysis of dreams to a whole new level.

For one thing, SeventhSIGHT explores the meaning of your dreams by analyzing the various elements and themes present. By doing so, it helps you gain powerful insights into your daily life. It works on the premise that understanding what your subconscious is trying to communicate can have profound effects on your waking life.

Imagine having a dream where you're soaring high in the sky. You wake up, intrigued and curious about what this dream could mean. Is it a manifestation of your desire for freedom? Or does it reflect your aspirations to reach new heights in your career? With SeventhSIGHT, you can delve into these questions and more. Its advanced AI algorithms can analyze the dream's content and provide you with a comprehensive interpretation.

dream fulfillment essay

It's interesting to note how this modern tool aligns with Freud's theories. Just as Freud believed in uncovering the latent content of dreams to understand our unconscious desires, SeventhSIGHT uses AI to decipher these hidden meanings, making the process faster and more accessible.

So, whether you're baffled by a bizarre dream or simply curious about the mysteries your subconscious mind is weaving each night, SeventhSIGHT can be a valuable tool. It combines the age-old fascination with dream interpretation with cutting-edge technology, helping you unlock the secrets your dreams hold.

Do dream interpretations hold any significance?

Yes, they do. Interpreting dreams can offer insights into your subconscious mind, emotional state, and life situations. However, the interpretations can vary greatly depending on individual context and perspective.

Is it beneficial to understand the interpretation of dreams?

Definitely. Gaining an understanding of your dreams can lead to a deeper comprehension of yourself, your emotions, and your experiences. It can also help resolve unresolved issues and bring clarity to various aspects of your life.

How can I determine what my dream means?

Start by noting down the details of your dream and the emotions associated with it. You can then refer to a dream dictionary or consult with a dream analyst. However, always remember to consider your personal context for an accurate interpretation.

Can dreams disclose truths?

Yes, dreams can reveal truths about our emotions, fears, desires, and more. They can bring to light issues that we might overlook or ignore when awake.

Do dreams convey a message?

Many believe that dreams do carry messages, either from our subconscious mind or from a higher spiritual plane. These messages can relate to our personal growth, life situations, or spiritual path.

Through the lens of both science and spirituality, interpreting dreams offers a profound journey into our subconscious minds. It can provide a clearer understanding of our inner selves and guide us along our life paths with greater clarity and purpose.

At SeventhSIGHT, we believe that dreams can be a powerful force for self-discovery and healing. We use cutting-edge Artificial Intelligence technology to help you gain meaningful insights into your dreams and ultimately, yourself. With SeventhSIGHT, you can unlock the secrets of your subconscious and explore possibilities far beyond the boundaries of the waking world.

Share this post

Popular articles.

dream fulfillment essay

Explore the fascinating world of dream analysis and the science behind it. Learn how this understanding can enhance creativity and emotional processing.

dream fulfillment essay

Explore common dream symbols and their meanings, demystifying the messages our subconscious sends us every night

dream fulfillment essay

Dive deep into the spiritual and religious aspects of dream interpretation. Learn how cultures around the globe interpret dreams through religious lenses.

Related articles

dream fulfillment essay

Dive deep into the world of dreams with our detailed guide on using a dream analyzer.

dream fulfillment essay

Dive deep into the fascinating world of Dream Symbolism as we explore Carl Jung's theory of archetypes.

dream fulfillment essay

Dive deep into the psychology of dreams, exploring the fascinating Activation-Synthesis Theory.

dream fulfillment essay

Powerful Dream Analysis Created to Translate your Subconscious to your Conscious Mind and Awaken Your Potential.

Quick Links

  • FAQs / Videos
  • Your Account

dream fulfillment essay

Dreams and Psychology

  • September 2020

Kanchan Pal at Indira Gandhi National Open University (IGNOU)

  • Indira Gandhi National Open University (IGNOU)

Discover the world's research

  • 25+ million members
  • 160+ million publication pages
  • 2.3+ billion citations
  • Richa Verma

Ayushi Sharma

  • Recruit researchers
  • Join for free
  • Login Email Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google Welcome back! Please log in. Email · Hint Tip: Most researchers use their institutional email address as their ResearchGate login Password Forgot password? Keep me logged in Log in or Continue with Google No account? Sign up

Become a Writer Today

Essays About Dreams In Life: 14 Examples And Topic Ideas

Dreams in life are necessary; if you are writing essays about dreams in life, you can read these essay examples and topic ideas to get started.

Everyone has a dream – a big one or even a small one. Even the most successful people had dreams before becoming who they are today. Having a dream is like having a purpose in life; you will start working hard to reach your dream and never lose interest in life.

Without hard work, you can never turn a dream into a reality; it will only remain a desire. Level up your essay writing skills by reading our essays about dreams in life examples and prompts and start writing an inspiring essay today!

Writing About Dreams: A Guide

Essays about dreams in life: example essays, 1. chase your dreams: the best advice i ever got by michelle colon-johnson, 2. my dream, my future by deborah massey, 3. the pursuit of dreams by christine nishiyama, 4. my dreams and ambitions by kathy benson, 5. turning big dreams into reality by shyam gokarn, 6. my hopes and dreams by celia robinson, 7. always pursue your dreams – no matter what happens by steve bloom, 8. why do we dream by james roland, 9. bad dreams by eli goldstone, 10. why your brain needs to dream by matthew walker, 11. dreams by hedy marks, 12. do dreams really mean anything by david b. feldman, 13. how to control your dreams by serena alagappan, 14. the sunday essay: my dreams on antidepressants by ashleigh young, essays about dreams in life essay topics, 1. what is a dream, 2. what are your dreams in life, 3. why are dreams important in life, 4. what are the reasons for a person to dream big, 5. what do you think about dreams in life vs. short-term sacrifice, 6. what is the purpose of dreaming, 7. why are dreams so strange and vivid, 8. why do dreams feel so real, 9. why are dreams so hard to remember, 10. do dreams mean anything, what is a dream short essay, how can i write my dream in life.

IMAGE PRODUCT  
Grammarly
ProWritingAid

Writing about dreams is an excellent topic for essays, brainstorming new topic ideas for fiction stories, or just as a creative outlet. We all have dreams, whether in our sleep, during the day, or even while walking on a sunny day. Some of the best ways to begin writing about a topic are by reading examples and using a helpful prompt to get started. Check out our guide to writing about dreams and begin mastering the art of writing today!

“Everyone has the ability to dream, but not everyone has the willingness to truly chase their dreams. When people aren’t living their dreams they often have limited belief systems. They believe that their current circumstances and/or surroundings are keeping them from achieving the things they want to do in life.”

In her essay, author Michelle Colon-Johnson encourages her readers to develop a mindset that will let them chase their dreams. So, you have to visualize your dream, manifest it, and start your journey towards it! Check out these essays about dreams and sleep .

“At the time when I have my job and something to make them feel so proud of me, I would like to give them the best life. I would like to make them feel comfortable and see sweet smiles on their faces. This is really the one I like to achieve in my life; mountains of words can’t explain how much I love and appreciate them.”

Author Deborah Massey’s essay talks about her dreams and everything she wanted to achieve and accomplish in her life. She also tells us that we must live our values, pursue our dreams, and follow our passions for the best future.

“Fast-forward 5+ years, and my first published book is coming out this May with Scholastic. And now, let me tell you the truth: I don’t feel any different. I’m extremely grateful for the opportunity, proud of the work I’ve done, and excited for the book’s release. But on a fundamental level, I feel the same.”

In her essay, author Christine Nishiyama shares what she felt when she first achieved one of her goals in life. She says that with this mindset, you will never feel the satisfaction of achieving your goal or the fulfillment of reaching your dream. Instead, she believes that what fulfills people is the pursuit of their dreams in life.

“My dream is to become a good plastic surgeon and day after day it has transformed into an ambition which I want to move towards. I do not want to be famous, but just good enough to have my own clinic and work for a very successful hospital. Many people think that becoming a doctor is difficult, and I know that takes many years of preparation, but anyone can achieve it if they have determination.”

Author Kathy Benson’s essay narrates her life – all the things and struggles she has been through in pursuing her dreams in life. Yet, no matter how hard the situation gets, she always convinces herself not to give up, hoping her dreams will come true one day. She believes that with determination and commitment, anyone can achieve their dreams and goals in life. 

“I have always been a big dreamer and involved in acting upon it. Though, many times I failed, I continued to dream big and act. As long as I recollect, I always had such wild visions and fantasies of thinking, planning, and acting to achieve great things in life. But, as anyone can observe, there are many people, who think and work in that aspect.”

In his essay, author Shyam Gokarn explains why having a big dream is very important in a person’s life. However, he believes that the problem with some people is that they never hold tight to their dreams, even if they can turn them into reality. As a result, they tend to easily give up on their dreams and even stop trying instead of persevering through the pain and anguish of another failure.

“When I was younger, I’ve always had a fairytale-like dream about my future. To marry my prince, have a Fairy Godmother, be a princess… But now, all of that has changed. I’ve realized how hard life is now; that life cannot be like a fairy tale. What you want can’t happen just like that.”

Celia Robinson’s essay talks about her dream since she was a child. Unfortunately, as we grow old, there’s no “Fairy Godmother” that would help us when things get tough. Everyone wants to succeed in the future, but we have to work hard to achieve our dreams and goals.

“Take writing for example. I’ve wanted to be a professional writer since I was a little boy, but I was too scared that I wouldn’t be any good at it. But several years ago I started pursuing this dream despite knowing how difficult it might be. I fully realize I may not make it, but I’m completely fine with that. At least I tried which is more than most people can say.”

In his essay, author Steve Bloom encourages his readers always to pursue their dreams no matter what happens. He asks, “Would you rather pursue them and fail or never try?”. He believes that it’s always better to try and fail than look back and wonder what might have been. Stop thinking that failure or success is the only end goal for pursuing your dreams. Instead, think of it as a long journey where all the experiences you get along the way are just as important as reaching the end goal.

“Dreams are hallucinations that occur during certain stages of sleep. They’re strongest during REM sleep, or the rapid eye movement stage, when you may be less likely to recall your dream. Much is known about the role of sleep in regulating our metabolism, blood pressure, brain function, and other aspects of health. But it’s been harder for researchers to explain the role of dreams. When you’re awake, your thoughts have a certain logic to them. When you sleep, your brain is still active, but your thoughts or dreams often make little or no sense.”

Author James Roland’s essay explains the purpose of having dreams and the factors that can influence our dreams. He also mentioned some of the reasons that cause nightmares. Debra Sullivan, a nurse educator, medically reviews his essay. Sullivan’s expertise includes cardiology, psoriasis/dermatology, pediatrics, and alternative medicine. For more, you can also see these articles about sleep .

“The first time I experienced sleep paralysis and recognised it for what it was I was a student. I had been taking MDMA and listening to Django Reinhardt. My memories of that time are mainly of taking drugs and listening to Django Reinhardt. When I woke up I was in my paralysed body. I was there, inside it. I was inside my leaden wrists, my ribcage, the thick dead roots of my hair, the bandages of skin. This time the hallucinations were auditory. I could hear someone being beaten outside my door. They were screaming for help. And I could do nothing but lie there, locked inside my body . . . whatever bit of me is not my body. That is the bit that exists, by itself, at night.”

In her essay, Author Eli Goldstone talks about her suffering from bad dreams ever since childhood. She also talks about what she feels every time she has sleep paralysis – a feeling of being conscious but unable to move.

“We often hear stories of people who’ve learned from their dreams or been inspired by them. Think of Paul McCartney’s story of how his hit song “Yesterday” came to him in a dream or of Mendeleev’s dream-inspired construction of the periodic table of elements. But, while many of us may feel that our dreams have special meaning or a useful purpose, science has been more skeptical of that claim. Instead of being harbingers of creativity or some kind of message from our unconscious, some scientists have considered dreaming to being an unintended consequence of sleep—a byproduct of evolution without benefit.”

Author Matthew Walker, a professor of psychology and neuroscience, shares some interesting facts about dreams in his essay. According to research, dreaming is more than just a byproduct of sleep; it also serves essential functions in our well-being. 

“Dreams are basically stories and images that our mind creates while we sleep. They can be vivid. They can make you feel happy, sad, or scared. And they may seem confusing or perfectly rational. Dreams can happen at any time during sleep. But you have your most vivid dreams during a phase called REM (rapid eye movement) sleep, when your brain is most active. Some experts say we dream at least four to six times a night.”

In his essay, Author Hedy Marks discusses everything we need to know about dreams in detail – from defining a dream to tips that may help us remember our dreams. Hedy Marks is an Assistant Managing Editor at WebMD , and Carol DerSarkissian, a board-certified emergency physician, medically reviews his essay.

“Regardless of whether dreams foretell the future, allow us to commune with the divine, or simply provide a better understanding of ourselves, the process of analyzing them has always been highly symbolic. To understand the meaning of dreams, we must interpret them as if they were written in a secret code. A quick search of an online dream dictionary will tell you that haunted houses symbolize “unfinished emotional business,” dimly lit lamps mean you’re “feeling overwhelmed by emotional issues,” a feast indicates “a lack of balance in your life,” and garages symbolize a feeling of “lacking direction or guidance in achieving your goals.” 

Author David B. Feldman, an author, speaker, and professor of counseling psychology, believes that dreams may not mean anything, but they tell us something about our emotions. In other words, if you’ve been suffering from a series of bad dreams, it could be worth checking in with yourself to see how you’ve been feeling and perhaps consider whether there’s anything you can do to improve your mood.

“Ever wish you could ice skate across a winter sky, catching crumbs of gingerbread, like flakes of snow, on your tongue? How about conquering a monster in a nightmare, bouncing between mountain peaks, walking through walls, or reading minds? Have you ever longed to hold the hand of someone you loved and lost? If you want to fulfill your fantasies, or even face your fears, you might want to try taking some control of your dreams (try being the operative). People practiced in lucid dreaming—the phenomenon of being aware that you are dreaming while you are asleep—claim that the experience allows adventure, self-discovery, and euphoric joy.”

In her essay, Author Serena Alagappan talks about lucid dreams – a type of dream where a person becomes conscious during a dream. She also talked about ways to control our dreams, such as keeping a journal, reciting mantras before bed, and believing we can. However, not everyone will be able to control their dreams because the levels of lucidity and control differ significantly between individuals.

“There was a period of six months when I tried to go off my medication – a slowly unfolding disaster – and I’d thought my dreams might settle down. Instead, they grew more deranged. Even now I think of the dream in which I was using a cigarette lighter to melt my own father, who had assumed the form of a large candle. I’ve since learned that, apart from more research being needed, this was probably a case of “REM rebound”. When you stop taking the medication, you’ll likely get a lot more REM sleep than you were getting before. In simple terms, your brain goes on a dreaming frenzy, amping up the detail.”

Author Ashleigh Young’s essay informs us how some medications, such as antidepressants, affect our dreams based on her own life experience. She said, “I’ve tried not to dwell too much on my dreams. Yes, they are vivid and sometimes truly gruesome, full of chaotic, unfathomable violence, but weird nights seemed a reasonable price to pay for the bearable days that SSRIs have helped me to have.” 

In simple terms, a dream is a cherished aspiration, ambition, or ideal; is it the same as your goal in life? In your essay, explore this topic and state your opinion about what the word “dream” means to you.

This is an excellent topic for your statement or “about me” essay. Where do you see yourself in the next ten years? Do you have a career plan? If you still haven’t thought about it, maybe it’s time to start thinking about your future.

Having dreams is very important in a person’s life; it motivates, inspires, and helps you achieve any goal that you have in mind. Without dreams, we would feel lost – having no purpose in life. Therefore, in your essay, you should be able to explain to your readers how important it is to have a dream or ambition in life. 

What are the reasons for a person to dream big?

Dreaming big sounds great; however, it’s easier said than done. First, you’ve got to have reasons to dream big, which will motivate you to achieve your goals in life. If you’re writing an essay about dreams in life, mention why most people dare to dream big and achieve more in life. Is it about freedom, money, praise from other people, satisfaction, or something else entirely?

For example, you could watch movies, play video games, relax every night, or give up all of them to learn a complex skill – what would you choose, and why? In your essay about dreams in life, answer the question and include other examples about this topic so your readers can relate.

There are many answers to this question – one is that dreams may have an evolutionary function, testing us in scenarios crucial to our survival. Dreams may also reduce the severity of emotional trauma. On the other hand, some researchers say dreams have no purpose or meaning, while some say we need dreams for physical and mental health. Take a closer look at this topic, and include what you find in your essay.

Weird dreams could result from anxiety, stress, or sleep deprivation. So, manage your stress levels, and stick to a sleep routine to stop having weird dreams. If you wake up from a weird dream, you can fall back asleep using deep breaths or any relaxing activity. You can research other causes of weird dreams and ways to stop yourself from having them for your essay about dreams and sleep.

The same areas of the brain that are active when we learn and process information in the actual world are active when we dream, and they replay the information as we sleep. Many things we see, hear, and feel in our everyday lives appear in our dreams. If you want to write an informative essay about dreams and sleep, look into more details about this topic.

Tip: When editing for grammar, we also recommend taking the time to improve the readability score of a piece of writing before publishing or submitting it.

People may not remember what happened in their dreams. Studies show that people tend to forget their dreams due to the changing levels of acetylcholine and norepinephrine during sleep. This will be quite an exciting topic for your readers because many people can relate. That being said, research more information about this topic, and discuss it in detail in your essay. 

Although some people believe that dreams don’t mean anything, many psychologists and other experts have theorized about the deeper meaning of dreams. Therefore, your essay about dreams and sleep should delve deeper into this topic. If you’re stuck picking your next essay topic, check out our round-up of essay topics about education .

FAQS on Essays About Dreams in Life

There are many great short essays about dreams; you can write your own too! Some great examples include Do Dreams Really Mean Anything? by David B. Feldman and  Dreams by Hedy Marks.

Writing about your dreams in life is a fantastic creative outlet and can even help you plan your future. Use a prompt to get started, like “What are your dreams in life?” or “What do you aspire to be in ten years?” and begin writing without thinking too much about it. See where the pen takes you and start mapping out your future with this writing exercise.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Dreams and Dreaming

Dreams and dreaming have been discussed in diverse areas of philosophy ranging from epistemology to ethics, ontology, and more recently philosophy of mind and cognitive science. This entry provides an overview of major themes in the philosophy of sleep and dreaming, with a focus on Western analytic philosophy, and discusses relevant scientific findings.

1.1 Cartesian dream skepticism

1.2 earlier discussions of dream skepticism and why descartes’ version is special, 1.3 dreaming and other skeptical scenarios, 1.4 descartes’ solution to the dream problem and real-world dreams, 2.1 are dreams experiences, 2.2 dreams as instantaneous memory insertions, 2.3 empirical evidence on the question of dream experience, 2.4 dreams and hallucinations, 2.5 dreams and illusions, 2.6 dreams as imaginative experiences, 2.7 dreaming and waking mind wandering, 2.8 the problem of dream belief, 3.1 dreaming as a model system and test case for consciousness research, 3.2 dreams, psychosis, and delusions, 3.3 beyond dreams: dreamless sleep experience and the concepts of sleep, waking, and consciousness, 4. dreaming and the self, 5. immorality and moral responsibility in dreams, 6.1 the meaning of dreams, 6.2 the functions of dreaming, 7. conclusions, other internet resources, related entries, 1. dreams and epistemology.

Dream skepticism has traditionally been the most famous and widely discussed philosophical problem raised by dreaming (see Williams 1978; Stroud 1984). In the Meditations , Descartes uses dreams to motivate skepticism about sensory-based beliefs about the external world and his own bodily existence. He notes that sensory experience can also lead us astray in commonplace sensory illusions such as seeing things as too big or small. But he does not think such cases justify general doubts about the reliability of sensory perception: by taking a closer look at an object seen under suboptimal conditions, we can easily avoid deception. By contrast, dreams suggest that even in a seemingly best-case scenario of sensory perception (Stroud 1984), deception is possible. Even the realistic experience of sitting dressed by the fire and looking at a piece of paper in one’s hands (Descartes 1641: I.5) is something that can, and according to Descartes often does, occur in a dream.

There are different ways of construing the dream argument. A strong reading is that Descartes is trapped in a lifelong dream and none of his experiences have ever been caused by external objects (the Always Dreaming Doubt ; see Newman 2019). A weaker reading is that he is just sometimes dreaming but cannot rule out at any given moment that he is dreaming right now (the Now Dreaming Doubt ; see Newman 2019). This is still epistemologically worrisome: even though some of his sensory-based beliefs might be true, he cannot determine which these are unless he can rule out that he is dreaming. Doubt is thus cast on all of his beliefs, making sensory-based knowledge slip out of reach.

Cartesian-style skeptical arguments have the following form (quoted from Klein 2015):

  • If I know that p , then there are no genuine grounds for doubting that p .
  • U is a genuine ground for doubting that p .
  • Therefore, I do not know that p .

If we apply this to the case of dreaming, we get:

  • If I know that I am sitting dressed by the fire, then there are no genuine grounds for doubting that I am really sitting dressed by the fire.
  • If I were now dreaming, this would be a genuine ground for doubting that I am sitting dressed by the fire: in dreams, I have often had the realistic experience of sitting dressed by the fire when I was actually lying undressed in bed!
  • Therefore, I do not know that I am now sitting dressed by the fire.

Importantly, both strong and weak versions of the dream argument cast doubt only on sensory-based beliefs, but leave other beliefs unscathed. According to Descartes, that 2+3=5 or that a square has no more than 4 sides is knowable even if he is now dreaming:

although, in truth, I should be dreaming, the rule still holds that all which is clearly presented to my intellect is indisputably true. (Descartes 1641: V.15)

By Descartes’ lights, dreams do not undermine our ability to engage in the project of pure, rational enquiry (Frankfurt 1970; but see Broughton 2002).

Dream arguments have been a staple of philosophical skepticism since antiquity and were so well known that in his objections to the Meditations , Hobbes (1641) criticized Descartes for not having come up with a more original argument. Yet, Descartes’ version of the problem, more than any other, has left its mark on the philosophical discussion.

Earlier versions tended to touch upon dreams just briefly and discuss them alongside other examples of sensory deception. For example, in the Theaetetus (157e), Plato has Socrates discuss a defect in perception that is common to

dreams and diseases, including insanity, and everything else that is said to cause illusions of sight and hearing and the other senses.

This leads to the conclusion that knowledge cannot be defined through perception.

Dreams also appear in the canon of standard skeptical arguments used by the Pyrrhonists. Again, dreams and sleep are just one of several conditions (including illness, joy, and sorrow) that cast doubt on the trusthworthiness of sensory perception (Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers; Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism) .

Augustine ( Against the Academics ; Confessions) thought the dream problem could be contained, arguing that in retrospect, we can distinguish both dreams and illusions from actual perception (Matthew 2005: chapter 8). And Montaigne ( The Apology for Raymond Sebond ) noted that wakefulness itself teems with reveries and illusions, which he thought were even more epistemologically worrisome than nocturnal dreams.

Descartes devoted much more space to the discussion of dreaming and cast it as a unique epistemological threat distinct from both waking illusions and evil genius or brain-in-a-vat-style arguments. His claim that he has often been deceived by his dreams implies he also saw dreaming as a real-world (rather than merely hypothetical) threat.

This is further highlighted by the intimate, first-person style of the Meditations . Their narrator is supposed to exemplify everyone’s epistemic situation, illustrating the typical defects of the human mind. Readers are further drawn in by Descartes’ strategy of moving from commonsense examples towards more sophisticated philosophical claims (Frankfurt 1970). For example, Descartes builds up towards dream skepticism by first considering familiar cases of sensory illusions and then deceptively realistic dreams.

Finally, much attention has been devoted to several dreams Descartes reportedly had as a young man. Some believe these dreams embodied theoretical doubts he developed in the Discourse and Meditations (Baillet 1691; Leibniz 1880: IV; Cole 1992; Keefer 1996). Hacking (2001:252) suggests that for Descartes, dream skepticism was not just a philosophical conundrum but a source of genuine doubt. There is also some discussion about the dream reports’ authenticity (Freud 1940; Cole 1992; Clarke 2006; Browne 1977).

In the Meditations , after discussing the dream argument, Descartes raises the possibility of an omnipotent evil genius determined to deceive us even in our most basic beliefs. Contrary to dream deception, Descartes emphasizes that the evil genius hypothesis is a mere fiction. Still, it radicalizes the dream doubt in two respects. One, where the dream argument left the knowability of certain general truths intact, these are cast in doubt by the evil genius hypothesis . Two, where the dream argument, at least on the weaker reading, involves just temporary deception, the evil genius has us permanently deceived.

One modernized version, the brain-in-a-vat thought experiment, says that if evil scientists placed your brain in a vat and stimulated it just right, your conscious experience would be exactly the same as if you were still an ordinary, embodied human being (Putnam 1981). In the Matrix -trilogy (Chalmers 2005), Matrixers live unbeknownst to themselves in a computer simulation. Unlike the brain-in-a-vat , they have bodies that are kept alive in pods, and flaws in the simulation allow some of them to bend its rules to their advantage.

Unlike dream deception, which is often cast as a regularly recurring actuality (cf. Windt 2011), brain-in-a-vat-style arguments are often thought to be merely logically or nomologically possible. However, there might be good reasons for thinking that we actually live in a computer simulation (Bostrom 2003), and if we lend some credence to radical skeptical scenarios, this may have consequences for how we act (Schwitzgebel 2017).

Even purely hypothetical skeptical scenarios may enhance their psychological force by capitalizing on the analogy with dreams. Clark (2005) argues that the Matrix contains elements of “industrial-strength deception” in which both sensory experience and intellectual functioning are exactly the same as in standard wake-states, whereas other aspects are more similar to the compromised reasoning and bizarre shifts that are the hallmark of dreams.

At the end of the Sixth Meditation , Descartes suggests a solution to the dream problem that is tied to a reassessment of what it is like to dream. Contrary to his remarks in the First Meditation , he notes that dreams are only rarely connected to waking memories and are often discontinuous, as when dream characters suddenly appear or disappear. He then introduces the coherence test:

But when I perceive objects with regard to which I can distinctly determine both the place whence they come, and that in which they are, and the time at which they appear to me, and when, without interruption, I can connect the perception I have of them with the whole of the other parts of my life, I am perfectly sure that what I thus perceive occurs while I am awake and not during sleep. (Meditation VI. 24)

For all practical purposes, he has now found a mark by which dreaming and waking can be distinguished (cf. Meditation I.7), and even if the coherence test is not fail-safe, the threat of dream deception has been averted.

Descartes’ remarks about the discontinuous and ad hoc nature of many dreams are backed up by empirical work on dream bizarreness (see Hobson 1988; Revonsuo & Salmivalli 1995). Still, many of his critics were not convinced this helped his case against the skeptic. Even if Descartes’ revised phenomenological description characterizes most dreams, one might occasionally merely dream of successfully performing the test (Hobbes 1641), and in some dreams, one might seem to have a clear and distinct idea but this impression is false (Bourdin 1641). Both the coherence test and the criterion of clarity and distinctness would then be unreliable.

How considerations of empirical plausibility impact the dream argument continues to be a matter of debate. Grundmann (2002) appeals to scientific dream research to introduce an introspective criterion: when we introspectively notice that we are able to engage in critical reflection, we have good reason to think that we are awake and not dreaming. However, this assumes critical reasoning to be uniformly absent in dreams. If attempts at critical reasoning do occur in dreams and if they generally tend to be corrupted, the introspective criterion might again be problematic (Windt 2011, 2015a). There are also cases in which even after awakening, people mistake what was in fact a dream for reality (Wamsley et al. 2014). At least in certain situations and for some people, dream deception might be a genuine cause of concern (Windt 2015a).

2. The ontology of dreams

In what follows, the term “conscious experience” is used as an umbrella term for the occurrence of sensations, thoughts, impressions, emotions etc. in dreams (cf. Dennett 1976). These are all phenomenal states: there is something it is like to be in these states for the subject of experience (cf. Nagel 1974). To ask about dream experience is to ask whether it is like something to dream while dreaming, and whether what it is like is similar to (or relevantly different from) corresponding waking experiences.

Cartesian dream skepticism depends on a seemingly innocent background assumption: that dreams are conscious experiences. If this is false, then dreams are not deceptive experiences during sleep and we cannot be deceived, while dreaming, about anything at all. Whether dreams are experiences is a major question for the ontology of dreams and closely bound up with dream skepticism.

The most famous argument denying that dreams are experiences was formulated by Norman Malcolm (1956, 1959). Today, his position is commonly rejected as implausible. Still, it set the tone for the analysis of dreaming as a target phenomenon for philosophy of mind.

For Malcolm, the denial of dream experience followed from the conceptual analysis of sleep: “if a person is in any state of consciousness it logically follows that he is not sound asleep” (Malcolm 1956: 21). Following some remarks of Wittgenstein’s (1953: 184; see Chihara 1965 for discussion), Malcolm claimed

the concept of dreaming is derived, not from dreaming, but from descriptions of dreams, i.e., from the familiar phenomenon that we call “telling a dream”. (Malcolm 1959:55)

Malcolm argued that retrospective dream reports are the sole criterion for determining whether a dream occurred and there is no independent way of verifying dream reports. While first-person, past-tense psychological statements (such as “I felt afraid”) can at least in principle be verified by independent observations (but see Canfield 1961; Siegler 1967; Schröder 1997), he argued dream reports (such as “in my dream, I felt afraid”) are governed by different grammars and merely superficially resemble waking reports. In particular, he denied dream reports imply the occurrence of experiences (such as thoughts, feelings, or judgements) in sleep:

If a man had certain thoughts and feelings in a dream it no more follows that he had those thoughts and feelings while asleep, than it follows from his having climbed a mountain in a dream that he climbed a mountain while asleep. (Malcolm 1959/1962: 51–52)

What exactly Malcolm means by “conscious experience” is unclear. Sometimes he seems to be saying that conscious experience is conceptually tied to wakefulness (Malcolm 1956); other times he claims that terms such as mental activity or conscious experience are vague and it is senseless to apply them to sleep and dreams (Malcolm 1959: 52).

Malcolm’s analysis of dreaming has been criticized as assuming an overly strict form of verificationism and a naïve view of language and conceptual change. A particularly counterintuitive consequence of his view is that there can be no observational evidence for the occurrence of dreams in sleep aside from dream reports. This includes behavioral evidence such as sleepwalking or sleeptalking, which he thought showed the person was partially awake; as he also thought dreams occur in sound sleep, such sleep behaviors were largely irrelevant to the investigation of dreaming proper. He also claimed adopting a physiological criterion of dreaming (such as EEG measures of brain activity during sleep) would change the concept of dreaming, which he argued was tied exclusively to dream reporting. This claim was particularly radical as it explicitly targeted the discovery of REM sleep and its association with dreaming (Dement & Kleitman 1957), which is commonly regarded as the beginning of the science of sleep and dreaming. Malcolm’s position was that the very project of a science of dreaming was misguided.

Contra Malcolm, most assume that justification does not depend on strict criteria with the help of which the truth of a statement can be determined with absolute certainty, but “on appeals to the simplicity, plausibility, and predictive adequacy of an explanatory system as a whole” (Chihara & Fodor 1965: 197). In this view, behavioral and/or physiological evidence can be used to verify dream reports (Ayer 1960) and the alleged principled difference between dream reports and other first-person, past-tense psychological sentences (Siegler 1967; Schröder 1997) disappears.

Putnam noted that Malcolm’s analysis of the concept of dreaming relies on the dubious idea that philosophers have access to deep conceptual truths that are hidden to laypeople:

the lexicographer would undoubtedly perceive the logical (or semantical) connection between being a pediatrician and being a doctor, but he would miss the allegedly “logical” character of the connection between dreams and waking impressions. […] this “depth grammar” kind of analyticity (or “logical dependence”) does not exist. (Putnam 1962 [1986]: 306)

Nagel argued that even if one accepts Malcolm’s analysis of the concept of dreaming,

it is a mistake to invest the demonstration that it is impossible to have experiences while asleep with more import than it has. It is an observation about our use of the word “experience”, and no more. It does not imply that nothing goes on in our minds while we dream. (Nagel 1959: 114)

Whether dream thoughts, feelings or beliefs should count as real instances of their kind now becomes an open question, and in any case there is no conceptual contradiction involved in saying one has experiences while asleep and dreaming.

To ask about dream experience is also to ask whether there is something it is like to dream during sleep as opposed to there just being something it is like to remember dreaming after awakening. Dennett’s (1976, 1979) cassette theory says dreams are the product of instantaneous memory insertion at the moment of the awakening, as if a cassette with pre-scripted dreams had been inserted into memory, ready for replay. Dennett claims the cassette theory and the view that dreams are experiences can deal equally well with empirical evidence for instance on the relationship between dreaming and REM sleep. The cassette theory is preferable because it is more parsimonious, positing only an unconscious dream composition process rather than an additional conscious presentation process in sleep. For Dennett, the important point is that it is impossible to distinguish between the two rival theories based on dream recall; the question of dream experience should be settled by independent empirical evidence.

While Dennett shares Malcolm’s skepticism about dream experience, this latter claim is diametrically opposed to Malcolm’s rejection of a science of dreaming. For Dennett, the unreliability of dream recall also is not unique, but exemplifies a broader problem with memory reports: we generally cannot use retrospective recall to distinguish conscious experience from memory insertion (Dennett 1991; see also Emmett 1978).

An earlier and much discussed (Binz 1878; Goblot 1896; Freud 1899; Hall 1981; Kramer 2007:22–24) version of Dennett’s cassette theory goes back to Maury’s (1861) description of a long and complex dream about the French revolution that culminated in his execution at the guillotine, at which point Maury suddenly awoke to find that the headboard had fallen on his neck. Because the dream seemed to systematically build up to this dramatic conclusion, which in turn coincided with a sudden external event, he suggested that such cases were best explained as instantaneous memory insertions experienced at the moment of awakening. Similarly, Gregory (1916) described dreams are psychical explosions occurring at the moment of awakening.

The trustworthiness of dream reports continues to be contentious. Rosen (2013) argues that dream reports are often fabricated and fail to accurately describe experiences occurring during sleep. By contrast, Windt (2013, 2015a) argues that dream reports can at least under certain conditions (such as in laboratory studies, when dreams are reported immediately after awakening by trained participants) be regarded as trustworthy sources of evidence with respect to previous experience during sleep.

Unlike Malcolm, many believe that whether dreams are experiences is an empirical question; and unlike Dennett, the predominant view is that the empirical evidence does indeed support this claim (Flanagan 2000; Metzinger 2003; Revonsuo 2006; Rosen 2013; Windt 2013, 2015a).

A first reason for thinking that dreams are experiences during sleep is the relationship between dreaming and REM (rapid eye movement) sleep. Researchers in the 1950s discovered that sleep is not a uniform state of rest and passivity, but there is a sleep architecture involving different stages of sleep that is relatively stable both within and across individuals (Aserinsky & Kleitman 1953, 1955; Dement & Kleitman 1957). Following sleep onset, periods of non-REM (or NREM) sleep including slow wave sleep (so called because of the presence of characteristic slow-wave, high-voltage EEG activity) are followed by periods of high-frequency, low-voltage activity during REM sleep. EEG measures from REM sleep strongly resemble waking EEG. REM sleep is additionally characterized by rapid eye movements and a near-complete loss of muscle tone (Dement 1999: 27–50; Jouvet 1999).

The alignment between conscious experience on the one hand and wake-like brain activity and muscular paralysis on the other hand would seem to support the experiential status of dreams as well as explain the outward passivity that typically accompanies them. Reports of dreaming are in fact much more frequent following REM (81.9%) than NREM sleep awakenings (43%; Nielsen 2000). REM reports tend to be more elaborate, vivid, and emotionally intense, whereas NREM reports tend to be more thought-like, confused, non-progressive, and repetitive (Hobson et al. 2000). These differences led to the idea that REM sleep is an objective marker of dreaming (Dement & Kleitman 1957; Hobson 1988: 154).

Attempts to identify dreaming with mental activity during REM sleep have not, however, been successful, and many now hold that dreams can occur in all stages of sleep (e.g., Antrobus 1990; Foulkes 1993b; Solms 1997, 2000; Domhoff 2003; Nemeth & Fazekas 2018). In recent years there has been renewed interest in NREM sleep for the study of dreaming (Noreika et al. 2009; Siclari et al. 2013, 2017). This suggests the inference from the physiology of REM sleep to the phenomenology of dreaming is not straightforward.

A second line of evidence comes from lucid dreams, or dreams in which one knows one is dreaming and often has some level of dream control (Voss et al. 2013; Voss & Hobson 2015; Baird et al. 2019). The term lucid dreaming was coined by van Eeden (1913), but Aristotle ( On Dreams ) already noted that one can sometimes be aware while dreaming that one is dreaming.

Scientific evidence that lucid dreaming is real and a genuine sleep phenomenon comes from laboratory studies (Hearne 1978; LaBerge et al. 1981) showing lucid dreamers can use specific, pre-arranged patterns of eye movements (e.g., right-left-right-left) to signal in real-time that they are now lucid and engaging in dream experiments. These signals are clearly identifiable on the EOG and suggest a correspondence between dream-eye movements and real-eye movements (as predicted by the so-called scanning hypothesis ; see Dement & Kleitman 1957; Leclair-Visonneau et al. 2010). Retrospective reports confirm that the dreamer really was lucid and signalled lucidity (Dresler et al. 2012; Stumbrys et al. 2014).

Signal-verified lucid dreams have been used to study muscular activity accompanying body movements in dreams (Erlacher et al. 2003; Dresler et al. 2011), for advanced EEG analysis of brain activity during lucid dreaming (Voss et al. 2009), and imaging studies (Dresler et al. 2011, 2012). Eye signals can also be used to measure the duration of different activities performed in lucid dreams; contrary to the cassette theory, lucid dreams have temporal extension and certain dream actions even seem to take slightly longer than in waking (Erlacher et al. 2014). There have also been attempts to induce lucidity through non-invasive electrical stimulation during sleep (Stumbrys et al. 2013; Voss et al. 2014). The combination of signal-verified lucid dreaming with volitional control over dream content, retrospective report, and objective sleep measures has been proposed to provide controlled conditions for the study of conscious experience in sleep and a new methodology for investigating the relationship between conscious experience and neurophysiological processes (Baird et al.2019).

A third line of evidence (Revonsuo 2006: 77) comes from dream-enactment behavior (Nielsen et al. 2009), most prominently in patients with REM-sleep behavior disorder (RBD; Schenck & Mahowald 1996; Schenck 2005; Leclair-Visonneau et al. 2010). Due to a loss of the muscular atonia that accompanies REM sleep in healthy subjects, these patients show complex, seemingly goal-directed outward behaviors such as running or fighting off an attacker during REM sleep. Retrospective dream reports often match these behaviors, suggesting that patients literally act out their dreams during sleep.

While persuasive, these lines of evidence might not satisfy skeptics about dream experience. They might worry that results from lucid dreaming and dream enactment do not generalize to ordinary, non-lucid dreams; they might also construe alternative explanations that do not require conscious experience in sleep. There are also methodological concerns, for instance about how closely sleep-behaviors actually match dream experience. A key issue is that to support the experiential status of dreams, evidence from sleep polysomnography, signal verified lucid dreams, or sleep behavior requires convergence with retrospective dream reports. This means trusting dream reports is built into any attempt to empirically resolve the question of dream experience – which then invites the familiar skeptical concerns. Again, an anti-skeptical strategy may be to appeal to explanatory considerations. In this view, the convergence of dream reports and objective polysomnographic or behavioral observations is best explained by the assumption that dreams are experiences in sleep, and this assumption is strengthened by further incoming findings. This strategy places dream reports at the center of scientific dream research while avoiding the contentious claim that their trustworthiness, and with it the experiential status of dreams, can be demonstrated conclusively by independent empirical means (Windt 2013, 2015a).

Even where philosophers agree dreams are experiences, they often disagree on how exactly to characterize dreaming relative to wake-state psychological terms. Often, questions about the ontology of dreaming intersect with epistemological issues. Increasingly, they also incorporate empirical findings.

The standard view is that dreams have the same phenomenal character as waking perception in that they seemingly put us in contact with mind-independent objects, yet no such object is actually being perceived. This means dreams count as hallucinations in the philosophical sense (Crane & French 2017; Macpherson 2013). Even if, in a particularly realistic dream, my visual experience was exactly as it would be if I were awake (I could see my bedroom, my hands on the bed sheets, etc.), as long as my eyes were closed during the episode, I would not, literally, be seeing anything.

There is some controversy in the psychological literature about whether dreams should be regarded as hallucinations. Some believe the term hallucination should be reserved for clinical contexts and wake-state pathologies (Aleman & Larøi 2008: 17; but see ffytche 2007; ffytche et al. 2010).

The view that dreams involve hallucinations is implicit in Descartes’ assumption that even when dreaming,

it is certain that I seem to see light, hear a noise, and feel heat; this cannot be false, and this is what in me is properly called perceiving ( sentire ). (Descartes 1641: II.9)

It also lies at the heart of Aristotle’s ( On Dreams ) assumption that dreams result from the movements of the sensory organs that continue even after the original stimulus has ceased. He believed that in the silence of sleep, these residual movements result in vivid sensory imagery that is subjectively indistinguishable from genuine perception (see also Dreisbach 2000; Barbera 2008).

The assumption of phenomenological equivalence between dream and waking experience can also be found in Berkeley’s (1710: I.18) idealist claim that the existence of external bodies is not necessary for the production of vivid, wake-like perceptual experience. Similarly, Russell defended sense-data theory by noting that in dreams,

I have all the experiences that I seem to have; it is only things outside my mind that are not as I believe them to be while I am dreaming. (Russell 1948: 149–150)

Elsewhere, he argued dreams and waking life

must be treated with equal respect; it is only by some reality not merely sensible that dreams can be condemned. (Russell 1914: 69)

Hume was less clear on this matter, proposing that dreams occupy an intermediate position between vivid and largely non-voluntary sensory impressions and ideas, or “the faint images of previous impressions in thinking and reasoning” (Hume 1739: 1.1.1.1). On the one hand, as mere creatures of the mind, Hume wanted to categorize dreams as ideas. On the other hand, he acknowledged that in sleep, “our ideas can approach the vivacity of sensory impressions” (Hume 1739: 1.1.1.1). Dreams do not fit comfortably into Hume’s attempt to draw a dichotomous distinction between impressions, including perception, and ideas, including sensory imagination (Ryle 1949; Waxman 1994; Broughton 2006).

Phenomenologists often focus not so much on the quality of dream imagery as on the overall character of experience, noting that dreams are experienced as reality; as in waking perception, we simply feel present in a world. This also sets dreams apart from waking fantasy and daydreams (Husserl 1904/1905; Uslar 1964; Conrad 1968; Globus 1987: 89.

At its strongest, the hallucination view claims that dreaming and waking experience are identical in both the quality of sensory imagery and their overall, self-in-a-world structure (Revonsuo 2006: 84). This claim is central to the virtual reality metaphor , according to which consciousness itself is dreamlike and waking perception a kind of online hallucination modulated by the senses (Llinás & Ribary 1994; Llinás & Paré 1991; Revonsuo 2006; Metzinger 2003, 2009).

This seems to be empirically supported. Neuroimaging studies (Dang-Vu et al. 2007; Nir & Tononi 2010; Desseilles et al. 2011) show that the predominance of visual and motor imagery as well as strong emotions in dreams is paralleled by high activation of the corresponding brain areas in REM sleep, which may exceed waking; at the same time, the cognitive deficits often thought to characterize dreams such as the loss of self-awareness, the absence of critical thinking, delusional reasoning, and mnemonic deficits fit in well with the comparative deactivation of frontal areas (Hobson et al. 2000). Hobson (1988, Hobson et al. 2000) has argued that the vivid, hallucinatory character of dreaming results from the fact that in REM sleep, the visual and motor areas are activated in the same way as in waking perception, the sole difference being dreams’ dependence on internal signal generation. Horikawa and colleagues (2013) used neuroimaging data from sleep onset to predict the types of objects described in mentation reports, which they took to support the perceptual equivalence between dreaming and waking.

Generally, versions of the hallucination view that suggest dreams replicate all aspects of waking perception are too vague to be informative. Especially for subtle perceptual activities (such as visual search), we might not know enough about dream phenomenology to make any strong claims (Nielsen 2010). Specifying points of similarity leads to a more informative and precise, but likely also more nuanced view. Dreams are heterogeneous, and some might be more perception-like while others resemble imagination (Windt 2015a). There might also be differences between or even within specific types of imagery. For example, visual imagery might be quite different from touch sensations, which tend to be rare in dreams (Hobson 1988). Visual dream imagery might overall resemble waking perception but lack color saturation, background detail and focus (Rechtschaffen & Buchignani, 1992). Classifying dreams as either hallucinatory or imaginative is further complicated by the fact that there is strong overlap in cortical activity associated with both visual imagery and perception (Zeidman & Maguire, 2016). This means even a strong overlap in cortical activity between, say, visual dream imagery and visual perception does not necessarily set dreaming apart from waking imagination.

This is also true for evidence on eye movements in dreams. LaBerge and colleagues (2018) recently showed that eye tracking of objects is smooth in lucid dreaming and perceiving, but not in imagining. Drawing from this evidence, Rosen (forthcoming) suggests many dreams mimic the phenomenology of interacting with a stable world, including eye movements and visual search. Others argue we should not analogize dream imagery to mind-independent, scannable objects and that eye movements might instead be implicated in the generation of dream imagery (Windt 2018).

Another way to make sense of the claim that dreaming has the same phenomenal character as waking perception is to say some kinds of dream imagery are illusory: they involve misperception of an external object as having different properties than it actually has (cf. Smith 2002; Crane & French 2017). The illusion view disagrees with the hallucination view on whether dreams have a contemporaneous external stimulus source.

The illusion view has fallen out of favor but has a long history. The Ancients believed dreams have bodily sources. This idea underlies the practice of using dreams to diagnose illness, as practiced in the shrines at Epidaurus (Galen On Diagnosis in Dreams ; van de Castle 1994). Aristotle ( On Dreams ) thought some dreams are caused by indigestion, and Hobbes adopted this view, claiming different kinds of dreams could be traced to different bodily sensations. For instance, “lying cold breedeth Dreams of Feare, and raiseth the thought and Image of some fearfull object” (Hobbes 1651: 91).

Appeals to the bodily sources of dreaming became especially popular in the 19 th and early 20 th centuries. Many believed specific dream themes such as flying were linked to sleeping position (Macnish 1838; Scherner 1861; Vold 1910/1912; Ellis 1911) and realizing, in sleep, that one’s feet are not touching the ground (Bergson 1914).

There were also attempts to explain the phenomenology of dreaming by appealing to the absence of outward movement. The lack of appropriate feedback and of movement and touch sensations was thought to cause dreams of being unable to move (Bradley 1894) or of trying but failing to do something (Gregory 1918).

Some proponents of the “ Leibreiztheorie ” (or somatic-stimulus theory) of dreaming attempted to go beyond anecdotal observations to conduct controlled experiments. Weygandt (1893) investigated the influence of various factors including breathing, blood circulation, temperature changes, urge to urinate, sleeping position, and visual or auditory stimulation during sleep on dream content (see Schredl 2010 for details). Singer (1924) proposed experiments on stimulus incorporation in dreams can inform claims on the ontology of dreaming: If dreams are sensations, a particular auditory stimulus should increase the frequency of dreams in nearby sleepers as well as the frequency of sound in their dreams, and it should decrease the range of quality and intensity of these dreams, making them overall more similar and predictable.

Newer studies provide evidence for the incorporation of external stimuli in dreams, including light flashes, sounds, sprays of water applied to the skin (Dement & Wolpert 1958), thermal (Baldridge 1966), electrical (Koulack 1969), and verbal stimuli (Berger 1963; Breger et al. 1971; Hoelscher et al., 1981), as well as blood pressure cuff stimulation on the leg (Nielsen et al. 1995; Sauvageau et al. 1998).

Muscular activity also often leaves its mark on dreams. It occurs throughout sleep but is especially frequent in REM sleep, mostly in the form of twitching but occasionally also in the form of larger, seemingly goal-directed movements (Blumberg 2010; Blumberg & Plumeau 2016). The relation between outward and dream movements is complex: in some cases, outward movements might mirror dream movements, while in others, sensory feedback might prompt dream imagery (Windt 2018).

Generally, it seems external and bodily stimuli can be related to varying degrees to dream and sleep onset imagery (Nielsen 2017; Windt 2018; Windt et al. 2016). Some of these cases appear to fit the concept of illusion, as in when the sound of the alarm clock is experienced, in a dream, as a siren, or when blood pressure cuff inflation on the leg leads to dreams of wearing strange shoes (Windt 2018; for these and other examples, see Nielsen et al. 1995). In other cases, such as when blood pressure cuff stimulation on the leg prompts a dream of seeing someone else’s leg being run over, describing this as illusory misperception might be less straightforward.

Saying that dreams can be prompted by external stimuli and that in some cases these are best described as illusions is different from the stronger claim, sometimes advanced by historical proponents of somatic-stimulus theory, that dreams generally are caused by external or bodily stimuli. As an example of the stronger claim, consider Wundt’s proposal that the

ideas which arise in dreams come, at least to a great extent, from sensations, especially from those of the general sense, and are therefore mostly illusions of fancy, probably only seldom pure memory ideas which hence become hallucinations. (Wundt 1896: 179)

This claim is likely too strong. It is also likely that appeals to external or bodily stimuli on their own cannot fully explain dream imagery, including when and how external stimuli are incorporated in dreams. Sensory incorporation in dreams is often hard to predict and indirect; associated imagery seems related not just to stimulus intensity, but also to short- and long term memories. A full explanation of dream content additionally has to take the cognitive and memory sources of dreaming into account (Windt 2018; Nielsen 2017; cf. Silberer 1919).

The most important rival to the hallucination view is that dreams are imaginative experiences (Liao & Gendler 2019; Thomas 2014). This can mean dream imagery involves imaginings rather than percepts (including hallucinations or illusions; McGinn 2004), that dream beliefs are imaginative and not real beliefs (Sosa 2007), or both (Ichikawa 2008, 2009). An important advantage is that by assimilating dreams to commonplace mental states such as waking fantasy and daydreaming, rather than a rare and often pathological occurrence such as hallucinations, it provides a more unified account of mental life (Stone 1984). However, the reasons for adopting the imagination view are diverse, and dreams have been proposed to resemble imaginings and differ from perception along a number of dimensions (e.g. McGinn 2004, 2005a,b; Thomas 2014). This issue is complicated by the fact that there is little agreement on the definition of imagination and its relation to perception (Kind 2013).

One way is to deny dreams involve presence or the feeling of being in a world, which many believe is central to waking perception. Imagination theorists compare the sense in which we feel present in our dreams to cognitive absorption, as when we are lost in a novel, film, or vivid daydream (Sartre 1940; McGinn 2004; but see Hering 1947; Globus 1987). Some argue that reflexive consciousness or meta-awareness (as in lucid dreams) interrupts cognitive absorption and terminates the ongoing dream (Sartre 1940), essentially denying lucid dreams are possible.

Another issue is whether dreams are subject to the will (Ichikawa 2009). Imagination is often characterized as active and under our control (Wittgenstein 1967: 621, 633), involving “a special effort of the mind” (Descartes 1641: VI, 2), whereas perception is passive. Because dreams just seem to happen to us without being under voluntary control, they present an important challenge for the imagination view. Ichikawa (2009) argues lucid control dreams show dreams are generally subject to the will even where they are not under deliberate control.

Dreams are widely described as more indeterminate than waking perception (James 1890: 47; Stone 1984). In scientific dream research, vagueness is regarded as one of three main subtypes of bizarreness (Hobson 1988; Revonsuo & Salmivalli 1995). An example are dream characters who are identified not by their behavior or looks, but by just knowing (Kahn et al. 2000, 2002; Revonsuo & Tarkko 2002). Dreams are also attention-dependent and lack foreground-background structure (Thompson 2014); while it is tempting to construe the dream world as rich in detail, there is no more to dreams than meets the eye, and many think dream experience is exhausted by what is the focus of selective attention (Hunter 1983; Thompson 2014).

Indeterminacy is also related to the question of whether we dream in color or in black and white. Based on a review of historical and recent studies, Schwitzgebel (2002, 2011) argues there has been a shift in theories on dream color that coincides with the rise first of black-and-white and then color television. He argues it is unlikely that dreams themselves changed from colored to black and white and back to colored, proposing that a change in opinion is a more plausible explanation. Maybe dreams were either black and white or colored all along; or maybe they are indeterminate with respect to color, as may be the case for imagined or fictional objects; were this the case, it would strengthen the imagination view (Ichikawa 2009). Schwitzgebel’s main point is that reports of colored dreaming are unreliable and our opinions about dreams can be mistaken (but see Windt 2013, 2015a). This relates to Schwitzgebel’s (2011; Hurlburt & Schwitzgebel 2007) general skepticism about the reliability of introspection.

The issue of dream color has led to a number of follow-up studies (Schwitzgebel 2003; Schwitzgebel et al. 2006; Murzyn 2008; Schredl et al. 2008; Hoss 2010). They suggest most people dream in color and a small percentage describe grayscale or even mixed dreams (Murzyn 2008) or dreams involving moderate color saturation (Rechtschaffen and Buchignani 1992). Indeterminacy is rarely reported.

The imagination view has consequences for Cartesian dream skepticism. If dream pain does not feel like real pain, there is a fail-safe way to determine whether one is now dreaming: one need only pinch oneself (Nelson 1966; Stone 1984; but see Hodges & Carter 1969; Kantor 1970). As Locke put it,

if our dreamer pleases to try, whether the glowing heat of a glass furnace, be barely a wandering imagination in a drowsy man’s fancy, by putting his hand into it, he may perhaps be wakened into a certainty greater than he could wish, that it is something more than bare imagination. (Locke 1689: IV.XI.8)

If dreaming feels different from waking, this raises the question why we tend to describe dreams in the same terms as waking perception. Maybe this is because most people haven’t thought about these matters and they would find the imagination view plausible if they considered it (Ichikawa 2009). Or maybe

it is just because we all know that dreams are throughout un like waking experiences that we can safely use ordinary expressions in the narration of them. (Austin 1962: 42)

Some authors classify dreams as imaginings while acknowledging they feel like perceiving. For example, Hobbes describes dreams as “the imaginations of them that sleep” (Hobbes 1651: 90), and imagination as a “ decaying sense ” (Hobbes 1651: 88). Yet he also uses the concepts of imagination and fancy to describe perception and argues “their appearance to us is Fancy, the same waking, that dreaming” (Hobbes 1651: 86).

In the scientific literature, the imagination view is complemented by cognitive theories. Foulkes (1978: 5) describes dreaming as a form of thinking with its own grammar and syntax, but allows that dream imagery is sufficently perception-like to deceive us. Domhoff’s neurocognitive model of dreaming (2001, 2003) emphasizes the dependence of dreaming on visuospatial skills and on a network including the association areas of the forebrain. The theory draws from findings on the partial or global cessation of dreaming following brain lesions (cf. Solms 1997, 2000), evidence that dreaming develops gradually and in tandem with visuospatial skills in children (Foulkes 1993a, 1999; but see Resnick et al. 1994), and results from dream content analysis supporting the continuity of dreaming with waking concerns and memories (the so-called continuity hypothesis ; see Domhoff 2001, 2003; Schredl & Hofmann 2003; Schredl 2006; see also Nir & Tononi 2010).

A number of researchers have begun to consider dreaming in the context of theories of mind wandering. Mind wandering is frequent in waking and involves spontaneous thoughts that unfold dynamically and are only weakly constrained by ongoing tasks and environmental demands (Schooler et al. 2011; Smallwood & Schooler 2015; Christoff et al. 2016). Based on phenomenological and neurophysiological similarities, dreams have been proposed to be an intensified form of waking mind wandering (Pace-Schott 2007, 2013; Domhoff 2011; Wamsley 2013; Fox et al. 2013). This basic idea seems to have been anticipated by Leibniz, who noted that the spontaneous formation of visions in dreams surpasses the capacity of our waking imagination (Leibniz, Philosophical Papers and Letters , Vol. I, 177–178).

The analogy between dreams and waking mind wandering has been discussed in the context of cognitive agency. Metzinger (2013a,b, 2015) describes dreams and waking mind wandering as involving a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy, or the ability to deliberately control one’s conscious thought processes. Dreams and waking mind wandering are not mental actions but unintentional mental behaviors, comparable to subpersonal processes such as breathing or heartbeat. Because dreaming and waking mind wandering make up a the majority of our conscious mental lives, he argues that cognitive agency and mental autonomy are the exception, not the rule.

This raises the question of how to make sense of lucid control dreams, which involve both meta-awareness and agency. Windt and Voss (2018) argue that in such cases, spontaneous processes including imagery formation co-exist alongside more deliberate, top-down control; they also argue metacognitive insight and control themselves can have spontaneous elements. This suggests spontaneity and control are not opposites, but a more complex account is needed. Possibly, certain dreams and instances of waking mind wandering can be both spontaneous and agentive.

The analogy with mind wandering might help move forward the debate on the ontology of dreaming. In this debate, a common assumption is that dreams can be categorized as either hallucinatory or imaginative. Yet the application of these terms to dreams quickly runs into counterexamples and it is unclear they are mutually exclusive. One option is pluralism (Rosen 2018b), in which some aspects of dreaming are hallucinatory, others imaginative, and yet again others illusory. Another is that dreams are sui generis, combining aspects associated with wake states such as hallucinating, imagining, or perceiving in a novel manner without mimicking them completely. Windt (2015a) proposes that mind wandering, which describes a range of mental states loosely characterized by their spontaneous and dynamic character, might be particularly suitable for the characterization of dreaming precisely because that term leaves open more specific questions on the phenomenology of dreaming, allowing for variation in control, determinacy, and so on. This might be a good starting point for describing what is unique about dreaming while also acknowledging continuities across sleep-wake states and capitalizing on the strengths of the hallucination, illusion, imagination, and cognitive views.

The second strand of the imagination view argues that dream beliefs are not real beliefs, but propositional imaginings. This may or may not be combined with the claim that dream imagery is imaginative rather than perceptual (Sosa 2007; Ichikawa 2009).

Denying that dream beliefs have the status of real beliefs only makes sense before the background of a specific account of what beliefs are and how they are distinguished from other mental states such as delusions or propositional imaginings. For instance, Ichikawa (2009) argues that if we follow interpretationist or dispositionalist accounts of belief, dream beliefs fall short of real beliefs. He claims dream beliefs lack connection with perceptual experience and fail to motivate actions; consequently, they do not have the same functional role as real beliefs. Moreover, we cannot ascribe dream beliefs to a person by observing them lying asleep in bed. Dream beliefs are often inconsistent with longstanding waking beliefs and acquired and discarded without any process of belief revision (Ichikawa 2009).

This analysis of dream beliefs has consequences for skepticism. If dream beliefs are propositional imaginings, then we do not falsely believe while dreaming that we are now awake, but only imagine that we do (Sosa 2007). It is not clear though that this protects us from deception. If dream beliefs fall short of real beliefs, this might even make the specter of dream deception more worrisome: in mistaking dream beliefs for the real thing, we would now be deceived about the status of our own mental states (Ichikawa 2008).

It is also not clear whether the same type of argument extends to mental states other than beliefs. As Lewis points out, a person might

in fact believe or realize in the course of a dream that he was dreaming, and even if we said that, in such case, he only dreamt that he was dreaming, this still leaves it possible for someone who is asleep to entertain at the time the thought that he is asleep. (Lewis 1969: 133)

Mental states other than believing such as entertaining, thinking, or minimally appraisive instances of taking for granted might be sufficient for deception (Reed 1979).

The debate about dream beliefs is paralleled by a debate about whether delusions are beliefs or imaginings (see Currie 2000; Currie & Ravenscroft 2002; McGinn 2004; Bayne & Pacherie 2005; Bortolotti 2009; Gendler 2013). Both debates might plausibly inform each other, especially as dreams are sometimes proposed to be delusional (Hobson 1999).

3. Dreaming and theories of consciousness

Dreams are a global state of consciousness in which experience arises under altered behavioral and neurophysiological conditions as compared to standard wakefulness; unlike other altered states of consciousness (such as drug-induced or deep meditative states) and pathological wake states (such as psychosis or neurological syndromes), dreams occur spontaneously and regularly in healthy subjects. For both reasons, many regard dreams as a test case for theories of consciousness or even an ideal model system for consciousness research (Churchland 1988; Revonsuo 2006).

Existing proposals differ on the phenomenology of dreaming: referring to dream bizarreness, Churchland describes dream experience as robustly different from waking, whereas Revonsuo argues dreaming is similar to waking and the purest form of experience:

the dreaming brain brings out the phenomenal level of organization in a clear and distinct form. Dreaming is phenomenality pure and simple, untouched by external physical stimulation or behavioural activity. (Revonsuo 2006: 75)

Revonsuo argues dreaming reveals the basic, state-independent structure of consciousness to be immersive: “dreaming depicts consciousness first and foremost as a subjective world- for-me ” (Revonsuo 2006: 75). This leads him to introduce the “world-simulation metaphor of consciousness”, according to which consciousness itself is essentially simulational and dreamlike. This is taken to support internalism about conscious experience.

This latter claim is also contentious. Noë (2004: 213) argues that phenomenological differences between dreaming and waking (such as greater instability of visual dream imagery) result from the lack of dynamic interaction with the environment in dreams. He proposes this shows that neural states are sufficient for dreaming but denies they are also sufficient for perceptual experience.

A possible problem for both views is their reliance on background assumptions about the phenomenology of dreaming and its disconnection from environmental stimuli and bodily sensations. Windt (2015a, 2018) argues both internalism and externalism mistakenly assume dreams to be isolated from external sensory input and own-body perception; she believes both the phenomenology of dreaming and its correlation with external stimuli are complex and variable. She argues the analysis of dreaming does not clearly support either side in the debate on internalism vs externalism (but see Rosen 2018a). Generally, in the absence of a well worked out theory of dreaming and its sleep-stage and neural correlates, proposals for using dreaming as a model system or test case run the risk of relying on an oversimplified description of the target phenomenon (Windt & Noreika 2011).

Recent accounts appealing to generative models and predictive processing (Clark 2013b; Hohwy 2013) suggest a new, unified account of perception, imagination, and dreaming. In these accounts, different mental states, including perception and action, embody different strategies of hypothesis testing and prediction error minimization. Perception is the attempt to model the hidden external causes of sensory stimuli; action involves keeping the internal model stable while changing the sensory input. Clark argues that on such a model,

systems that know how to perceive an object as a cat are thus systems that, ipso facto , are able to use a top-down cascade to bring about the kinds of activity pattern that would be characteristic of the presence of a cat. […] Perceivers like us, if this is correct, are inevitably potential dreamers and imaginers too. Moreover, they are beings who, in dreaming and imagining, are deploying many of the very same strategies and resources used in ordinary perception. (Clark 2013a: 764)

Predictive processing accounts have also been used to explain specific features of dreaming. Bizarreness has been associated with the comparative lack of external stimulus processing, implying dream imagery is relatively unconstrained by prediction errors (cf. Hobson & Friston 2012; Fletcher & Frith 2008; Bucci & Grasso 2017). Windt (2018) suggests a predictive processing account of dream imagery generation that links bodily self-experience to own-body perception and subtle motor behaviors such as twitching in REM sleep (Blumberg 2010; Blumberg & Plumeau 2016). She argues that movement sensations in dreams, in relation to REM-sleep related muscle twitching, involve a form of bodily self-sampling in which coordinated muscular activity contributes to the generation and maintenance of a body model. This is important because in predictive processing accounts neither the bodily nor the external causes of sensory inputs are known; at the same time, having an accurate body model is a prerequisite for action, requiring the system to disambiguate between self- and other generated changes to sensory inputs. Especially in early development, sleep might provide the ideal conditions for exploring one’s own body via subtle but coordinated muscular activity while processing of visual and auditory stimuli is reduced.

Dreams have also been suggested as a test case for whether phenomenal consciousness can be divorced from cognitive access (e.g., Block 2007; but see Cohen & Dennett 2011). Sebastián (2014a) argues that dreams provide empirical evidence that conscious experience can occur independently of cognitive access. This is because during (non-lucid) REM-sleep dreams, the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC) as the most plausible mechanism underlying cognitive access is selectively deactivated (see also Pantani et al. 2018). This would challenge theories linking conscious experience to access, such as higher-order-thought theory (Sebastián 2014b). However, both the hypoactivation of the dlPCF in REM sleep and its association with cognitive access have been debated. Fazekas and Nemeth (2018) suggest that certain kinds of cognitive access may be independent of dlPFC activation, necessitating a more complex account.

Dreaming has been suggested as a model system not just of waking consciousness in general, but also of psychotic wake states in particular. The analogy between dreaming and madness has a long philosophical history (Plato, Phaedrus ; Kant 1766; Schopenhauer 1847) and finds particularly stark expression in Hobson’s claim that “dreaming is not a model of a psychosis. It is a psychosis. It’s just a healthy one” (Hobson 1999: 44). Gottesmann (2006) proposes dreaming as a neurophysiological model of schizophrenia. There is a rich discussion on the theoretical and methodological implications of dream research for psychiatry (see Scarone et al. 2007; d’Agostino et al. 2013; see Windt & Noreika 2011 as well as the other papers in this special issue) and a number of studies have investigated differences in dream reports from schizophrenic and healthy subjects (Limosani et al. 2011a,b).

Rather than likening dreaming to waking in general or specific wake states such as psychosis, there have also been attempts to compare specific dream phenomena to wake-state delusions. Gerrans (2012, 2013, 2014) focuses on character misidentification in dreams and delusions of hyperfamiliarity (such as the Frégoli delusion, in which strangers are mistakenly identified as family members, and déjà vu ) to argue that anomalous experience and faulty reality testing both play a role in delusion formation. Rosen (2015) analyzes instances of thought insertion and of auditory hallucinations, which are key symptoms of schizophrenia, to raise broader questions about the altered sense of agency in dreams as compared to waking.

Philosophers have focused almost exclusively on dreaming, largely leaving to the side questions about dreamless sleep including whether it is uniformly unconscious. In recent years there has been a surge of interest in the possibility of dreamless sleep experience and foundational issues about the definition of sleep and waking. This has been paralleled by growing interest in dreaming in NREM sleep.

Conceptually, interest in dreamless sleep experience has been facilitated by the precise definition of dreaming offered by simulation views (Revonsuo et al. 2015). If dreams are immersive sleep experiences characterized by their here -and- now structure, it makes sense to ask whether this is true for all or just a subset of sleep-related experiences and whether non-immersive sleep experiences exist. By contrast, if dreaming is broadly identified with any conscious mentation in sleep (Pagel et al. 2001), there is no conceptual space for dreamless sleep experience.

Following Thompson's (2014, 2015) discussion of dreamless sleep in Indian and Buddhist philosophy, Windt and colleagues (2016; see also Windt 2015b) introduce a framework for different kinds of dreamless sleep experience ranging from thinking and isolated imagery, perception, or bodily sensations, where these lack integration into a scene, to minimal kinds of experience lacking imagery or specific thought contents. A possible example of minimal phenomenal experience in sleep are white dreams, where people report having had experiences during sleep but cannot remember any details. Taken at face value, some white dream reports might describe experiences that lack reportable content (Windt 2015b); others might describe forgotten dreams or dreams with degraded content (Fazekas et al. 2018). Another example are reports of witnessing dreamless sleep, as described in certain meditation practices. This state is said to involve non-conceptual awareness of sleep, again in the absence of imagery or specific thought contents, and loss of sense of self (Thompson 2014, 2015). Some schools in Buddhist philosophy explain claims of deep and dreamless sleep by saying we never fully lose consciousness in sleep (Prasad 2000, 66; and Thompson 2014, 2015).

Empirically, interest in dreamless sleep experience is paralleled by increasing interest in experiences in NREM sleep (Fazekas et al. 2018). Most researchers now accept that dreaming is not confined to REM sleep, but also occurs at sleep onset and in NREM sleep. The deeper stages of NREM sleep are particularly interesting as they involve roughly similar proportions of dreaming, unconscious sleep, and white dreams (Noreika et al. 2009: Siclari et al. 2013, 2017). In the search for the neural correlates of dreaming vs unconscious dreamless sleep, this makes comparisons within the same sleep stage possible and avoids confounds involved in comparing presumably dreamful REM sleep with presumably dreamless NREM sleep. Findings suggest that activity in the same parietal hot zone underlies dreaming in both NREM and REM sleep (Siclari et al. 2017).

Where sleep and dream research have traditionally tried to identify the sleep stage correlates of dreaming, newer research suggests local changes occurring independently of sleep stages might in fact be more relevant. Traditionally regarded as global, whole-brain phenomena, there is now increasing evidence that sleep itself is locally driven, and local changes in sleep depth might be associated with changes in sleep-related experience (Siclari & Tononi 2017; Andrillon et al. 2019). While sleep and dream research are often considered as separate fields, changes in how sleep in general and sleep stages in particular are defined appear closely associated with changes in the theoretical conception of dreaming and its empirical investigation.

Historically, discoveries about dreaming have precipitated changing conceptions of sleep (for an excellent history of the study of sleep and dreaming, see Kroker 2007). Following Aristotle ( On Sleeping and Waking ), sleep was traditionally defined in negative terms as the absence of wakefulness and perception. This is still reflected in Malcolm’s assumption that “to a person who is sound asleep, ‘dead to the world’, things cannot even seem” (Malcolm 1956: 26). With the discovery of REM sleep, sleep came to be regarded as a heterogeneous phenomenon characterized by the cyclic alteration of different sleep stages. REM sleep was now considered as “neither sleeping nor waking. It was obviously a third state of the brain, as different from sleep as sleep is from wakefulness” (Jouvet 1999: 5). The folk-psychological dichotomy between sleep and wakefulness now seemed oversimplified and empirically implausible. At the same time dreaming, which had previously been considered as an intermediate state of half-sleeping and half-waking, came to be regarded as a genuine sleep phenomenon, but narrowed to REM sleep. Today, the framework for describing dreams and other sleep-related experiences is more precise, but dreaming has also been cast adrift from REM sleep.

A closely associated issue is how to define waking. Crowther’s (2018) capacitation thesis casts waking consciousness as a state in which the individual is fully switched on to their environment, but also to their own epistemic (cf. O’Shaugnessy 2002) and agentive potential; the waking individual is empowered to act and think in certain ways, though this potential need not be actualized. By contrast, dreaming is an “imagining-of consciousness” (O’Shaughnessy 2002: 430) and consciousness is conceptually tied to wakefulness. Because in lucid dreams, the epistemic and agentive profile of waking is at least partly realized, they might, according to Crowther, be regarded as closer to waking than nonlucid dreams.

This account of waking and sleep may also have consequences for the imagination model of dreaming and dream skepticism (Soteriou 2017). As in the imagination model, dreaming would be passive and action, including cognitive agency, would be tied to waking. If dreaming nonetheless involved passive episodes of imagining oneself to be active, one would be unable to tell that one were dreaming and imagining, as this insight would require the exercise of real agency. The sceptical consequence would be that when dreaming, one would lose agency as well as the capacity to gain insight into one’s current state. Yet our ability to know we are waking when waking would be unscathed; according to Soteriou, waking would thus have an epistemic function connected to the capacity to exercise agency over our mental lives.

Finally, definitions of consciousness themselves are bound up with conceptions of sleep and dreaming. As dreaming went from a state whose experiential status was doubted to being widely recognized as a second global state of consciousness, consciousness sometimes came to be defined contrastively as that which disappears in deep, dreamless sleep and reappears in waking and dreaming (Searle 2000; Tononi 2008). In light of dreamless sleep experience, such definitions are problematic (Thompson 2014, 2015; Windt 2015b; Windt et al. 2016). Dreamless sleep experience has been proposed to be particularly relevant for understanding minimal phenomenal experience, or the conditions under which the simplest kind of conscious experience arises (Windt 2015b). The investigation of dreamless sleep might thus shed light on the transition from unconscious sleep to sleep-related experience.

We almost always have a self in dreams, though this self can sometimes be a slightly different (e.g. older or younger) version of our waking self or even a different person entirely. Dreams therefore raise interesting questions about the identity between the dream and waking self. Locke (1689) invites us to imagine two men alternating in turns between sleep and wakefulness and sharing one continuously thinking soul (Locke 1689: II.I.12). He argues that if one man retained no memory of the soul’s thoughts and perceptions while it was linked to the other man’s body, they would be distinct persons. His position is that personal identity depends on psychological continuity, including recall: in the absence of recall, as illustrated by the toy example of two people sharing one soul, continuous conscious thinking does not suffice for identity. Locke also rejects the possibility of unrecalled dreams and the idea that we dream throughout sleep, remembering only a small proportion of our dreams (Locke 1689: II.I.19).

Valberg distinguishes between the subject of the dream (i.e., the dream self) and the sleeping person who is the dreamer of the dream and recalls it upon awakening (Valberg 2007). He argues that awakening from a dream involves crossing a chasm between discrete worlds with discrete spaces and times; it does not make sense to say that “the ‘I’ at these times [is] a single individual who crosses from one world to the other” (Valberg 2007: 69). According to Valberg, this is relevant to dream skepticism because there is no simple way to make sense of the claims that it is I who emerge from a dream or that I was the victim of dream deception.

Vicarious dreams, or dreams in which the protagonist of the dream seems to be a different person from the dreamer, are particularly puzzling with respect to identity. They may even raise the question of whether the dream self has an independent existence (Rosen & Sutton 2013: 1047). Such dreams are superficially similar to cases in which we imagine being another person, but according to Rosen and Sutton require a different explanation: in the case of dreaming, the imagined person’s thoughts are not framed as diverging from one’s own and one does not retain one’s own perspective in addition to the imagined one; in nonlucid dreams, only the perspective of the dream’s protagonist is retained.

The dream self is also at the center of simulation views of dreaming, which define dreaming via its immersive, here and now character as the experience of a self in a world. This leads to further questions about the phenomenology of self-experience in dreams and how it is different from waking self-experience. Different versions of the simulation view focus on different aspects of self- and world experience in dreams, ranging from social simulation (Revonsuo et al. 2015) to the typical features of selfhood in dreams (Revonsuo 2005, 2006, Metzinger 2003, 2009) to the minimal conditions for experiencing oneself as a self in dreams and what this tells us about minimal phenomenal selfhood in general (Windt 2015a, 2018). Yet these different versions of the simulation view are largely complementary and together have forged unity in a field that was previously hampered by lack of agreement about the definition of dreaming. They also integrate the philosophy of dreaming and scientific dream research.

As so often in debates about dreaming, there is disagreement about basic phenomenological questions. Revonsuo (2005) describes self-experience including bodily experience in dreams as identical to waking, whereas Metzinger (2003, 2009; see also Windt & Metzinger 2007) argues that important layers of waking self-experience (such as autobiographical memory, agency, a stable first-person perspective, metacognitive insight, and self-knowledge) are missing in nonlucid dreams. He argues this is due to the cognitive and mnemonic deficit that characterizes nonlucid dreams (cf. Hobson et al. 2000). Windt (2015a) analyzes the range of cognitive and bodily self-experience in dreams, both of which she describes as variable. She argues that in a majority of cases, dreams are weakly phenomenally embodied states in which bodily experience is largely related to movement sensations but a detailed and integrated body representation is lacking; instead, bodily experience in dreams is largely indeterminate (for an attempt to test this empirically, see Koppehele-Gossel et al. 2016). She proposes this is because dreams are also weakly functionally embodied states, in which the specific pattern of bodily experience reflects altered processing of bodily sensations (as in the illusion view). She also analyzes instances of bodiless dreams, in which dreamers say they experienced themselves as disembodied entities, to argue that self-experience can be reduced to pure spatiotemporal-self-location (Windt 2010); she proposes these cases can help identify the conditions for the emergence of minimal phenomenal selfhood (Blanke & Metzinger 2009; see also Metzinger 2013b).

How the phenomenology of dreaming compares to waking and what to say about how the dream self relates to the waking self bears on questions about the moral status of dreams. For Augustine ( Confessions ) dreams were a cause of moral concern because of their indistinguishability from waking life. What particularly worried him about dreams of sexual acts was their vividness, as well as the feeling of pleasure and seeming acquiescence or consent on the part of the dreamer. He concluded, however, that the transition from sleep to wakefulness involves a radical chasm, enabling the dreamer to awaken with a clear conscience and absolving them from taking responsibility for their dream actions.

What exactly Augustine thought the chasm between dreaming and waking consists in allows for different interpretations (Matthews 1981). Firstly, if the dream and waking self are not identical, then waking Augustine is not morally responsible for dream-Augustine’s actions. Secondly, actions performed in dreams might be morally irrelevant because they did not really happen. And thirdly, assuming that moral responsibility requires the ability to act otherwise, dreams provide no grounds for moral concern because we cannot refrain from having certain types of dreams.

The issue of dream immorality may also present a choice point between different accounts of moral evaluation. Where internalists assume the moral status of a person’s actions is entirely determined by internal factors such as intentions and motives, externalists look beyond these to the effects of actions. Driver (2007) argues that the absurdity of dream immorality itself should count against purely internalist accounts; yet she also acknowledges this absurdity is not a necessary feature of dreams.

Central to the question of dream immorality is the status of dreams as actions rather than mere behaviors. Mullane (1965) argues that while we don’t have full control over our dreams, they are not completely involuntary either; as is the case for blushing, considerable effort is required to attain control over our dreams and in some cases they can even be considered as actions. That lucid dream control is, to some extent, a learnable skill (Stumbrys et al. 2014) lends some support to this claim.

6. The meaning of dreams and the functions of dreaming

Philosophical discussions of dreaming tend to focus on (a) dream deception and (b) questions about the ontology of dreaming, its moral status, etc., that tend to intersect with dream skepticism. By contrast, the main source of interest in dreams outside of philosophy traditionally has been dream interpretation and whether dreams are a source of knowledge and insight. Historically, the epistemic status of dreams and the use of prophetic and diagnostic dreams was not just a theoretical, but a practical problem (Barbera 2008). Different types of dreams were distinguished by their putative epistemic value. Artemidorus, for instance, used the term enhypnion to refer to dreams that merely reflect the sleeper’s current bodily or psychological state and hence do not merit further interpretation, whereas he reserved the term oneiron for meaningful and symbolic dreams of divine origin.

The practice of dream interpretation was famously attacked by Aristotle in On Prophecy in Sleep . He denied that dreams are of divine origin, but allowed that occasionally, small affections of the sensory organs as might stem from distant events that cannot be perceived in waking are perceptible in the quiet of sleep. He also believed such dreams were mostly likely to occur in dullards whose minds resemble an empty desert – an assessment that was not apt to encourage interest in dreams (Kroker 2007: 37). A similarly negative view was held by early modern philosophers who believed dreams were often the source of superstitious beliefs (Hobbes 1651; Kant 1766; Schopenhauer 1847).

In Freudian dream theory, dream interpretation once more assumed a prominent role as the royal road to knowledge of the unconscious. This was associated with claims about the psychic sources of dreaming. Freud (1899) also rejected the influence of external or bodily sources, as championed by contemporary proponents of somatic-stimulus theory.

In the neuroscience of dreaming, Hobson famously argued that dreams are the product of the random, brain-stem driven activation of the brain during sleep (Hobson 1988) and at best enable personal insights in the same way as a Rorschach test (Hobson et al. 2000). Dennett (1991) illustrates the lack of design underlying the production of dream narratives through the “party game of psychoanalysis”, which involves an aimless game of question-and-answer. In the game, players follow simple rules to jointly produce narratives that can seem symbolic and meaningful, even though no intelligent and deliberate process of narration was involved.

Even if we grant that dreams are not messages from a hidden entity in need of decoding, this does not imply that dream interpretation cannot be a personally meaningful source of insight and creativity (Hobson & Wohl 2005). Whether and under which conditions, and following which methods, dream interpretation can lead to personally significant insights is an empirical question that is only beginning to be investigated systematically (see Edwards et al. 2013).

Finally, throughout history, views on the epistemic status of dreams and the type of knowledge to be gained from dream interpretation (e.g., knowledge about the future, diagnosis of physical illness, or insights about one’s current concerns) often changed in tandem with views on the origin and sources of dreaming, which gradually moved from divine origins and external sources, via the body, to the unconscious, and finally to the brain.

Different theories on the functions of dreaming have been proposed and the debate is ongoing. An important distinction is between the functions of sleep stages and the functions of dreaming. Well-documented functions of REM sleep include thermoregulation and the development of cortical structures in birds and mammals, as well as neurotransmitter repletion, the reconstruction and maintenance of little-used brain circuits, the structural development of the brain in early developmental phases, as well as the preparation of a repertoire of reflexive or instinctive behaviors (Hobson 2009). Yet none of these functions are obviously linked to dreaming. An exception is protoconsciousness theory, in which REM sleep plays an important role in foetal development by providing a virtual world model even before the emergence of full-blown consciousness (Hobson 2009: 808) .

Numerous studies have investigated the contribution of sleep to memory consolidation, with different sleep stages promoting different types of memories (Diekelmann et al. 2009; Walker 2009). However, only a few studies have investigated the relationship between dream content and memory consolidation in sleep (for a review, see Nielsen & Stenstrom 2005). Dreams rarely involve episodic replay of waking memories (Fosse et al. 2003). The incorporation of memory sources seems to follow a specific temporal pattern in which recent memories are integrated with older but semantically related memories (Blagrove et al. 2011). Nielsen (2017) presents a model of how external and bodily stimuli on one hand and short- and long-term memories on the other hand form seemingly novel, complex, and dreamlike images at sleep onset; he proposes these microdreams shed light on the formation and sources of more complex dreams. There is also some evidence that dream imagery might be associated with memory consolidation and task performance after sleep, though this is preliminary (Wamsley & Stickgold 2009, 2010; Wamsley et al. 2010).

Prominent theories on the function of dreaming focus on bad dreams and nightmares. It has long been thought that dreaming contributes to emotional processing and that this is particularly obvious in the dreams of nightmare sufferers or in dreams following traumatic experiences (e.g., Hartmann 1998; Nielsen & Lara-Carrasco 2007; Levin & Nielsen 2009; Cartwright 2010; Perogamvros et al. 2013). Based on the high prevalence of negative emotions and threatening dream content, threat simulation theory suggests that the evolutionary function of dreaming lies in the simulation of ancestral threats and the rehearsal of threatening events and avoidance skills in dreams has an adaptive value by enhancing the individual’s chances of survival (see Revonsuo 2000; Valli 2008). A more recent proposal is social simulation theory, in which social imagery in dreams supports social cognition, bonds, and social skills. (Revonsuo et al. 2015).

An evolutionary perspective can also be fruitfully applied to specific aspects of dream phenomenology. According to the vigilance hypothesis , natural selection disfavored the occurrence of those types of sensations during sleep that would compromise vigilance (Symons 1993). Dream sounds, but also smells or pains might distract attention from the potentially dangerous surroundings of the sleeping subject, and the vigilance hypothesis predicts that they only rarely occur in dreams without causing awakening. By contrast, because most mammals sleep with their eyes closed and in an immobile position, vivid visual and movement hallucinations during sleep would not comprise vigilance and thus can occur in dreams without endangering the sleeping subject. Focusing on the stuff dreams are not made of might then be at least as important for understanding the function of dreaming as developing a positive account.

Finally, even if dreaming in general and specific types of dream content in particular were found to be strongly associated with specific cognitive functions, it would still be possible that dreams are mere epiphenomena of brain activity during sleep (Flanagan 1995, 2000). It is also possible that the function of dreams is not knowable (Springett 2019).

A particular problem for any theory on the function of dreaming is to explain why a majority of dreams are forgotten and how dreams can fulfill their putative function independently of recall. Crick and Mitchinson (1983) famously proposed that REM sleep “erases” or deletes surplus information and unnecessary memories, which would suggest that enhanced dream recall is counterproductive. Another problem is that dreaming can be lost selectively and independently of other cognitive deficits (Solms 1997, 2000).

Some of the problems that arise for theories on the functions of dreaming can be avoided if we do not assume that dreaming has a specific function, separate from the function(s) of conscious wakeful states. This depends on the broader taxonomy of dreaming in relation to wakeful states. For example, if dreaming is continuous with waking mind wandering, imagination, and/or own-body perception, we should not expect it to have a unique function, but rather to express a similar function as these wakeful states, perhaps to varying degrees. Nor should we expect dreams to have a single function; the functions of dreaming might be as varied and complex as those of consciousness, and given the complexity of the target phenomenon, the failure to pin down a single function should not be surprising (Windt 2015a).

Questions about dreaming in different areas of philosophy such as epistemology, ontology, philosophy of mind and cognitive science, and ethics are closely intertwined. Scientific evidence from sleep and dream research can meaningfully inform the philosophical discussion and has often done so in the past. The discussion of dreaming has also often functioned as a lens on broader questions about knowledge, morality, consciousness, and self. Long a marginalized area, the philosophy of dreaming and of sleep is central to important philosophical questions and increasingly plays an important role in interdisciplinary consciousness research, for example in the search for the neural correlates of conscious states, in conscious state taxonomies, and in research on the minimal conditions for phenomenal selfhood and conscious experience.

  • Aleman, A. and F. Larøi, 2008, Hallucinations: The Science of Idiosyncratic Perception , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • Andrillon, T., J. Windt, T. Silk, S. Drummond, M. Bellgrove, and N. Tsuchiya, 2019, “Does the mind wander when the brain takes a break? Local sleep in wakefulness, attentional lapses and mind-wandering”, Frontiers in Neuroscience , 13(949), doi:10.3389/fnins.2019.00949
  • Antrobus, J.S., 1990, “The Neurocognition of Sleep Mentation: Rapid Eye Movements, Visual Imagery, and Dreaming”, in Sleep and Cognition , R. Bootzin, J. Kihlstrom, and D. Schacter (eds.), Washington: American Psychological Association, pp. 3–24.
  • Aristotle, On Dreams , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • –––, On Prophecy in Sleep , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • –––, On Sleeping and Waking , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • Artemidorus, The Interpretation of Dreams , R.J. White (ed.), New Jersey: Noyes Press, 1975.
  • Aserinsky, E. and N. Kleitman, 1953, “Regularly Occurring Periods of Eye Motility and Concurrent Phenomena during Sleep”, Sleep Medicine Review , 118: 273–274.
  • –––, 1955, “Two Types of Ocular Motility Occurring in Sleep”, Journal of Applied Physiology , 8: 1–10.
  • Augustine, Against the Academics , J.J. O’Meara (ed.), Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1950.
  • –––, Confessions , H. Chadwick (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
  • Austin, J.L., 1962, Sense and Sensibilia , G.J. Warnock (ed.), Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Ayer, A.J., 1960, “Professor Malcolm on Dreams”, Journal of Philosophy , 57: 517–535.
  • Baillet, A., 1691, La Vie de Monsieur Descartes , Paris: La Table Ronde.
  • Baird, B., S. Mota-Rolim, and M. Dresler, 2019, “The cognitive neuroscience of lucid dreaming”, Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews , 100: 305–323.
  • Baldridge, B.J., 1966, “Physical Concomittants of Dreaming and the Effect of Stimulation on Dreams”, Ohio State Medical Journal , 62: 1272–1275.
  • Barbera, J., 2008, “Sleep and Dreaming in Greek and Roman Philosophy”, Sleep Medicine , 9: 906–910.
  • Barrett, D. and P. McNamara (eds.), 2007a, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 1: Biological Aspects , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • ––– (eds.), 2007b, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 2: Content, Recall, Personality Correlates , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • ––– (eds.), 2007c, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 3: Cultural and Theoretical Perspectives , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • Bayne, T.J. and E. Pacherie, 2005, “In Defence of the Doxastic Conception of Delusions”, Mind and Language , 20(2): 163–188.
  • Berger, R.J., 1963, “Experimental Modification of Dream Content by Meaningful Verbal Stimuli”, British Journal of Psychiatry , 109: 722–740.
  • Bergson, H., 1914, Dreams , E.E. Slosson (ed. and trans.), New York: B.W. Huebsch. [ Bergson 1914 available online ]
  • Berkeley, G., 1710, “A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge”, in Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues , H. Robinson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–96.
  • Binz, C., 1878, Über den Traum , Bonn: Adolph Marcus.
  • Blanke, O. and T. Metzinger, 2009, “Full-Body Illusions and Minimal Phenomenal Selfhood”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 13(1): 7–13.
  • Block, N., 2007, “Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh between Psychology and Neuroscience”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 30: 499–548.
  • Blumberg, M., 2010, “Beyond dreams: do sleep-related movements contribute to brain development?”, Frontiers in Neurology , 1(140), doi:10.3389/fneur.2010.00140
  • Blumberg, M., and A. Plumeau, 2016, “A new view of ‘dream enactment’ in REM sleep behavior disorder”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 30: 34–42.
  • Bortolotti, L., 2009, Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bostrom, N., 2003, “Are We Living in a Computer Simulation?”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 53(211): 243–255.
  • Bourdin, P., 1641, “Seventh Set of Objections”, reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 214–231.
  • Bradley, F.H., 1894, “The Failure of Movement in Dream”, Mind , 3(11): 373–377.
  • Breger, L., I. Hunter, and R.W. Lane, 1971, The Effect of Stress on Dreams , New York: International Universities Press.
  • Broughton, J., 2002, Descartes’s Method of Doubt , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2006, “Impressions and Ideas”, in The Blackwell Guide to Hume’s Treatise , S. Traiger (ed.), Malden, MA & Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 43–57.
  • Browne, A., 1977, “Descartes’s Dreams”, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes , 40: 256–273.
  • Bucci, A., and M. Grasso, 2017, “Sleep and dreaming in the predictive processing framework”, in T. Metzinger and W. Wiese (eds.), Philosophy and Predictive Processing (Volume 6), Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Canfield, J.V., 1961, “Judgments in Sleep”, The Philosophical Review , 70: 224–230.
  • Cartwright, R.D., 2010, The Twenty-four Hour Mind: The Role of Sleep and Dreaming in our Emotional Lives , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, D.J., 2005, “The Matrix as Metaphysics”, in Grau 2005: 132–176.
  • Chihara, C.S., 1965, “What Dreams Are Made On”, Theoria , 31: 145–158.
  • Chihara, C.S. and J.A. Fodor, 1965, “Operationalism and Ordinary Language: A Critique of Wittgenstein”, American Philosophical Quarterly 2: 281–295; page reference is to the reprint in Dunlop 1977.
  • Christoff, K., Z. Irving, K. Fox, R. Spreng, and J. Andrews-Hanna, 2016, “Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 17(11): 718–731.
  • Churchland, P.S., 1988, “Reduction and the Neurobiological Basis of Consciousness”, in Consciousness in Contemporary Science , A. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 273–304.
  • Clark, A., 2005, “The Twisted Matrix: Dream, Simulation, or Hybrid?”, in Grau 2005: 177–197.
  • –––, 2013a, “Dreaming the Whole Cat: Generative Models, Predictive Processing, and the Enactivist Conception of Perceptual Experience”, Mind , 121(483), 753–771.
  • –––, 2013b, “Whatever Next? Predictive Brains, Situated Agents, and the Future of Cognitive Science”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 36(03), 181–204.
  • Clarke, D.M., 2006, Descartes: A Biography , Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cohen, M.A. and D.C. Dennett, 2011, “Consciousness Cannot Be Separated from Function”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15(8), 358–364.
  • Cole, J.R., 1992, The Olympian Dreams and Youthful Rebellion of René Descartes , Urbana & Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
  • Conrad, T., 1968, Zur Wesenslehre des psychischen Lebens und Erlebens , (Phaenomenologica: Vol. 27), DenHaag: Nijhoff.
  • Crane, T. and C. French, 2017, “The Problem of Perception”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/perception-problem/ >.
  • Crick, F. and G. Mitchinson, 1983, “The Function of Dream Sleep”, Nature , 304, 111–114.
  • Crowther, T., 2018, “Experience, dreaming, and the phenomenology of wakeful consciousness”, in F. Dorsch, F. MacPherson, & M. Nida-Rumelin (eds.), Phenomenal Presence , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Currie, G., 2000, “Imagination, Delusion and Hallucination”, Mind & Language , 15(1), 168–183.
  • Currie, G. and I. Ravenscroft, 2002, Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • D’Agostino, A., A. Castelnovo, and S. Scarone, 2013, “Dreaming and the Neurobiology of Self: Recent Advances and Implications for Psychiatry”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00680 [ available online ]
  • Dang-Vu, T.T., M. Schabus, M. Desseilles, S. Schwartz, P. Maquet, 2007, “Neuroimaging of Sleep and Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007a: 95–114.
  • Dement, W.C., 1999, The Promise of Sleep. The Scientific Connection between Health, Happiness and a Good Night’s Sleep , London: Pan Books.
  • Dement, W.C. and N. Kleitman, 1957, “The Relation of Eye Movements during Sleep to Dream Activity: An Objective Method for the Study of Dreaming”, Journal of Experimental Psychology , 53: 89–97.
  • Dement, W.C. and E. Wolpert, 1958, “The Relation of Eye Movements, Body Motility, and External Stimuli to Dream Content”, Journal of Experimental Psychology , 55: 543–553.
  • Dennett, D.C., 1976, “Are dreams experiences?”, The Philosophical Review , 85(2): 151–171.
  • –––, 1979, “The Onus Re Experiences: A Reply to Emmett”, Philosophical Studies , 35(April): 315–318.
  • –––, 1991, Consciousness Explained . Boston, New York & London: Little, Brown and Company.
  • Descartes, R., 1637, Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting the Reason, and Seeking Truth in the Sciences ., G.B. Rawlings (ed.). [ Descartes 1637 available online ]
  • –––, 1641, Meditations on First Philosophy , reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 1–64.
  • Desseilles, M., T.T. Dang-Vu, V. Sterpenich, and S. Schwartz, 2011, “Cognitive and Emotional Processes during Dreaming: A Neuroimaging View”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 998–1008.
  • Diekelmann, S., I. Wilhelm, and J. Born, 2009, “The Whats and Whens of Sleep-Dependent Memory Consolidation”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 13(5): 309–321.
  • Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers , R.D. Hicks (ed.), Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1943.
  • Domhoff, G.W., 2001, “A New Neurocognitive Theory of Dreams”, Dreaming , 11: 13–33.
  • –––, 2003, The Scientific Study of Dreams: Neural Networks, Cognitive Development, and Content Analysis , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • –––, 2011, “The Neural Substrate for Dreaming: Is It a Subsystem of the Default Network?”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 1163–1174.
  • Dreisbach, C., 2000, “Dreams in the History of Philosophy”, Dreaming , 10(1): 31–41.
  • Dresler, M., S.P. Koch, R. Wehrle, V.I. Spoormaker, F. Holsboer, A. Steiger, P. Sämann, H. Obrig, and M. Czisch, 2011, “Dreamed Movement Elicits Activation in the Sensorimotor Cortex”, Current Biology , 21(21): 1833–1837.
  • Dresler, M., R. Wehrle, V.I. Spoormaker, S.P. Koch, F. Holsboer, A. Steiger, H. Obrig, P. Sämann, and M. Czisch, 2012, “Neural Correlates of Dream Lucidity Obtained from Contrasting Lucid versus Non-lucid REM Sleep: A Combined EEG/fMRI Case Study”, Sleep , 35(7): 1017–1020.
  • Driver, J., 2007, “Dream immorality”, Philosophy , 82(1): 5–22.
  • Dunlop, C.E.M. (ed.), 1977, Philosophical Essays on Dreaming . Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press.
  • Edwards, C.L., P.M. Ruby, J.E. Malinowski, P.D. Bennett, and M.T. Blagrove, 2013, “Dreaming and Insight”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00979 [ available online ]
  • Ellis, H., 1911, The World of Dreams , London: Constable & Company LTD.
  • Emmett, K., 1978, “Oneiric Experiences”, Philosophical Studies , 34(November): 445–450.
  • Erlacher, D., M. Schredl, and S. LaBerge, S., 2003, “Motor Area Activation during Dreamed Hand Clenching: A Pilot Study on EEG Alpha Band”, Sleep and Hypnosis , 5: 182–187.
  • Erlacher, D., M. Schädlich, T. Stumbrys, and M. Schredl, 2014, “Time for Actions in Lucid Dreams: Effects of Task Modality, Length, and Complexity”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01013 [ available online ]
  • Fazekas, P., and G. Nemeth, 2018, “Dream experiences and the neural correlates of perceptual consciousness and cognitive access”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B (Biological Sciences), 373(1755): 20170356.
  • Fazekas, P., G. Nemeth, and M. Overgaard, 2019, “White dreams are made of colours: What studying contentless dreams can teach about the neural basis of dreaming and conscious experiences”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 43: 84–91.
  • ffytche, D.H., 2007, “Visual Hallucinatory Syndromes: Past, Present, and Future”, Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience , 9(2): 173–189.
  • ffytche, D.H., J.D. Blom, and M. Catani, 2010, “Disorders of Visual Perception”, Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry , 81(11): 1280–1287.
  • Flanagan, O., 1995, “Deconstructing Dreams: The Spandrels of Sleep”, The Journal of Philosophy , 92: 5–27.
  • –––, 2000, Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind , Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Fletcher, P.C. and C.D. Frith, 2008, “Perceiving is Believing: A Bayesian Approach to Explaining the Positive Symptoms of Schizophrenia”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 10(1): 48–58.
  • Fosse, M.J., R. Fosse, J.A. Hobson, and R.J. Stickgold, 2003, “Dreaming and Episodic Memory: A Functional Dissociation?”, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 15: 1–9.
  • Foulkes, D., 1978, A Grammar of Dreams , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1993a, “Children’s Dreaming”, in Dreaming as Cognition , C. Cavallero and D. Foulkes (eds.), New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, pp. 114–132.
  • –––, 1993b, “Dreaming and REM Sleep”, Journal of Sleep Research , 2:199–202.
  • –––, 1999, Children’s Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness , Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.
  • Fox, K.C.R., S. Nijeboer, E. Solomonova, G.W. Domhoff, and K. Christoff, 2013, “Dreaming as Mind Wandering: Evidence from Functional Neuroimaging and First-Person Content Reports”, Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7, doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00412 [ available online ]
  • Frankfurt, H.G., 1970, Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes’s Meditations , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • Freud, S., 1899, Die Traumdeutung , Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag (2003).
  • –––, 1940, Schriften über Träume und Traumdeutungen , Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag (2003).
  • Galen, On Diagnosis in Dreams , L. Pearcy (ed.), < available online >.
  • Gerrans, P., 2012, “Dream Experience and a Revisionist Account of Delusions of Misidentification”, Consciousness and Cognition , 21(1): 217–227.
  • –––, 2013, “Delusional Attitudes and Default Thinking”, Mind & Language , 28(1): 83–102.
  • –––, 2014, “Pathologies of Hyperfamiliarity in Dreams, Delusions and Déjà Vu”, Frontiers in Psychology , 5, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00097 [ available online ]
  • Globus, G.G., 1987, Dream Life, Wake Life: The Human Condition Through Dreams , New York: State University of New York Press.
  • Goblot, 1896, “Sur le souvenir des rêves”, Revue philosophique , XLII .
  • Gottesmann, C., 2006, “The Dreaming Sleep Stage: A New Neurobiological Model of Schizophrenia?”, Neuroscience , 140: 1105–1115.
  • Grau, C. (ed.), 2005, Philosophers Explore the Matrix , C. Grau (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gregory, J.C., 1916, “Dreams as Psychical Explosions”, Mind , 25(98): 193–205.
  • –––, 1918, “The Dream of ‘Frustrated Effort’: A Suggested Explanation”, Mind , 27(105): 125–128.
  • Grundmann, T., 2002, “Die Struktur des skeptischen Traumarguments”, Grazer Philosophische Studien , 64: 57–81.
  • Hacking, I., 2001, “Dreams in Place”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 59(3):244–260.
  • Hall, C.S., 1981, “Do We Dream during Sleep? Evidence for the Globot Hypothesis”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 53(1): 239–246.
  • Hartmann, E., 1998, Dreams and Nightmares: The New Theory on the Origin and Meaning of Dreams , Cambridge: Perseus Books.
  • Hearne, K., 1978, Lucid Dreams: An Electro-Physiological and Psychological Study , (Ph.D. thesis), University of Liverpool, England. [ Hearne 1978 available online ]
  • Hering, J., 1947, “Concerning Image, Idea, and Dream”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 8(2): 188–205.
  • Hobbes, T., 1651, Leviathan , C.B. Macpherson (ed.), London: Penguin (1985).
  • –––, 1641, “Third Set of Objections”, reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 107–124.
  • Hobson, J.A., 1988, The Dreaming Brain , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1999, Dreaming as Delirium. How the Brain Goes Out of Its Mind , Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2009, “REM Sleep and Dreaming: Towards a Theory of Protoconsciousness”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 10(November): 803–813.
  • Hobson, J. and K. Friston, 2012, “Waking and Dreaming Consciousness: Neurobiological and Functional Considerations”, Progress in Neurobiology , 98(1): 82–98.
  • Hobson, J., E.F. Pace-Schott, and R. Stickgold, 2000, “Dreaming and the Brain. Toward a Cognitive Neuroscience of Conscious States”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 793–842.
  • Hobson, J. and H. Wohl, 2005, From Angels to Neurones. Art and the New Science of Dreaming , Parma: Mattioli 1885.
  • Hodges, M. and W.R. Carter, 1969, “Nelson on Dreaming a Pain”, Philosophical Studies , 20(3): 43–46.
  • Hoelscher, T.J., E. Klinger, and S.G. Barta, 1981, “Incorporation of Concern- and Nonconcern-related Verbal Stimuli into Dream Content”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology , 90: 88–91.
  • Hohwy, J., 2013, The Predictive Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Horikawa, T., M. Tamaki, Y. Miyawaki, and Y. Kamitani, 2013, “Neural Decoding of Visual Imagery during Sleep”, Science 340 (6132): 639–642.
  • Hoss, R.J., 2010, “Content Analysis on the Potential Significance of Color in Dreams: A Preliminary Investigation”, International Journal of Dream Research , 3(1): 80–90.
  • Hume, D., 1739, A Treatise of Human Nature , D.F. Norton, M.J. Norton (eds.), Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press (2000).
  • Hunter, J. F. M., 1983, “The difference between dreaming and being awake”, Mind , 92(365): 80–93.
  • Hurlburt, R.T. and E. Schwitzgebel, 2007, Describing Inner Experience?: Proponent Meets Skeptic , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Husserl, E., 1904/1905, Phantasie und Bildbewußtsein , E. Marbach (ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner (2006).
  • Ichikawa, J., 2008, “Scepticism and the Imagination Model of Dreaming”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 58(232): 519–527.
  • –––, 2009, “Dreaming and Imagination”, Mind & Language , 24(1): 103–121.
  • James, W., 1890, The Principles of Psychology , Volume Two, New York: Dover Publications (1950).
  • Jouvet, M., 1999, The Paradox of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming , L. Garey (ed.), Cambridge & London: MIT Press.
  • Kahn, D., E.F. Pace-Schott, and J.A. Hobson, 2002, “Emotion and Cognition: Feeling and Character Identification in Dreaming”, Consciousness and Cognition , 11: 34–50.
  • Kahn, D., R. Stickgold, E.F. Pace-Schott, and J.A. Hobson, 2000, “Dreaming and Waking Consciousness: A Character Recognition Study”, Journal of Sleep Research , 9: 317–325.
  • Kant, I., 1766 [2002], Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik , Stuttgart: Reclam.
  • Kantor, J., 1970, “Pinching and Dreaming”, Philosophical Studies , 21(1–2): 28–32.
  • Keefer, M.H., 1996, “The Dreamer’s Path: Descartes and the Sixteenth Century”, Renaissance Quarterly , 49(1): 30–76.
  • Kind, A., 2013, “The heterogeneity of the imagination”, Erkenntnis , 78(1): 141–159.
  • Klein, P., 2015, “Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/skepticism/ >.
  • Koppehele-Gossel, J., A. Klimke, K. Schermelleh-Engel, and U. Voss, 2016, “A template model of embodiment while dreaming: Proposal of a mini-me.” Consciousness and Cognition , 46: 148–162.
  • Koulack, D., 1969, “Effects of Somatosensory Stimulation on Dream Content”, Archives of General Psychiatry , (20): 718–725.
  • Kramer, M., 2007, The Dream Experience: A Systematic Exploration , New York & London: Routledge.
  • Kroker, K., 2007, The Sleep of Others and the Transformations of Sleep Research , Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
  • LaBerge, S., 2007, “Lucid Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007a: 307–328.
  • LaBerge, S., L.E. Nagel, W.C. Dement, and V.P. Zarcone, 1981, “Lucid Dreaming Verified by Volitional Communication during REM Sleep”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 52: 727–732.
  • LaBerge, S., B. Baird, and P. Zimbardo, 2018, “Smooth tracking of visual targets distinguishes lucid REM sleep dreaming and waking perception from imagination”, Nature Communications , 9(1), doi:10.1038/s41467-018-05547-0
  • Leclair-Visonneau, L., D. Oudiette, B. Gaymard, S. Leu-Semenescu, and I. Arnulf, 2010, “Do the Eyes Scan Dream Images during Rapid Eye Movement Sleep? Evidence from the Rapid Eye Movement Sleep Behaviour Disorder Model”, Brain , 133(6): 1737–1746.
  • Leibniz, G.W., 1880, Die Philosophischen Schriften , Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.
  • –––, Philosophical Papers and Letters , L.E. Loemker (ed.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956.
  • Levin, R. and T.A. Nielsen, 2009, “Nightmares, Bad Dreams, and Emotions Dysregulation: A Review and New Neurocognitive Model of Dreaming”, Current Directions in Psychological Science , 18(2): 84–88.
  • Lewis, H.D., 1969, The Elusive Mind , London: George Allan & Unwin LTD.
  • Liao, Shen-yi and Gendler, Tamar, “Imagination”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/imagination/ >.
  • Limosani, I., A. D’Agostino, M.L. Manzone, and S. Scarone, 2011a, “The Dreaming Brain/Mind, Consciousness and Psychosis”, Consciousness & Cognition , 20(4): 987–992.
  • –––, 2011b, “Bizarreness in Dream Reports and Waking Fantasies of Psychotic, Schizophrenic and Manic Patients: Empirical Evidences and Theoretical Consequences”, Psychiatry Research , 189(2): 195–199.
  • Llinás, R. and D. Paré, 1991, “Of Dreaming and Wakefulness”, Neuroscience , 44: 521–535.
  • Llinás, R. and U. Ribary, 1994, “Perception as an Oneiric-like State Modulated by the Senses”, in Large-Scale Neuronal Theories of the Brain , C. Koch and J. Davis (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 111–124.
  • Locke, J., 1689, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , R. Woolhouse (ed.), London: Penguin (1997).
  • Macnish, R., 1838, The Philosophy of Sleep , Glasgow: W.R. M’Phun.
  • Macpherson, F., 2013, “The Philosophy and Psychology of Hallucination: An Introduction”, in Hallucination. Philosophy and Psychology , F. Macpherson and D. Platchias (eds.), Cambridge MA: MIT Press, pp. 1–38.
  • Malcolm, N., 1956, “Dreaming and Skepticism”, The Philosophical Review , 65(1): 14–37.
  • –––, 1959, Dreaming , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Matthews, G.B., 1981, “On Being Immoral in a Dream”, Philosophy , 56(January): 47–64.
  • –––, 2005, Augustine , Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub.
  • Maury, L.-F. A., 1861, Le sommeil et les rêves: études psychologiques sur ces phénomènes et les divers états qui s’y rattachent , Paris: Didier et Cie Libraires-Éditeurs.
  • McGinn, C., 2004, Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning , Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2005a, “The Matrix of Dreams”, in Grau 2005: 62–70.
  • –––, 2005b, The Power of Movies: How Screen and Mind Interact , New York: Vintage Books.
  • Metzinger, T., 2003, Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2009, The Ego Tunnel: The Science of the Mind and the Myth of the Self , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 2013a, “The Myth of Cognitive Agency: Subpersonal Thinking as a Cyclically Recurring Loss of Mental Autonomy”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00931 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2013b, “Why Are Dreams Interesting for Philosophers? The Example of Minimal Phenomenal Selfhood, Plus an Agenda for Future Research”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00746 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015, “M-autonomy”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 22(11–12): 270–302.
  • Montaigne, M. de, “The Apology for Raymond Sebond”, in Readings in the History of Philosophy , R.M. Popkin (ed.), The Philosophy of the 16th and 17th Centuries , Toronto: Collier-Macmillan (1966): 70–81.
  • Moriarty, M. (ed.), 2008, Meditations, Objections, and Replies , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Mullane, H., 1965, “Moral Responsibility for Dreams”, Dialogue , 4(02): 224–229.
  • –––, 1966, “Dreaming as an Action”, Dialogue , 5(02): 239–242.
  • Murzyn, E., 2008, “Do We Only Dream in Colour? A Comparison of Reported Dream Colour in Younger and Older Adults with Different Experiences of Black and White Media”, Consciousness and Cognition , 17: 1228–1237.
  • Nagel, T., 1959, “Dreaming”, Analysis , 19(5): 112–116.
  • –––, 1974, “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?”, Philosophical Review , 83: 435–450.
  • Nelson, J.O., 1966, “Can One Tell that He is Awake by Pinching Himself?”, Philosophical Studies , 17(6): 81–84.
  • Nemeth, G., and P. Fazekas, 2018, “Beyond the REM--NREM Dichotomy: A Multidimensional Approach to Understanding Dreaming”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 25(11–12): 13–33.
  • Newman, L., 2019, “Descartes’ Epistemology”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/descartes-epistemology/ >.
  • Nielsen, T.A., 2000, “A Review of Mentation in REM and NREM Sleep: ‘Covert’ REM Sleep as a Possible Reconciliation of Two Opposing Models”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23(6): 851–866.
  • –––, 2010, “Dream Analysis and Classification: The Reality Simulation Perspective”, in Principles and Practice of Sleep Medicine , M. Kryger, T. Roth, and W.C. Dement (eds.), New York: Elsevier, pp. 595–603.
  • –––, 2017, “Microdream neurophenomenology”, Neuroscience of Consciousness , 1: nix001; doi:10.1093/nc/nix001
  • Nielsen, T.A. and J. Lara-Carrasco, 2007, “Nightmares, Dreaming, and Emotion Regulation: A Review”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007b: 253–284.
  • Nielsen, T.A. and P. Stenstrom, 2005, “What Are the Memory Sources of Dreaming?”, Nature , 437(7063): 1286–1289.
  • Nielsen, T.A., L. Ouellet, and A.L. Zadra, 1995, “Pressure Stimulation during REM Sleep Alters Dream Limb Activity and Body Bizarreness”, Sleep Research , 24: 134.
  • Nielsen, T.A., C. Svob, and D. Kuiken, 2009, “Dream-Enacting Behaviors in a Normal Population”, Sleep , 32(12): 1629–1636.
  • Nir, Y. and G. Tononi, 2010, “Dreaming and the Brain: From Phenomenology to Neurophysiology”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 14(2): 88–100.
  • Noë, A., 2004, Action in Perception , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Noreika, V., K. Valli, H. Lahtela, and A. Revonsuo. “Early-night serial awakenings as a new paradigm for studies on NREM dreaming”, International Journal of Psychophysiology , 74(1): 14–18.
  • O’Shaughnessy, B., 2002, “Dreaming”, Inquiry , 45: 399–432.
  • Pace-Schott, E.F., 2007, “The Frontal Lobes and Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007b: 115–154.
  • –––, 2013, “Dreaming as a Story-Telling Instinct”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00159 [ available online ]
  • Pagel, J.F., M. Blagrove, R. Levin, B. States, B. Stickgold, and S. White, 2001, “Definitions of Dream: A Paradigm for Comparing Field Descriptive Specific Studies of Dream”, Dreaming , 11: 195–202.
  • Pantani, M., A. Tagini, and A. Raffone, 2018, “Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness and self across waking and dreaming: bridging phenomenology and neuroscience”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(1): 175–197.
  • Perogamvros, L., T.T. Dang-Vu, M. Desseilles, S. Schwartz, 2013, “Sleep and Dreaming Are for Important Matters”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00474 [ available online ]
  • Plato, Phaedrus , B. Jowett (ed.), in The Internet Classics Archive , available online .
  • –––, Theaetetus , B. Jowett (ed.), in The Internet Classics Archive , available online .
  • Prasad, H.S., 2000, “Dreamless Sleep and Soul: a controversy between Vedānta and Buddhism”, Asian Philosophy , 10(1): 61–73. doi:10.1080/09552360050001770
  • Putnam, H., 1981, “Brains in a Vat”, in Reason, Truth and History , H. Putnam (ed.), Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–21.
  • –––, 1962 [1986], “Dreaming and ‘Depth Grammar’”, in Analytical Philosophy First Series , R. Butler (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell & Mott; page reference is to the reprint in H. Putnam (ed.), 1986, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2.: Mind, Language and Reality , Cambridge: University Press, pp. 304–324.
  • Rechtschaffen, A. and C. Buchignani, 1992, “The Visual Appearance of Dreams”, in The Neuropsychology of Sleep and Dreaming , J.S. Antrobus and M. Bertini (eds.), Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 143–156.
  • Reed, T.M., 1979, “Dreams, Scepticism and Waking Life”, in Body, Mind, and Method. Essays in Honor of Virgil C. Aldrich , D.F. Gustafson and B.L. Tapscott (eds.), Dodrecht & Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 37–64.
  • Resnick, J., R. Stickgold, C.D. Rittenhouse, and J.A. Hobson, 1994, “Self-Representation and Bizarreness in Children’s Dream Reports Collected in the Home Setting”, Consciousness and Cognition , 3: 30–45.
  • Revonsuo, A., 2000, “The Reinterpretation of Dreams: An Evolutionary Hypothesis of the Function of Dreaming”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 877–901.
  • –––, 2005, “The Self in Dreams”, in The Lost Self. Pathologies of the Brain and Identity , T.E. Feinberg and J.P. Keenan (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 206–219.
  • –––, 2006, Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Revonsuo, A. and C. Salmivalli, 1995, “A Content Analysis of Bizarre Elements in Dreams”, Dreaming , 5:169–187.
  • Revonsuo, A. and K. Tarkko, 2002, “Binding in Dreams. The Bizarreness of Dream Images and the Unity of Consciousness”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 9: 3–24.
  • Revonsuo, A., J. Tuominen, and K. Valli, 2015, “The Avatars in the Machine – Dreaming as a Simulation of Social Reality”, in T. Metzinger and J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Rosen, M.G., 2013, “What I Make up when I Wake up: Anti-Experience Views and Narrative Fabrication of Dreams”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00514 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015, “I’m thinking your thoughts while I sleep: Sense of agency and ownership over dream thought”, Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice , 2(3): 326–339.
  • –––, 2018a, “Enactive or inactive? Cranially envatted dream experience and the extended conscious mind”, Philosophical Explorations , 21(2): 295–318.
  • –––, 2018b, “How bizarre? A pluralist approach to dream content”, Consciousness and Cognition , 62: 148–162.
  • –––, forthcoming, “Dreaming of a stable world: vision and action in sleep”, first online 22 February 2019 Synthese , doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02149-1
  • Rosen, M.G. and J. Sutton, 2013, “Self-Representation and Perspectives in Dreams”, Philosophy Compass , 8(11): 1041–1053.
  • Russell, B., 1914, Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy , London & New York: Routledge (2009).
  • –––, 1948, Human Knowledge: It’s Scope and Limits , London & New York: Routledge (2009).
  • Ryle, G., 1949, The Concept of Mind , Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
  • Sartre, J.-P., 1940, L’imaginaire: Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination , Paris: Gallimard, 2005.
  • Sauvageau, A., T.A. Nielsen, and J. Montplaisir, 1998, “Effects of Somatosensory Stimulation on Dream Content in Gymnasts and Control Participants: Evidence of Vestibulomotor Adaptation in REM Sleep”, Dreaming , 8: 125–134.
  • Scarone, S., M.L. Manzone, O. Gambini, I. Kantzas, I. Limosani, A. D’Agostino, and J.A. Hobson, 2007, “The Dream as a Model for Psychosis: An Experimental Approach Using Bizarreness as a Cognitive Marker”, Schizophrenia Bulletin , 34(3): 515–522.
  • Schenck, C.H. 2005, Paradox Lost: Midnight in the Battleground of Sleep and Dreams , Minneapolis: Extreme Nights, LLC.
  • Schenck, C.H. and M.W. Mahowald, 1996, “REM Sleep Parasomnias”, Neurological Clinics , 14: 697–720.
  • Scherner, K.A., 1861, Das Leben des Traumes , Berlin: Verlag von Heinrich Schindler.
  • Schooler, J.W., J. Smallwood, K. Christoff, T.C. Handy, E.D. Reichle, and M.A. Sayette, 2011, “Meta-awareness, Perceptual Decoupling and the Wandering Mind”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15(7): 319–326.
  • Schopenhauer, A., 1847, Kleinere Schriften , Zürich: Haffmans Verlag (1988).
  • Schredl, M., 2006, “Factors Affecting the Continuity between Waking and Dreaming: Emotional Intensity and Emotional Tone of the Waking-Life Event”, Sleep and Hypnosis , 8: 1–5.
  • –––, 2010, “History of Dream Research: The Dissertation ‘Entstehung der Träume (Origin of Dreams)’ of Wilhelm Weygandt Published in 1893”, International Journal of Dream Research , 3(1): 95–97.
  • Schredl, M. and F. Hofmann, 2003, “Continuity between Waking Activities and Dream Activities”, Consciousness and Cognition , 12: 298–308.
  • Schredl, M., A. Fuchedzhieva, H. Hämig, and V. Schindele, 2008, “Do We Think Dreams Are in Black and White Due to Memory Problems?”, Dreaming , 18(3): 175–180.
  • Schröder, S., 1997, “The Concept of Dreaming: On Three Theses by Malcolm”, Philosophical Investigations , 20(1): 15–38.
  • Schwitzgebel, E., 2002, “Why Did We Think We Dreamed in Black and White?”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 649–660.
  • –––, 2003, “Do People Still Report Dreaming in Black and White? An Attempt to Replicate a Questionnaire from 1942”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 96: 25–29.
  • –––, 2011, Perplexities of Consciousness , Cambridge & London: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2017, “1% Skepticism”, Noûs , 51(2): 271–290.
  • Schwitzgebel, E., C. Huang, and Y. Zhou, 2006, “Do We Dream in Color? Cultural Variations and Skepticism”, Dreaming , 16(1): 36–42.
  • Searle, J., 2000, “Consciousness”, Annual Review of Neuroscience , 23: 557–578.
  • Sebastián, M., 2014a, “Dreams: An Empirical Way to Settle the Discussion between Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Theories of Consciousness”, Synthese , 191(2): 263–285.
  • –––, 2014b, “Not a HOT dream”, In Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience, Springer, Dordrecht, pp. 415–432.
  • Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism , R.G. Bury (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1987).
  • Siclari, F., and G. Tononi, 2017, “Local aspects of sleep and wakefulness”, Current Opinion in Neurobiology , 44: 222–227.
  • Siclari, F., J. LaRocque, B. Postle, and G. Tononi, 2013, “Assessing sleep consciousness within subjects using a serial awakening paradigm”, Frontiers in psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00542
  • Siclari, F., B. Baird, L. Perogamvros, G. Bernardi, J. LaRocque, B. Riedner, M. Boly, B. Postle, and G. Tononi, 2017, “The neural correlates of dreaming”, Nature Neuroscience , 20(6): 872.
  • Siegler, F.A., 1967, “Remembering Dreams”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 17: 14–24.
  • Silberer, H., 1919, Der Traum: Einführung in die Traumpsychologie , Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.
  • Singer, E.A., 1924, “On Pain in Dreams”, The Journal of Philosophy , 21(22): 589–601.
  • Smallwood, J. and J.W. Schooler, 2015, “The science of mind wandering: empirically navigating the stream of consciousness”, Annual review of psychology , 66: 487–518.
  • Smith, A.D., 2002, The Problem of Perception , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Solms, M., 1997, The Neuropsychology of Dreams: A Clinico-Anatomical Study , Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
  • –––, 2000, “Dreaming and REM Sleep Are Controlled by Different Brain Mechanisms”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 843–850.
  • Sosa, E., 2007, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge , Volume I, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Soteriou, M., forthcoming, “Dreams, agency, and judgement”, Synthese , first online 20 July 2017, doi: 10.1007/s11229-017-1496-7
  • Springett, B., 2019, “Can we know about the evolution of dreaming?”, Dreaming , 29(3): 220.
  • Stickgold, R. and M.P. Walker (eds.), 2009, The Neuroscience of Sleep , London, Burlington MA, San Diego: Elsevier: Academic Press.
  • Stone, J., 1984, “Dreaming and Certainty”, Philosophical Studies , 45(May): 353–368.
  • Stroud, B., 1984, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Stumbrys, T., D. Erlacher, and M. Schredl, 2013, “Testing the involvement of the prefrontal cortex in lucid dreaming: a tDCS study”, Consciousness and Cognition , 22(4): 1214–1222.
  • Stumbrys, T., D. Erlacher, M. Johnson, and M. Schredl, M., 2014, “The Phenomenology of Lucid Dreaming: An Online Survey”, American Journal of Psychology , 127(2): 191–204.
  • Symons, D., 1993, “The Stuff that Dreams Aren’t Made of: Why Wake-State and Dream-State Sensory Experiences Differ”, Cognition , 47(3): 181–217.
  • Thomas, N., 2014, “The multidimensional spectrum of imagination: Images, dreams, hallucinations, and active, imaginative perception”, Humanities 3(2): 132–184.
  • Thompson, E., 2014, Waking, dreaming, being: Self and consciousness in neuroscience, meditation, and philosophy , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 2015, “Dreamless Sleep, the Embodied Mind, and Consciousness – The Relevance of a Classical Indian Debate to Cognitive Science”, in T. Metzinger and J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Tononi, G., 2008, “Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto”, Biological Bulletin , 215: 216–242.
  • Uslar, D. von, 1964, Der Traum als Welt: Untersuchungen zur Ontologie und Phänomenologie des Traums , Pfullingen: Neske.
  • Valberg, J.J., 2007, Dream, Death, and the Self , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • Valli, K., 2008, Threat Simulation: The Function of Dreaming? , doctoral thesis, Turku: Annales Universitatis Turkuensis.
  • van de Castle, R.L., 1994, Our Dreaming Mind , New York: Ballantine Books.
  • van Eeden, F., 1913, “A Study of Dreams”, Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research , 26: 431–461.
  • Vold, J.M., 1910/1912, Über den Traum , Vol. I and II, edited by O. Klemm, Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth.
  • Voss, U., R. Holzmann, I. Tuin, and J.A. Hobson, 2009, “Lucid Dreaming: A State of Consciousness with Features of Both Waking and Non-Lucid Dreaming”, Sleep , 32(9): 1191–1200.
  • Voss, U., K. Schermelleh-Engel, J. Windt, C. Frenzel, and A. Hobson, 2013, “Measuring consciousness in dreams: the lucidity and consciousness in dreams scale”, Consciousness and Cognition , 22(1): 8–21.
  • Voss, U. and A. Hobson, 2015, “What is the state-of-the-art on lucid dreaming? – Recent advances and questions for future research”, in T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt a. MIND Group.
  • Voss, U., R. Holzmann, A. Hobson, W. Paulus, J. Koppehele-Gossel, A. Klimke, and M. Nitsche, 2014, “Induction of self awareness in dreams through frontal low current stimulation of gamma activity”, Nature Neuroscience , 17(6): 810.
  • Walker, M.P., 2009, “Sleep-Dependent Memory Processing”, in Stickgold and Walker 2009: 230–240.
  • Wamsley, E.J., 2013, “Dreaming, Waking Conscious Experience, and the Resting Brain: Report of Subjective Experience as a Tool in the Cognitive Neurosciences”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00637 [ available online ]
  • Wamsley, E.J. and R. Stickgold, 2009, “Incorporation of Waking Events into Dreams”, in Stickgold and Walker 2009: 330–336.
  • –––, 2010, “Dreaming and Offline Memory Processing”, Current Biology , 20(23): R1010–1013.
  • Wamsley, E.J., M. Tucker, J.D. Payne, J.A. Benavides, and R. Stickgold, 2010, “Dreaming of a Learning Task Is Associated with Enhanced Sleep-Dependent Memory Consolidation”, Current Biology , 20(9): 850–855.
  • Wamsley, E., C. Donjacour, T. Scammell, G. Lammers, and R. Stickgold, 2014, “Delusional confusion of dreaming and reality in narcolepsy”, Sleep , 37(2): 419–422.
  • Waxman, W., 1994, Hume’s Theory of Consciousness , Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Weygandt, W., 1893, Entstehung der Träume , Leipzig: Grübel & Sommerlatte.
  • Williams, B., 1978, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry , Middlesex: Pelican Books.
  • Windt, J.M., 2010, “The Immersive Spatiotemporal Hallucination Model of Dreaming”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , 9: 295–316.
  • –––, 2011, “Altered Consciousness in Philosophy”, in Altering Consciousness. Multidisciplinary Perspectives, Volume 1: History, Culture, and the Humanities , E. Cardeña and M. Winkelman (eds.), Santa Barbera, Denver & Oxford: Praeger, pp. 229–254.
  • –––, 2013, “Reporting Dream Experience: Why (Not) to Be Skeptical about Dream Reports”, Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7, doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00708 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015a, Dreaming: A Conceptual Framework for Philosophy of Mind and Empirical Research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2015b, “Just in time – dreamless sleep experience as pure subjective temporality”, in T. Metzinger & J.M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • –––, 2018, “Predictive brains, dreaming selves, sleeping bodies: how the analysis of dream movement can inform a theory of self-and world-simulation in dreams”, Synthese , 195(6): 2577–2625.
  • Windt, J.M. and T. Metzinger, 2007, “The Philosophy of Dreaming and Self-Consciousness: What Happens to the Experiential Subject during the Dream State?”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007c: 193–248.
  • Windt, J.M. and V. Noreika, 2011, “How to Integrate Dreaming into a General Theory of Consciousness—A Critical Review of Existing Positions and Suggestions for Future Research”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 1091–1107.
  • Windt, J.M., and U. Voss, 2018, “Spontaneous thought, insight, and control in lucid dreams”, in The Oxford Handbook of Spontaneous Thought: Mind-Wandering, Creativity, and Dreaming , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 385–410.
  • Windt, J.M., T. Nielsen, and E. Thompson, 2016, “Does consciousness disappear in dreamless sleep?”, Trends in cognitive sciences , 20(12): 871–882.
  • Wittgenstein, L., 1953, Philosophical Investigations , G.E.M. Anscombe (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 1967, Zettel , G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright (eds.), Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Wundt, W.M., 1896, Grundriss der Psychologie , Leipzig: Engelman; page reference is to the excerpt translated by C.H. Judd, reprinted in R.L. Woods and H.B. Greenhouse (eds.), The New World of Dreams , New York: Macmilllan (1974), pp. 179–180.
  • Zeidman, P., and E. Maguire, 2016, “Anterior hippocampus: the anatomy of perception, imagination and episodic memory”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 17(3): 173.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Philosophy of Dreaming , entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  • Dreams , PhilPapers collection.
  • Dreams and Skepticism , PhilPapers collection.

belief | Berkeley, George | delusion | Descartes, René: epistemology | imagination | Locke, John | perception: the problem of | personal identity | personal identity: and ethics | Plato: on knowledge in the Theaetetus | sense data | skepticism | skepticism: and content externalism

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Regina Fabry and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and constructive criticism on an earlier version of this manuscript. And as always, I am greatly indebted to Stefan Pitz for his support.

Copyright © 2019 by Jennifer M. Windt < jennifer . windt @ monash . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Front Psychol

Freud's Dream Interpretation: A Different Perspective Based on the Self-Organization Theory of Dreaming

The self-organization theory of dreaming proposes that the sleeping brain is a self-organizing system that can combine discontinuous and incongruous neuronal signals (i.e., different elements of dreams) into a relatively continuous narrative during sleep (Kahn and Hobson, 1993 ; Kahn et al., 2000 , 2002 ). This theory also implies that dreams are not independently functional but rather a coproduct of the sleeping brain, reflecting the dreamer's physiological and psychological activities such as memory consolidation, emotion regulation, and reception of external stimuli (Zhang, 2016 ).

By contrast, Freud regarded dreams as a royal road to the unconscious; dream interpretation has thus been an important psychoanalytic technique. His theory of dreams mainly refers to two key points: (a) what are the materials of a dream? and (b) how do these materials work together? The answers to these questions are closely related to an understanding of dream interpretation. In this article, we refer to the self-organization theory of dreaming and seek to elucidate its meaning for dream interpretation.

What are the materials of a dream?

According to Freud ( 1900 ), sources of dreams include stimuli from the external world, subjective experiences, organic stimuli within the body, and mental activities during sleep (p. 22). Empirical evidence has supported some of these assertions. The self-organization theory of dreaming posits that memory consolidation, emotion regulation, and reception of external stimuli can contribute to dream content (Zhang, 2016 ); hence, dream content can contain important information about the dreamer.

Consider, for example, the case of memory consolidation during sleep: according to the two-stage memory model (McClelland et al., 1995 ; Stickgold and Walker, 2005 ; Born and Wilhelm, 2012 ), the process of memory consolidation generates memory fragments to extract pertinent information when an individual is asleep. Moreover, salient memories for the sleeper, such as newly encoded memories (Born and Wilhelm, 2012 ; Wamsley, 2014 ), memories that will be incorporated into long-term memory within 6–7 days (e.g., Blagrove et al., 2011 ; van Rijn et al., 2015 ), and corresponding long-term memories (Lewis and Durrant, 2011 ), are preferentially activated and then manifested in dream content. In addition, rapid eye movement (REM) sleep and non-REM (NREM) sleep refer to the processing of different types of memories: REM sleep is primarily implicated in emotional memory and implicit memory, whereas NREM sleep is more closely associated with declarative memory (Rauchs et al., 2005 ; Smith, 2010 ). From this perspective, newly encoded memories are related to what Freud ( 1900 ) called the “day's residues” in that they reflect some daytime activities of the dreamer. Temporarily stored memories, denoted as the “dream-lag effect,” offer another window into a patient's recent life. Long-term memory is correlated with remote events, implying that dream content may harken back to early experiences (e.g., childhood trauma). Remote memory may even involve information collected over the course of evolution and reflected in typical dream themes, such as flying and being chased (e.g., Revonsuo, 2000 ; Valli and Revonsuo, 2009 ; Mathes et al., 2014 ; Yu, 2016 ). Moreover, many psychoanalysts have emphasized emotional memories in dream content. Freud ( 1900 ) found that affect remains stable in the process of dream formation, at least with respect to quality (p. 460–487). Affect or emotion can be a gateway to learning more about the state of the dreamer. “The principle of affective organization of memory” suggests that the memory network is organized by affect (see Reiser, 2001 ); accordingly, a therapist may be able to identify a patient's similar affective memories (e.g., traumatic experiences) via emotional material in dream content.

The focus on transference dreams and countertransference dreams in contemporary psychoanalysis aligns with this point. Unconscious communications between the patient and analyst may be reflected in dream content as either the day's residues or a major emotional focus. As such, the therapist can perceive and address interaction issues in treatment (e.g., transference, resistance, countertransference, and counterresistance) based on these dreams (e.g., Hill et al., 2014 ; Sirois, 2016 ; Ogden, 2017 ). To understand and use dreams in this way implies a focus on manifest rather than latent dream content. However, the self-organization theory of dreaming does not endorse the existence of latent dream content (see the following section), although many analysts have expressed interest in manifest dream since the 1950s (see Spanijaard, 1969 ; Lane, 1997 ). Even Freud came to realize the significance of such content and suggested considering it seriously at the end of his life (Jiménez, 2012 ).

Some researchers have contended that manifest dream content represents the whole dream, with no element of distortion or disguise. For example, Kavanagh ( 1994 ) advocated eschewing Freudian latent content and instead proposed that manifest content constitutes “real” dreams. Greenberg and Pearlman ( 1999 ) proposed that if psychoanalysts understand how manifest dream content attempts to convey the dreamer's problems and resolve them, then a dream can be expressed directly rather than through an obscured purpose. Jennings ( 2007 ) purported that dreams are self-evident in that they directly reflect the dreamer's experiences, traits, and wishes. From this perspective, the therapist should use the self-evident method to discover dreams as they truly are in therapy. That is, even if no hidden implications exist, dreams can still be a tool by which the therapist and patient can work together to enrich the therapeutic process. Nevertheless, Freud paid close attention to how these materials combine, and his technique of dream interpretation also relied on this integration, which brings us to our second point.

How do the materials of a dream work together?

Freud ( 1900 ) realized that dream content is derived from but not identical to real life; thus, he suggested that some transformation and connection must exist between these materials. He contended that these connections are not random but rather constrained by one's unconscious desires, such that “a dream is the fulfillment of a wish” (p. 122). He also found that “disagreeable” dreams seem more widespread than “pleasant” dreams (p. 134), hence his hypothesis that dreams can disguise their true purpose (i.e., indirectly fulfilling wishes). Freud therefore identified two types of dreams: manifest dream and latent dream. He stated that the latent dream is the real dream, and the goal of dream interpretation is to reveal it.

To further elaborate on this idea, Freud proposed four mechanisms by which latent dream can be obscured. Condensation refers to the reduction and simplification of rich contents of latent dream. Displacement refers to a process that substitutes various aspects (e.g., constituents, intensity, significance, and properties) of manifest and latent dream to render them dissimilar. Symbols indicate that latent dream is expressed by relevant signs. Secondary revision involves making disordered and incoherent dream materials more well-organized and reasonable. This mechanism causes a dream to appear meaningful, but the presented dream is in fact quite different from its actual implication (Freud, 1900 ).

The self-organization theory of dreaming does not concur with this viewpoint; instead, it offers a different perspective on Freud's dream-work. According to this theory, the nature of condensation is the fragmentation of memories during consolidation, as this process must extract important information for further processing. Displacement, from this perspective, depends on weak control of the sleeping brain and the high degree of freedom in dream elements. In this state, the brain develops new connections between different elements; then, the self-organization mechanism combines various elements to construct a relatively concordant “story,” deemed secondary revision per Freud's theory. No analogous symbols exist in dream content because the elements presented therein are merely memory fragments and other components of information processing (see Zhang, 2016 ). Some researchers have also pointed out that dream symbols are too far-fetched (see Freud, 1916 ). In other words, dreams are not riddles to be translated (Hartmann, 2010a ), and “the manifest dream is the real dream” (Jiménez, 2012 ); thus, Freud's dream-work does not exist according to this point of view.

However, this position does not mean that the self-organization mechanism does not provide support for dream interpretation. According to self-organization theory, the sleeping brain's control of physical and mental activities is weaker than in the awake brain (Kahn et al., 2000 , 2002 ). Thus, dream elements are characterized by more freedom than mental content when an individual is awake, rendering hyperassociativity between these components possible (Hartmann, 2010b ; Horton and Malinowski, 2015 ). This is why dreams can present bizarre scenes and “miracles” that cannot happen in real life (Zhang, 2016 ). Nevertheless, this “disordered state” is not unlimited; it could impair brain function otherwise. Therefore, the self-organization mechanism is necessary: it provides a relatively stable state for the dreaming brain, as it can offer a way in which the system can give rise to ordered behavior, structure, or pattern from disorder (Haken, 1977 ; Prigogine and Stengers, 1984 ; Fingelkurts et al., 2013 ). Order parameters or collective variables are crucial during this process.

A system's state is generally determined based on many variables that describe its different aspects. Under certain conditions, the interactions between different components will cause the system to reach a critical state at which most of these variables vanish quickly. To put it another way, few variables survive, but those that do reflect the state of this system. These variables (i.e., order parameters or collective variables) also serve as an invisible hand that controls the operation and evolution of the system, leading to the emergence of a new ordered pattern or behavior. The formation of order parameters is therefore the key channel through which self-organization can successfully continue (see Haken, 1977 ; Fingelkurts et al., 2013 ).

Emotion is a pivotal factor during sleep. Several investigations have revealed that dreams are often accompanied by emotions, especially negative ones (e.g., Valli et al., 2008 ; Malinowski and Horton, 2014 ). Many researchers have identified a close relationship between dreams and emotions (e.g., Desseilles et al., 2011 ), even labeling emotions indispensable to dream formation. For instance, Reiser ( 1997 ) noted that images serving as nodal points in an individual's memory network are connected by similar types of affect, indicating that affect plays an essential role in memory organization. Reiser ( 1997 ) further conjectured that strong affect during sleep evokes existing images that are loaded with similar affect and hence activate relevant earlier experiences to form a dream. Clément ( 2008 ) hypothesized the following chain of processes: emotions in sleep are activated and combine to form different emotional scripts, which then serve as templates and replicate a series of images to finally construct a dream narrative. Hartmann ( 2010b ) stated that combinations of dream elements are not random but rather guided by emotion; accordingly, dreams are helpful for building and rebuilding an individual's emotional memory system. In brief, emotions likely play the role of order parameters: they control and guide combinations of dream elements. Emotions can therefore serve as a springboard in comprehending dreams. For instance, perhaps traumatic experiences constitute a core theme of a patient's dreams, suggesting an avenue for further treatment.

The self-organization theory of dreaming offers a framework distinct from psychoanalytic theories to explain how dreams are generated and operate. This theory proposes that dreams are a byproduct of the dreamer's physical and mental state during sleep, distinguishes between manifest and latent dream, and points out that the dream-work proposed by Freud is actually a result of information processing and self-organization in the sleeping brain. However, this theory allows the therapist to derive important information (e.g., significant memories) from dream content and underscores emotions as a potential order parameter that can provide an effective means of grasping the core of a dream. Therefore, dream analysis may still prove useful in the therapeutic process.

Author contributions

WZ is responsible for the writing of this paper. BG is in charge of the idea.

Conflict of interest statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

This research was supported by funding from Postgraduate Research & Practice Innovation Program of Jiangsu Province (KYCX18_1239). We would like to express our thanks to the reviewer for his valuable comments.

  • Blagrove M., Fouquet N. C., Henley-Einion J. A., Pace-Schott E. F., Davies A. C., Neuschaffer J. L., et al.. (2011). Assessing the dream-lag effect for REM and NREM stage 2 dreams . 6 :e26708. 10.1371/journal.pone.0026708 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Born J., Wilhelm I. (2012). System consolidation of memory during sleep . Psychol. Res. 76 , 192–203. 10.1007/s00426-011-0335-6 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Clément P. (2008). Dream imagery as a result of emotions matching with images . Imag. Cogn. Pers. 27 , 245–257. 10.2190/IC.27.3.d [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Desseilles M., Dang-Vu T. T., Sterpenich V., Schwartz S. (2011). Cognitive and emotional processes during dreaming: a neuroimaging view . Conscious. Cogn. 20 , 998–1008. 10.1016/j.concog.2010.10.005 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fingelkurts A. A., Fingelkurts A. A., Neves C. F. H. (2013). Consciousness as a phenomenon in the operational architectonics of brain organization: criticality and self-organization considerations . Chaos Solitons Fract. 55 , 13–31. 10.1016/j.chaos.2013.02.007 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Freud S. (1900). The interpretation of dreams , in The Standard Edition of the Complete Works of Sigmund Freud , Vol. 4 , 5, ed Strachey J. (London: Hogarth Press; ). [ Google Scholar ]
  • Freud S. (1916). Introductory lectures on psycho-analysis , in The Standard Edition of the Complete Works of Sigmund Freud , Vol. 15 , ed Strachey J. (London: Hogarth Press; ). [ Google Scholar ]
  • Greenberg R., Pearlman C. A. (1999). The interpretation of dreams: a classic revisited . Psychoanal. Dialogues 9 , 749–765. 10.1080/10481889909539359 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Haken H. (1977). Synergetics . Phys. B 9 , 412–414. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Hartmann E. (2010a). Meteorite or gemstone? Dreaming as one end of a continuum of functioning: implications for research and for the use of dreams in therapy and self-knowledge . Dreaming 20 , 149–168. 10.1037/a0020575 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Hartmann E. (2010b). The dream always makes new connections: the dream is a creation, not a replay . Sleep Med. Clin. 5 , 241–248. 10.1016/j.jsmc.2010.01.009 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Hill C. E., Knox S., Crook-Lyon R. E., Hess S. A., Miles J., Spangler P. T., et al.. (2014). Dreaming of you: client and therapist dreams about each other during psychodynamic psychotherapy . Psychother. Res. 24 , 523–537. 10.1080/10503307.2013.867461 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Horton C. L., Malinowski J. E. (2015). Autobiographical memory and hyperassociativity in the dreaming brain: implications for memory consolidation in sleep . Front. Psychol. 6 :874. 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00874 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Jennings J. L. (2007). Dreams without disguise: the self-evident nature of dreams . Humanist Psychol. 35 , 253–274. 10.1080/08873260701415413 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Jiménez J. P. (2012). The manifest dream is the real dream: the changing relationship between theory and practice in the interpretation of dreams , in The Significance of Dreams: Bridging Clinical and Extraclinical Research in Psychoanalysis , eds Fonagy P., Kächele H., Leuzinger-Bohleber M., Taylor D. (London: Karnac Books; ), 31–48. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kahn D., Combs A., Krippner S. (2002). Dreaming as a function of chaos-like stochastic processes in the self-organizing brain . Nonlinear Dyn. Psychol. 6 , 311–322. 10.1023/A:1019758527338 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kahn D., Hobson J. A. (1993). Self-organization theory of dreaming . Dreaming 3 , 151–178. 10.1037/h0094378 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kahn D., Krippner S., Combs A. (2000). Dreaming and the self-organizing brain . J. Conscious. Stud. 7 , 4–11. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kavanagh G. (1994). The patient's dreams of the analyst . Contemp. Psychoanal. 30 , 500–509. 10.1080/00107530.1994.10746869 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lane R. C. (1997). Dream controversies . Psychother. Private Pract. 16 , 39–68. 10.1300/J294v16n01_04 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lewis P. A., Durrant S. J. (2011). Overlapping memory replay during sleep builds cognitive schemata . Trends Cogn. Sci. 15 , 343–351. 10.1016/j.tics.2011.06.004 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Malinowski J., Horton C. L. (2014). Evidence for the preferential incorporation of emotional waking-life experiences into dreams . Dreaming 24 , 18–31. 10.1037/a0036017 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mathes J., Schredl M., Göritz A. S. (2014). Frequency of typical dream themes in most recent dreams: an online study . Dreaming 24 , 57–66. 10.1037/a0035857 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • McClelland J. L., McNaughton B. L., O'Reilly R. C. (1995). Why there are complementary learning systems in the hippocampus and neocortex: insights from the successes and failures of connectionist models of learning and memory . Psychol. Rev. 102 , 419–457. 10.1037/0033-295X.102.3.419 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Ogden T. H. (2017). Dreaming the analytic session: a clinical essay . Psychoanal. Q. 86 , 1–20. 10.1002/psaq.12124 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Prigogine I., Stengers I. (1984). Order Out of Chaos: Man's New Dialogue with Nature . New York, NY: Bantam books. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Rauchs G., Desgranges B., Foret J., Eustache F. (2005). The relationships between memory systems and sleep stages . J. Sleep Res. 14 , 123–140. 10.1111/j.1365-2869.2005.00450.x [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Reiser M. F. (1997). The art and science of dream interpretation: Isakower revisited . J. Am. Psychoanal. Assoc. 45 , 891–905. 10.1177/00030651970450030901 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Reiser M. F. (2001). The dream in contemporary psychiatry . Am. J. Psychiatr. 158 , 351–359. 10.1176/appi.ajp.158.3.351 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Revonsuo A. (2000). The reinterpretation of dreams: an evolutionary hypothesis of the function of dreaming . Behav. Brain Sci. 23 , 793–1121. 10.1017/S0140525X00004015 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Sirois F. (2016). Analytic process and dreaming about analysis . Int. J. Psychoanal. 97 , 1479–1497. 10.1111/1745-8315.12529 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Smith C. (2010). Sleep states, memory processing, and dreams . Sleep Med. Clin. 5 , 217–228. 10.1016/j.jsmc.2010.01.002 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Spanijaard J. (1969). The manifest dream content and its significance for the interpretation of dreams . Int. J. Psychoanal. 50 , 221–235. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Stickgold R., Walker M. P. (2005). Memory consolidation and reconsolidation: what is the role of sleep? Trends Neurosci. 28 , 408–415. 10.1016/j.tins.2005.06.004 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Valli K., Revonsuo A. (2009). The threat simulation theory in light of recent empirical evidence: a review . Am. J. Psychol. 122 , 17–38. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Valli K., Strandholm T., Sillanmäki L., Revonsuo A. (2008). Dreams are more negative than real life: implications for the function of dreaming . Cogn. Emot. 22 , 833–861. 10.1080/02699930701541591 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • van Rijn E., Eichenlaub J. B., Lewis P. A., Walker M. P., Gaskell M. G., Malinowski J. E., et al. (2015). The dream-lag effect: selective processing of personally significant events during Rapid Eye Movement sleep, but not during Slow Wave Sleep . Neurobiol. Learn. Mem. 122 , 98–109. 10.1016/j.nlm.2015.01.009 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Wamsley E. J. (2014). Dreaming and offline memory consolidation . Curr. Neurol. Neurosci. 14 , 1–7. 10.1007/s11910-013-0433-5 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Yu C. K. (2016). Classification of typical dream themes and implications for dream interpretation . Neuropsychoanalysis 18 , 133–146. 10.1080/15294145.2016.1236701 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Zhang W. (2016). A supplement to self-organization theory of dreaming . Front. Psychol. 7 :332. 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.00332 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Entertainment
  • Environment
  • Information Science and Technology
  • Social Issues

Home Essay Samples Life

Essay Samples on Dream

Explaining why dreams and goals are valuable.

Human existence is marked by an innate yearning for progress, fulfillment, and purpose. At the core of this drive lies the pursuit of dreams and goals, powerful constructs that transcend cultures, backgrounds, and ages. In this essay, we delve into the profound value of dreams...

A Glimpse into Life 10 Years From Now

The pace of technological advancement and societal transformation is accelerating at an unprecedented rate. As we stand on the threshold of a new decade, it is intriguing to speculate about the world that awaits us a decade from now. This essay takes a journey into...

Turning My Dream to Become an Enterpreneur to Reality

My dream to become an entrepreneur is a journey fueled by ambition, creativity, and a desire to make a lasting impact on the world. In this essay, I will share my aspirations to become an entrepreneur, the steps I'm taking to turn this dream into...

If I Had a Million Dollars: Dreams and Possibilities

If I had a million dollars, my mind would be a canvas painted with dreams and aspirations waiting to be realized. While money cannot buy happiness, it can certainly open doors to experiences, opportunities, and contributions that align with my values and passions. This essay...

My Passion for Becoming a Registered Nurse

Career planning is essential because it allows a person to explore diverse aspects affecting their progress. This analysis aims to explore the job description, education and certification requirement, employment opportunities, and professional tasks inherent to registered nurses. An individual’s career path determines their associated job...

  • Dream Career

Stressed out with your paper?

Consider using writing assistance:

  • 100% unique papers
  • 3 hrs deadline option

Following Dreams: With Special Reference To Paulo Coelho’s The Alchemist

Dreams are aspirations that reflect a human’s wants and desires in life. Living one’s dreams add more meaning to life. It helps to achieve the impossible and helps to know that failure is a part of success. Dedication and hard work are the two things...

  • The Alchemist

Illusion vs Reality it "The Great Gatsby" and Other Literature

Everyday people create false reality and live in the world they want. Sometime people try to become what they want to be just by create a huge scam or false reality. They deceive themselves and others just to discover that they are drowning in reality....

  • The Great Gatsby

Passion And Dream Vs. Reality In The Face Of Apple

When selecting a career, many seek jobs that are gratifying and enjoyable so they will not be complaining to go to work everyday. In spite of the fact that making money in order to support oneself is exceptionally imperative, the want to induce up within...

Jungian Psychology And Dream Analysis Applied To The Movie Sleep Dealer

The most basic fact about films is that they are created and written basing on some studies of facts that exist in life. A movie like the sleep dealer can be explained by the use of psychology. Some of the approaches that have been adopted...

My Personal Struggles with Financial Need as a Student

I am honored to say that I will become the first in my family to graduate from a Four-Year University, at the beginning of my educational path everything I have experienced till now seemed impossible, but If someone is truly determined and committed to their...

What I Would Spend Lottery Money On

Everyone has probably heard the phrase ’money does not buy happiness’ by now. However, this assertion is not often true. A longitudinal study by Gardner and Oswald of lottery winners and a control group without any wins revealed that the winners had more markers for...

The Pact and Ways to Fulfill a Dream

The book I have chosen for the book analysis is “The Pact: Three Young Men Make A Promise And Fulfill A Dream” by Dr. Sampson Davis, George Jenkins, Rameck Hunt, and Lisa Frazier Page. This book is about three young African American doctors that grew...

Why I Want to Be a Neonatal Nurse

“I’m pregnant,” my mom whispered to me one evening over dinner. I sat there speechless, trying to process what I had just heard. ”What?' “What do mean my life will change forever?” “ Is this really happening?” “Why me?” All of these things screamed inside...

  • Why I Want To Be A Nurse

Waking Up from a Wishful Dream in Inception

In this movie, the main characters are played by Dominick Cobb (Dom), Arthur, Ariadne, Saito, Eames, Mal, Browning, Yusuf, Robert Fisher and his son Robert Fisher. Dom and Arthur, they perform the role of corporate spying utilizing test military innovation to penetrate the subconscious of...

Analysis of Separate Scenes and Narratives in Inception

Inception is a Sci-fi/ Thriller movie that came out July thirteenth in the summer of 2010. It had a total of 156 wins and 207 nominations; including Oscar’s for Best Achievement in Cinematography, Sound Mixing, Editing, Visual Effects as well as BAFTA awards for Best...

The Dreams and Illusions in the Glass Castle

We all have dreams, but reality always seem to get in the way. In the novel, The Glass Castle by Jeannette Walls. Rex Walls, the father of Jeannette is a drunk and is struggling to keep a job. Their whole goal is to keep food...

  • The Glass Castle

In Cold Blood Analysis: Pursuing Dreams and Failing to Obtain Them

What makes someone act out? In Truman Capote’s In Cold Blood, the main characters, Dick Hickock and Perry Smith, are young men who feel like outcasts in society. They brutally kill the Clutter family in the small town of Holcomb, Kansas to fulfill their dream...

  • In Cold Blood

Believing in Myself and My Dreams

I was always told to follow my dreams, or ill spend my life working for someone who did. My childhood, like many others started out with an aspiration to become rich and famous. As I grew older I began to see the different in my...

  • Believe in Myself

Never Give Up On Your Dreams

Once upon a time in the middle of winter, when the sky was overcast with shadows and ground was covered with snow, there lived a girl who was very fond of theatre. She took a theater class in her childhood, but she has remembered every...

  • Never Give Up

Never Give Up: Why People Sould Not Stop Pursuing Their Dreams

The writer Paulo Cohelo once said, “Never give up on a dream. Just try to see the signs that take you to them”. Every person in this world has a dream that they would love to reach. We make resolutions every New Year, but people...

The Misery of Pointless Dreams in A Wall of Fire Rising

I love watching phenomena in little kids that they feel like they need a certain toy or the universe will explode. Their whole world revolves around that one thing. But, once they get that toy, it’s no longer fun to them. Their joy fades away,...

  • A Wall of Fire Rising

Defining Myself and My Dream Through Passion

Passion for me is that sense of enjoyment and satisfaction after meeting my objectives and defying all the odds against me. Every single sportsman—or woman—will say the same thing: I have to use my body and mind in harmony to reach my passions. I thrive...

The ‘Misleading’ Concept Of Good, Bad And Heroism

I am going to start this composition by saying that i used to dream to become a hero when i was a child. It is because i grew up in an environment that everyone of us want to be a hero. We used to watched...

A Seed That Turns Into A Dream

Ever since I could remember, my grandfather would complain about how he sold his small chunk of land in Bakersfield, California. “We could have retired off that land!” He says every Sunday dinner to my grandma. In a sense, he is right. Bakersfield, among other...

  • Personal Life

Analysis Of My Dreams Using Freud's Interpretations

Everyone dreams, mostly when they reach rapid eye movement sleep, even though most people cannot remember their dreams. Even if they remember, most people forget their dreams within five minutes of waking up. Dreaming is still an ongoing study with many unknowns. Oneirology is defined...

  • Psychoanalysis
  • Sigmund Freud

Aristotle's View On Seeping And Dreams

Sleep is a state of unconsciousness where the primary sense-organ such as seeing, hearing, smelling stops functioning. Unlike deafness or blindness, sleep is a natural state of a living organism (human and animal). According to David Gallop (writer), he states that sleeping is a privation...

Best topics on Dream

1. Explaining Why Dreams and Goals Are Valuable

2. A Glimpse into Life 10 Years From Now

3. Turning My Dream to Become an Enterpreneur to Reality

4. If I Had a Million Dollars: Dreams and Possibilities

5. My Passion for Becoming a Registered Nurse

6. Following Dreams: With Special Reference To Paulo Coelho’s The Alchemist

7. Illusion vs Reality it “The Great Gatsby” and Other Literature

8. Passion And Dream Vs. Reality In The Face Of Apple

9. Jungian Psychology And Dream Analysis Applied To The Movie Sleep Dealer

10. My Personal Struggles with Financial Need as a Student

11. What I Would Spend Lottery Money On

12. The Pact and Ways to Fulfill a Dream

13. Why I Want to Be a Neonatal Nurse

14. Waking Up from a Wishful Dream in Inception

15. Analysis of Separate Scenes and Narratives in Inception

  • Perseverance
  • Personal Experience
  • Personality
  • Bad Memories

Need writing help?

You can always rely on us no matter what type of paper you need

*No hidden charges

100% Unique Essays

Absolutely Confidential

Money Back Guarantee

By clicking “Send Essay”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement. We will occasionally send you account related emails

You can also get a UNIQUE essay on this or any other topic

Thank you! We’ll contact you as soon as possible.

Becoming Minimalist

Own less. Live more.

How to Fulfill Dreams

Written by joshua becker · 80 Comments

“ Keep your dreams alive. Understand to achieve anything requires faith and belief in yourself, vision, hard work, determination, and dedication. Remember all things are possible for those who believe. ” – Gail Devers

This past week (February 22) marked the one year anniversary of our e-book’s launch. Over the past year, Simplify. 7 Guiding Principles to Anyone Declutter Their Home and Life has sold over 2,600 copies and it continues to sell every single day. Its launch was truly a life-changing experience.

And it continues to be the evidence of a dream fulfilled.

For nearly 35 years of my life, I wanted to write a book… to be an author. Selfishly, I wanted the pride that I associated with having my name written on a book’s cover. Unselfishly, I wanted to provide valuable inspiration to others… in a form that could far outlive me.

And given the fact that I wanted to write a book that people actually read, Simplify has indeed become the tangible realization of a lifelong dream. Actually, this past year has been defined by the fulfillment of a number of lifelong dreams:

  • Dream: Spend more time with my family. Accomplished by finding minimalism.
  • Dream: Write a book. Accomplished in February, 2010. Again in August, 2010.
  • Dream: Run a marathon. Finished in May, 2010 . Time: 4:31.
  • Dream: Save Financial Emergency Fund: Accomplished in November, 2010.

I’ve discovered over the past year that dreams come in all shapes and sizes. But their fulfillment is almost always found in the same 7 steps…

1. Select a dream to fulfill. Some of us have so many dreams swirling in our minds, we don’t know where to start… while others of us are unable to put our finger on even one. Whether the decision be to write a book, run a marathon, buy a home, or find true love, fulfillment always starts with the intentional identification of one single goal and the heartfelt conviction to accomplish it. Take some time. Pick one. And then, set out to accomplish it.

2. Believe it is achievable. Unfortunately, too many people will never accomplish their dreams because they simply refuse to believe in themselves. Optimism is absolutely required for dream fulfillment and life enjoyment. If you don’t have natural self-confidence, make finding it your first dream to accomplish. I suggest, “ A Helpful Guide to How to Be More Confident ” If you do have self-confidence, begin to specifically direct it towards your chosen goal.

3. Ask for help. People have gone before you. Learn as much as you can from them. When I decided to run a marathon, I read How to Run Your First Marathon and talked to my co-worker Carole almost every single week. When I decided to write an ebook, I talked to Jeramiah (technology), Martha (editing), and Jana (title/outline). Each had information that I needed and played a significant role in helping me accomplish my dreams. Don’t let your pride be the one obstacle that keeps you from them. Instead, humble yourself and ask for help.

4. Adjust your life as necessary. By definition, if you have not accomplished your dream yet, you’ll need to adjust your lifestyle to accomplish it. And while some of the adjustments may be major, they always start small:

  • Running a marathon starts with running one mile.
  • Writing a book starts with deciding on a subject.
  • Clearing your home of clutter starts with cleaning one drawer, closet, or room.
  • Losing 50 pounds starts with changing one meal.
  • Buying a home starts with saving one dollar.

Fulfilling your dreams will require you to change your lifestyle – one small step at a time. And while there may be a large number of steps to take, the good news is that the first one is completely achievable… and so is the second…

5. Set a deadline. Deadlines force our hand and call us to action. Therefore, it is absolutely essential to pick a realistic timeline and get moving. Buy a home in the next 3 years. Fix your marriage in the next year. Lose 20 pounds in the next 6 months. Or start a blog in the next 30 days. Find a calendar, a red marker, and a day. Go ahead, circle it. After all, a dream without a deadline is just a wish.

6. Tell others. I have found limitless encouragement by sharing my dreams with others. The number of people cheering for me automatically doubles. Soon, it triples. Suddenly, I’m not just trying to let myself down, but I’m trying to not let my friends down as well. And the cost of failure has just increased.

7. Stay focused. By nature, dreams will require perseverance. There will be successes and failures along the way. Those who persevere through the failures will accomplish their dreams. Those who give up will return to step #1. And if you’ve gotten this far, why would you want to start over? Instead of allowing failures to kill your dreams, use them to refocus you and your resolve.

On a side note, I realize all too well that the circumstances of life ebb and flow. I humbly recognize that the positive circumstances of my life this past year have allowed these dreams to be accomplished. One major illness, accident, or misstep could have derailed any of them listed above. If you currently find the circumstances of life derailing you from reaching your dreams, let me encourage you. Don’t lose hope. Just redirect your dreams.

In the comment section, I’d be interested to hear if you can specifically identify with any of these seven steps. Are their goals in your life that you are working to accomplish? If so, what are they? And which of the steps above are you currently working towards?

July 2, 2024 at 4:13 AM

Excellent write-up. Thank you so much.

March 14, 2024 at 10:49 AM

Keep dreaming big and anything is possible if you put your mind to it.Don’t let the devil tell you lies all things are possible with God.Dont be so hard on yourself.

January 2, 2024 at 10:19 AM

Guidelines are so clear but in my case I want and dream of putting up a bakery from small to huge bakery I have experience having worked as an accountant in a very big bakery in Zambia and at one time I ran my own bakery successfully for three years but I was renting both the equipment and the premises and when renewal time for for rentals came the landlord had already decided to venture into the business and refused to renew my tenancy agreement. The problem in Zambia where I am is financing even viable projects to knowledgable people even with a proven track record. I have tried asking financial institutions to purchase equipment for me, insure it in the financier’s name and open an account to be monitored jointly with the financier to no avail so the dream is hanging by the thread.

December 8, 2023 at 5:23 AM

My dream is to be a doctor a very good doctor I have BSC in medical technology but I want to upgrade my self to be a doctor is my dream but the big problem is money I have no money to start up my education also a have a lot of responsibilities already registered class starts up on April but i have no money I don’t know what to do how to get this money for my education …to be a doctor is my dream my big dream I want someone to help me to achieve my dream but I can’t find one I want to finish my education but I don’t know where to start what do I do to achieve my dream ..my parents also want me to start but I don’t have money what can I do

July 11, 2023 at 11:30 PM

Your article encourage me to more focus on my dream. Above 7 steps guide me how to achieve our dream without losing hope. I am trying to get a On-site job in IT department (Technical). I have short time to search my dream job because I got my Visa and need to move there as early as possible. Because my life partner is waiting for me and my daughter to stay with him but country is costly so we need to be financially strong and also complete dream job. So given me some points which will help me a lot. I will use those steps and will try to reach towards my dream job. Thank you

January 28, 2023 at 3:28 PM

I am a music producer and also want to fullfil my dream to be good Artist but there is a big problem that i live in a big joint family with my parents & i am the only earning person for my family, now my parents wants from me, get arranged marriage as soon as possible but i don’t want this, i want to live my life solo with my dream & even if i try to understand them that i dont want to be marry , they don’t care, no matter how hard i try, they just want to give me new responsibility to me, to show the society that they are good the parents, now i have only one option left to left the home & parents but my heart says don’t because my parents are old & they did alot for myself, now wgat i have to do

January 17, 2023 at 11:04 PM

My dream is to practice dentistry in USA. I am a dentist. I will do anything to achieve my dream. I wish my life partner is as ambitious as me and he will be a dentist as well. I wish i fulfill my dream 🥺

December 19, 2022 at 9:01 AM

The more I dream big the more I worry. I am so confuse wheather dream and goal in life caused us over worriness and do nothing about it.

December 19, 2022 at 8:55 AM

The more I dream big the more I worry. I am so confuse wheather dream and goal in life caused us over worry and do nothing about it.

December 3, 2022 at 11:55 AM

I want to fulfill my dreams help me please 🙏😭

February 15, 2022 at 7:26 PM

I’ve always had dreams to become a successful recording artist. But I’ve had these obstacles in my life, and honestly, I feel like giving up.

But this article was meant for me to read it. And the universe affirms that. Thank you.

January 6, 2021 at 11:56 AM

I want to be like Bill gates and always dream to be like him but when I think about it, it looks so hard as it is impossible or something that can be achievable by luck only and then I lose hope. I don’t know how to become such a man that can do anything that nobody else can and that’s the point where my mind stops thinking about what to do or how to do it?

May 4, 2021 at 11:36 AM

Just believe in yourself because it is so difficult to be like someone. May be you can be more than him.

May 6, 2021 at 12:19 AM

This word really inspired me alot… You’re right, It is hard when we’re trying to be like someone else, we should be ourselves and we can make more than them instead of having same like him…

Thanks and regards

December 23, 2020 at 6:19 AM

This site is meaningful,Very impressive and I got a reason to make meaningful mandatory tasks like: like 2nd marriage for children, losing weight, flat belly, touring the country on bike, becoming a contractor, building a beautiful home and earning more respect in my eyes as well others.etc.

I think, we can do little things nicely to achieve big goals

Thanks a lot …!

December 8, 2020 at 11:25 AM

My dream is actually to be k-pop start or singer, unfortunately 50% of this world parent’s never support there children and so as it is my parent’s only want me to concentrate on my studies only, but i am top student still i want that dream i always pray almost every single day. I think i will be one day !!

May 6, 2021 at 12:26 AM

Every parents look ahead for their children’s future… If you want to be a singer or k-pop hard work for use your time for it… And believe yourself that you’re a singer then its easy for you to find a way for it, and full fill your dream

November 12, 2020 at 12:10 PM

My dream is to become a singer. I’m wavering though. I wasn’t confident enough and thought that there are so many people who are talented than me. I used to think “what if I fail?” “What would i do i won’t be able to become a singer” “my life would be wasted then” but now I think its possible. I’m confident on my talent and I’m ready to do anything to achieve it. But sometimes I’m scared and want to give up.

May 6, 2020 at 3:39 AM

every new morning have new chance live your life as last chance Fullfill your dreams like joy enjoy your day every minute change your confident in your goal ?

December 23, 2020 at 6:24 AM

Good sayings. .. What’s your short and long term dreams?

February 20, 2020 at 4:25 AM

This page definitely has all the information I wanted concerning this subject and didn’t know who to ask.

January 15, 2020 at 5:37 PM

Thanks for finally talking about >How to Fulfill Dreams <Loved it!

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed .

ONE MILLION READERS CAN’T BE WRONG

Sign up to receive these posts delivered directly to your inbox for free.

© 2024 Joshua Becker · Design by Brian Gardner · Archives · Search · Privacy

  • Sign up and Get Listed

Outside of US & canada

Be found at the exact moment they are searching. Sign up and Get Listed

  • For Professionals
  • Worksheets/Resources

Find a Therapist

  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Marriage Counselor
  • Find a Child Counselor
  • Find a Support Group
  • Find a Psychologist
  • If You Are in Crisis
  • Self-Esteem
  • Sex Addiction
  • Relationships
  • Child and Adolescent Issues
  • Eating Disorders
  • How to Find the Right Therapist
  • Explore Therapy
  • Issues Treated
  • Modes of Therapy
  • Types of Therapy
  • Famous Psychologists
  • Psychotropic Medication
  • What Is Therapy?
  • How to Help a Loved One
  • How Much Does Therapy Cost?
  • How to Become a Therapist
  • Signs of Healthy Therapy
  • Warning Signs in Therapy
  • The GoodTherapy Blog
  • PsychPedia A-Z
  • Dear GoodTherapy
  • Share Your Story
  • Therapy News
  • Marketing Your Therapy Website
  • Private Practice Checklist
  • Private Practice Business Plan
  • Practice Management Software for Therapists
  • Rules and Ethics of Online Therapy for Therapists
  • CE Courses for Therapists
  • HIPAA Basics for Therapists
  • How to Send Appointment Reminders that Work
  • More Professional Resources
  • List Your Practice
  • List a Treatment Center
  • Earn CE Credit Hours
  • Student Membership
  • Online Continuing Education
  • Marketing Webinars
  • GoodTherapy’s Vision
  • Partner or Advertise

dream fulfillment essay

  • Learn About Therapy >
  • Types of Therapy >

Dream Analysis

A man's wishes circle his head in the form of images

Mental health professionals may also utilize dream analysis as part of therapeutic frameworks such as Jungian , Gestalt , cognitive behavioral , and art therapies .

The Use of Dream Analysis in Therapy

History of dream analysis in therapy, dream analysis in contemporary therapy, addressing mental health issues with dream analysis, limitations of dream analysis.

Most theoretical models use the basic tenets of dream analysis in the same way: A person in therapy relates a dream to the therapist, discussion and processing follows, and new information is gleaned from the dream. At the conclusion of the process, the therapist can help the person apply the new information in a useful way. Although these similarities exist, each therapy model applies dream analysis in different ways.

Psychoanalysis: In psychoanalytic theory, dreams represent wish fulfillment, unconscious desires, and conflicts. Dreams contain both manifest and latent content. Manifest content includes information from the dream as the dreamer remembers it. Latent content represents the repressed, symbolic meaning embedded within the dream. During dream analysis, the person in therapy shares the manifest content of the dream with the therapist.  After specific symbols are pulled from the manifest content, the therapist utilizes free association to facilitate the exploration of repressed material.

Jungian analysis: Jungian analysis is similar to Freud's psychoanalysis in that dreams are probed for unconscious material and symbols are explored for hidden meaning. However, in Jungian dream analysis, the dreamer is more crucial in unlocking the dream's message. Additionally, dreams are seen as attempts to express and create rather than efforts to repress and disguise, as in Freud's theory. Jungian dream analysis is based on Jung's belief that unless the interpretation resonates with the dreamer, the interpretation is not helpful.

In addition to the free association method described above, Jungian analysis also utilizes a technique called amplification. Amplification is based on the assumption that humanity shares a collective unconscious, or a set of inherited universal experiences. In this technique, collectively agreed-upon associations are explored. For example, if the person in therapy dreams about a dog, the therapist will encourage the exploration and research of universally understood information about dogs (dogs are affectionate, man's best friend, dogs in mythology, and so on). Amplification goes beyond using just the individual's associations; it explores the collective understanding of the symbol to help the individual find meaning in the dream.

Gestalt therapy: Dreamwork in Gestalt therapy is implemented somewhat differently than in psychoanalysis and Jungian analysis. Gestalt therapists believe that dreams are existential messages we send to ourselves. These messages are actively explored to bring dream content into a person's actual life.

A major technique used in Gestalt dream analysis is the “Take the Part of” technique. In this process, the therapist asks the person to write down everything remembered about the dream. The person is then asked to act out each “part” of the dream, creating a dialogue between the parts. For example, if a man dreams about a hooded figure standing in his garden, the therapist might tell the man to ask the figure questions. He might ask, “What are you doing in my garden?” and then answer, playing the part of the figure, “I am here to protect your loved ones.” This back-and-forth playing of parts helps people in therapy clarify feelings from all angles.

Existential art therapy: In this approach, dreams are explored through an existential lens. The therapist acts as a witness as the person in therapy attempts a journey of self-discovery. Dream images are explored, interacted with, and analyzed through art. The existential art therapist encourages those in therapy through their attempts to find meaning from the imagery, providing support but avoiding making interpretations for the individual.

Dreams have intrigued the human race for thousands of years. In ancient times, the Babylonians and Egyptians believed dreams were prophetic and held heavenly meaning. Aristotle interpreted dreams as psychological phenomena and viewed them as the life of one's soul while asleep. In the middle of the 19 th century, the first scientifically-based dream research took place, but it was not until Freud published The Interpretation of Dreams in 1900 that dream analysis widely developed. His was the first established theory that incorporated dreams within the context of the helping relationship. Jung adapted Freud's theory, proposing that dreams do not signify repressed unconscious drives but represent expressions of creativity aimed at resolution. Since then, other therapy models like Gestalt therapy, art therapy, and cognitive behavioral therapy have used dream analysis in one fashion or another.

Although dream analysis has waned in contemporary use, it remains an integral part of some theoretical frameworks. According to a study from the Journal of Psychotherapy Practice and Research , dream analysis appears to be most popular among psychoanalysts trained in psychodynamic theory. The study found that dream analysis is also used in the following models, although it is not as common: person-centered therapy , cognitive behavioral therapy, and Gestalt therapy. Additionally, psychotherapists who participated in the study estimated that approximately 70% of the individuals they treated obtained some benefit from dream analysis.

Because the primary goal of dream analysis is to help people address the problems they are currently facing, it can be used to address many mental health issues. A newer cognitive behavioral technique called image rehearsal therapy has been developed to address concerns like posttraumatic stress and chronic nightmares . In image rehearsal therapy (IRT), the goal is to rewrite the nightmare's story. The therapist may coach the person in treatment to relay the bad dream, write it down, and then change the content to something positive, encouraging the individual to mentally rehearse this new dream script for up to 20 minutes a day in order to decrease the frequency and intensity of the nightmare. Due to its reported effectiveness, IRT is recommended as a best-practice standard for the treatment of nightmares, according to the Journal of Clinical Sleep Medicine .

Although research indicates that there are benefits to dream analysis, some limitations do exist. Some believe that dreams are purely biological phenomena and therefore contain no symbolic meaning. The activation-synthesis hypothesis, coined by psychiatrists Allan Hobson and Robert McCarley, states that dream content is created by commands sent from the brain that never get carried out. In other words, dreaming is simply another form of thinking that happens while we sleep. This point of view calls into question how much “unconscious material” is truly contained in dreams.

When used in conjunction with psychoanalysis, dream analysis is subject to the same limitations as Freudian theory. One major critique of psychoanalysis is that the theory is based on case studies, the results of which are hard to generalize to a larger population. Another criticism is that the theory does not meet scientific standards. For example, the idea that dreams are based on wish fulfillment has not been backed by research. Another complaint about psychoanalytic theory is its negative and deterministic view of humanity, asserting that humans are inevitably driven by unconscious forces. This belief does not account for free will, a central concept in humanistic theories. 

References:

  • Aurora, R. N., Zak, R. S., Auerbach, S. H., Casey, K. R., Chowdhuri, S., Karippot, A., & Maganti, R. K. (2010). Best practice guide for the treatment of nightmare disorder in adults.  Journal of Clinical Sleep Medicine ,  6 (4), 389-401. Retrieved from American Academy of Sleep Medicine.
  • Benedetto, P. (2009). Dreams. In  Jungian Analysis . Retrieved from http://www.jungiananalysts.com/wp/?page_id=37
  • Coon, D. (2005). Psychology A Journey (2nd ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth.
  • Corey, G. (2009). Theory and Practice of Counseling and Psychotherapy (8th ed., pp. 245-248). Belmont, CA: Thomson Brooks/Cole.
  • How do we assess freud's theory today?. (n.d.). In  Freud Museum London . Retrieved from http://www.freud.org.uk/education/topic/10576/subtopic/40030
  • Jones, J. (n.d.). About how we work with dreams in psychoanalysis. In  Sigmund Freud Life and Work . Retrieved from http://www.freudfile.org/psychoanalysis/dreams_psychoanalysis.html
  • Kassin, S. (1998). Psychology (2nd ed., pp. 657-660). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
  • Moon, B. L. (2007). Dialoguing with dreams in existential art therapy [Electronic version].  Journal of the American Art Therapy Association ,  24 (3), 128-133.
  • Pre-History hypotheses about dreams from ancient times to the end of the 19th century. In  Freud Museum London . Retrieved from http://www.freud.org.uk/education/topic/10576/subtopic/40021
  • Schredl, M., Bohusch, C., Kahl, J., Mader, A., & Somesan, A. (2000). The use of dreams in psychotherapy: a survey of psychotherapists in private practice [Electronic version]. Journal of Psychotherapy Practice and Research, 9(2), 81-87.

dream fulfillment essay

More Like This

  • How Naming the Emotions That Emerge in Our Dreams Helps Us Heal
  • Why Are My Dreams So Stressful?
  • Initiation Dreams, Part I: Big Dreams That Change Our Lives

People Are Reading

  • Dialectical Dilemmas and How ACT Models Can Help Guide Treatment
  • How Emotionally Intelligent People Use Negative Emotions to Their Advantage
  • Political Differences May Shorten Thanksgiving Visits
  • Is ‘13 Reasons Why’ Part of the Problem or Part of the Solution?
  • Time-Management Hacks to Be More Efficient and Procrastinate Less

Join GoodTherapy!

Mental health professionals who meet our membership requirements can take advantage of benefits such as:

  • Client referrals
  • Continuing education credits
  • Publication and media opportunities
  • Marketing resources and webinars
  • Special discounts

Notice to users

Home — Essay Samples — Life — Dream — Hopes and Dreams: Nurturing Aspirations for a Fulfilling Life

test_template

Hopes and Dreams: Nurturing Aspirations for a Fulfilling Life

  • Categories: Dream Hope

About this sample

close

Words: 900 |

Published: Sep 7, 2023

Words: 900 | Pages: 2 | 5 min read

Table of contents

The significance of hopes and dreams, the evolution of hopes and dreams, obstacles to hopes and dreams, nurturing and sustaining hopes and dreams.

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr Jacklynne

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Life

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

1 pages / 647 words

1 pages / 681 words

1 pages / 584 words

3 pages / 1502 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Dream

Throughout the years I have found myself creating imaginary places across the world that have had different effects on me. Some have put me in dark places while others have lifted my feelings. I’ve also started to notice the [...]

Science has made it possible for deepening of our understanding about dreaming. Different research findings have explored the various reasons as to why people dream, and it can be stated that fundamental; answers are yet to be [...]

Lucid dreaming is a fascinating phenomenon that has captured the interest of researchers and the general public alike. It is a state of consciousness in which a person is aware that they are dreaming and can often control the [...]

Throughout my life, the concept of a "dream car" has evolved alongside my personal growth and changing tastes. As a child, I was fascinated by the flashy colors and sleek designs of sports cars, inspired by television shows and [...]

Let me assume that this letter is read on some kind of grapheme screen wrapped around your wrist or glued to your face. Future must be awesome with High-tech machines! Most probably my words of knowledge are going to be of no [...]

Brown, J. (2018). The Salon Business Handbook. Milady Publishing.Gupta, R. (2019). The Ultimate Salon Owner's Business Guide: The Complete Guide to Creating a Thriving Salon Business. CreateSpace Independent Publishing [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

dream fulfillment essay

PrepScholar

Choose Your Test

  • Search Blogs By Category
  • College Admissions
  • AP and IB Exams
  • GPA and Coursework

Best Analysis: The American Dream in The Great Gatsby

author image

Book Guides

feature_americandream.jpg

The Great Gatsby is a tragic love story on the surface, but it's most commonly understood as a pessimistic critique of the American Dream. In the novel, Jay Gatsby overcomes his poor past to gain an incredible amount of money and a limited amount of social cache in 1920s NYC, only to be rejected by the "old money" crowd. He then gets killed after being tangled up with them.

Through Gatsby's life, as well as that of the Wilsons', Fitzgerald critiques the idea that America is a meritocracy where anyone can rise to the top with enough hard work. We will explore how this theme plays out in the plot, briefly analyze some key quotes about it, as well as do some character analysis and broader analysis of topics surrounding the American Dream in The Great Gatsby .

What is the American Dream? The American Dream in the Great Gatsby plot Key American Dream quotes Analyzing characters via the American Dream Common discussion and essay topics

Quick Note on Our Citations

Our citation format in this guide is (chapter.paragraph). We're using this system since there are many editions of Gatsby, so using page numbers would only work for students with our copy of the book.

To find a quotation we cite via chapter and paragraph in your book, you can either eyeball it (Paragraph 1-50: beginning of chapter; 50-100: middle of chapter; 100-on: end of chapter), or use the search function if you're using an online or eReader version of the text.

What Exactly Is "The American Dream"?

The American Dream is the belief that anyone, regardless of race, class, gender, or nationality, can be successful in America (read: rich) if they just work hard enough. The American Dream thus presents a pretty rosy view of American society that ignores problems like systemic racism and misogyny, xenophobia, tax evasion or state tax avoidance, and income inequality. It also presumes a myth of class equality, when the reality is America has a pretty well-developed class hierarchy.

The 1920s in particular was a pretty tumultuous time due to increased immigration (and the accompanying xenophobia), changing women's roles (spurred by the right to vote, which was won in 1919), and extraordinary income inequality.

The country was also in the midst of an economic boom, which fueled the belief that anyone could "strike it rich" on Wall Street. However, this rapid economic growth was built on a bubble which popped in 1929. The Great Gatsby was published in 1925, well before the crash, but through its wry descriptions of the ultra-wealthy, it seems to somehow predict that the fantastic wealth on display in 1920s New York was just as ephemeral as one of Gatsby's parties.

In any case, the novel, just by being set in the 1920s, is unlikely to present an optimistic view of the American Dream, or at least a version of the dream that's inclusive to all genders, ethnicities, and incomes. With that background in mind, let's jump into the plot!

The American Dream in The Great Gatsby

Chapter 1 places us in a particular year—1922—and gives us some background about WWI.  This is relevant, since the 1920s is presented as a time of hollow decadence among the wealthy, as evidenced especially by the parties in Chapters 2 and 3. And as we mentioned above, the 1920s were a particularly tense time in America.

We also meet George and Myrtle Wilson in Chapter 2 , both working class people who are working to improve their lot in life, George through his work, and Myrtle through her affair with Tom Buchanan.

We learn about Gatsby's goal in Chapter 4 : to win Daisy back. Despite everything he owns, including fantastic amounts of money and an over-the-top mansion, for Gatsby, Daisy is the ultimate status symbol. So in Chapter 5 , when Daisy and Gatsby reunite and begin an affair, it seems like Gatsby could, in fact, achieve his goal.

In Chapter 6 , we learn about Gatsby's less-than-wealthy past, which not only makes him look like the star of a rags-to-riches story, it makes Gatsby himself seem like someone in pursuit of the American Dream, and for him the personification of that dream is Daisy.

However, in Chapters 7 and 8 , everything comes crashing down: Daisy refuses to leave Tom, Myrtle is killed, and George breaks down and kills Gatsby and then himself, leaving all of the "strivers" dead and the old money crowd safe. Furthermore, we learn in those last chapters that Gatsby didn't even achieve all his wealth through hard work, like the American Dream would stipulate—instead, he earned his money through crime. (He did work hard and honestly under Dan Cody, but lost Dan Cody's inheritance to his ex-wife.)

In short, things do not turn out well for our dreamers in the novel! Thus, the novel ends with Nick's sad meditation on the lost promise of the American Dream. You can read a detailed analysis of these last lines in our summary of the novel's ending .

body_bubble.jpg

Key American Dream Quotes

In this section we analyze some of the most important quotes that relate to the American Dream in the book.

But I didn't call to him for he gave a sudden intimation that he was content to be alone--he stretched out his arms toward the dark water in a curious way, and far as I was from him I could have sworn he was trembling. Involuntarily I glanced seaward--and distinguished nothing except a single green light, minute and far away, that might have been the end of a dock. (1.152)

In our first glimpse of Jay Gatsby, we see him reaching towards something far off, something in sight but definitely out of reach. This famous image of the green light is often understood as part of The Great Gatsby 's meditation on The American Dream—the idea that people are always reaching towards something greater than themselves that is just out of reach . You can read more about this in our post all about the green light .

The fact that this yearning image is our introduction to Gatsby foreshadows his unhappy end and also marks him as a dreamer, rather than people like Tom or Daisy who were born with money and don't need to strive for anything so far off.

Over the great bridge, with the sunlight through the girders making a constant flicker upon the moving cars, with the city rising up across the river in white heaps and sugar lumps all built with a wish out of non-olfactory money. The city seen from the Queensboro Bridge is always the city seen for the first time, in its first wild promise of all the mystery and the beauty in the world.

A dead man passed us in a hearse heaped with blooms, followed by two carriages with drawn blinds and by more cheerful carriages for friends. The friends looked out at us with the tragic eyes and short upper lips of south-eastern Europe, and I was glad that the sight of Gatsby's splendid car was included in their somber holiday. As we crossed Blackwell's Island a limousine passed us, driven by a white chauffeur, in which sat three modish Negroes, two bucks and a girl. I laughed aloud as the yolks of their eyeballs rolled toward us in haughty rivalry.

"Anything can happen now that we've slid over this bridge," I thought; "anything at all. . . ."

Even Gatsby could happen, without any particular wonder. (4.55-8)

Early in the novel, we get this mostly optimistic illustration of the American Dream—we see people of different races and nationalities racing towards NYC, a city of unfathomable possibility. This moment has all the classic elements of the American Dream—economic possibility, racial and religious diversity, a carefree attitude. At this moment, it does feel like "anything can happen," even a happy ending.

However, this rosy view eventually gets undermined by the tragic events later in the novel. And even at this point, Nick's condescension towards the people in the other cars reinforces America's racial hierarchy that disrupts the idea of the American Dream. There is even a little competition at play, a "haughty rivalry" at play between Gatsby's car and the one bearing the "modish Negroes."

Nick "laughs aloud" at this moment, suggesting he thinks it's amusing that the passengers in this other car see them as equals, or even rivals to be bested. In other words, he seems to firmly believe in the racial hierarchy Tom defends in Chapter 1, even if it doesn't admit it honestly.

His heart beat faster and faster as Daisy's white face came up to his own. He knew that when he kissed this girl, and forever wed his unutterable visions to her perishable breath, his mind would never romp again like the mind of God. So he waited, listening for a moment longer to the tuning fork that had been struck upon a star. Then he kissed her. At his lips' touch she blossomed for him like a flower and the incarnation was complete. (6.134)

This moment explicitly ties Daisy to all of Gatsby's larger dreams for a better life —to his American Dream. This sets the stage for the novel's tragic ending, since Daisy cannot hold up under the weight of the dream Gatsby projects onto her. Instead, she stays with Tom Buchanan, despite her feelings for Gatsby. Thus when Gatsby fails to win over Daisy, he also fails to achieve his version of the American Dream. This is why so many people read the novel as a somber or pessimistic take on the American Dream, rather than an optimistic one.  

...as the moon rose higher the inessential houses began to melt away until gradually I became aware of the old island here that flowered once for Dutch sailors' eyes--a fresh, green breast of the new world. Its vanished trees, the trees that had made way for Gatsby's house, had once pandered in whispers to the last and greatest of all human dreams; for a transitory enchanted moment man must have held his breath in the presence of this continent, compelled into an aesthetic contemplation he neither understood nor desired, face to face for the last time in history with something commensurate to his capacity for wonder.

And as I sat there brooding on the old, unknown world, I thought of Gatsby's wonder when he first picked out the green light at the end of Daisy's dock. He had come a long way to this blue lawn and his dream must have seemed so close that he could hardly fail to grasp it. He did not know that it was already behind him, somewhere back in that vast obscurity beyond the city, where the dark fields of the republic rolled on under the night." (9.151-152)

The closing pages of the novel reflect at length on the American Dream, in an attitude that seems simultaneously mournful, appreciative, and pessimistic. It also ties back to our first glimpse of Gatsby, reaching out over the water towards the Buchanan's green light. Nick notes that Gatsby's dream was "already behind him" then (or in other words, it was impossible to attain). But still, he finds something to admire in how Gatsby still hoped for a better life, and constantly reached out toward that brighter future.

For a full consideration of these last lines and what they could mean, see our analysis of the novel's ending .

Analyzing Characters Through the American Dream

An analysis of the characters in terms of the American Dream usually leads to a pretty cynical take on the American Dream.

Most character analysis centered on the American Dream will necessarily focus on Gatsby, George, or Myrtle (the true strivers in the novel), though as we'll discuss below, the Buchanans can also provide some interesting layers of discussion. For character analysis that incorporates the American Dream, carefully consider your chosen character's motivations and desires, and how the novel does (or doesn't!) provide glimpses of the dream's fulfillment for them.

Gatsby himself is obviously the best candidate for writing about the American Dream—he comes from humble roots (he's the son of poor farmers from North Dakota) and rises to be notoriously wealthy, only for everything to slip away from him in the end. Many people also incorporate Daisy into their analyses as the physical representation of Gatsby's dream.

However, definitely consider the fact that in the traditional American Dream, people achieve their goals through honest hard work, but in Gatsby's case, he very quickly acquires a large amount of money through crime . Gatsby does attempt the hard work approach, through his years of service to Dan Cody, but that doesn't work out since Cody's ex-wife ends up with the entire inheritance. So instead he turns to crime, and only then does he manage to achieve his desired wealth.

So while Gatsby's story arc resembles a traditional rags-to-riches tale, the fact that he gained his money immorally complicates the idea that he is a perfect avatar for the American Dream . Furthermore, his success obviously doesn't last—he still pines for Daisy and loses everything in his attempt to get her back. In other words, Gatsby's huge dreams, all precariously wedded to Daisy  ("He knew that when he kissed this girl, and forever wed his unutterable visions to her perishable breath, his mind would never romp again like the mind of God" (6.134)) are as flimsy and flight as Daisy herself.

George and Myrtle Wilson

This couple also represents people aiming at the dream— George owns his own shop and is doing his best to get business, though is increasingly worn down by the harsh demands of his life, while Myrtle chases after wealth and status through an affair with Tom.

Both are disempowered due to the lack of money at their own disposal —Myrtle certainly has access to some of the "finer things" through Tom but has to deal with his abuse, while George is unable to leave his current life and move West since he doesn't have the funds available. He even has to make himself servile to Tom in an attempt to get Tom to sell his car, a fact that could even cause him to overlook the evidence of his wife's affair. So neither character is on the upward trajectory that the American Dream promises, at least during the novel.

In the end, everything goes horribly wrong for both George and Myrtle, suggesting that in this world, it's dangerous to strive for more than you're given.

George and Myrtle's deadly fates, along with Gatsby's, help illustrate the novel's pessimistic attitude toward the American Dream. After all, how unfair is it that the couple working to improve their position in society (George and Myrtle) both end up dead, while Tom, who dragged Myrtle into an increasingly dangerous situation, and Daisy, who killed her, don't face any consequences? And on top of that they are fabulously wealthy? The American Dream certainly is not alive and well for the poor Wilsons.

Tom and Daisy as Antagonists to the American Dream

We've talked quite a bit already about Gatsby, George, and Myrtle—the three characters who come from humble roots and try to climb the ranks in 1920s New York. But what about the other major characters, especially the ones born with money? What is their relationship to the American Dream?

Specifically, Tom and Daisy have old money, and thus they don't need the American Dream, since they were born with America already at their feet.

Perhaps because of this, they seem to directly antagonize the dream—Daisy by refusing Gatsby, and Tom by helping to drag the Wilsons into tragedy .

This is especially interesting because unlike Gatsby, Myrtle, and George, who actively hope and dream of a better life, Daisy and Tom are described as bored and "careless," and end up instigating a large amount of tragedy through their own recklessness.

In other words, income inequality and the vastly different starts in life the characters have strongly affected their outcomes. The way they choose to live their lives, their morality (or lack thereof), and how much they dream doesn't seem to matter. This, of course, is tragic and antithetical to the idea of the American Dream, which claims that class should be irrelevant and anyone can rise to the top.

Daisy as a Personification of the American Dream

As we discuss in our post on money and materialism in The Great Gatsby , Daisy's voice is explicitly tied to money by Gatsby:

"Her voice is full of money," he said suddenly.

That was it. I'd never understood before. It was full of money--that was the inexhaustible charm that rose and fell in it, the jingle of it, the cymbals' song of it. . . . High in a white palace the king's daughter, the golden girl. . . . (7.105-6)

If Daisy's voice promises money, and the American Dream is explicitly linked to wealth, it's not hard to argue that Daisy herself—along with the green light at the end of her dock —stands in for the American Dream. In fact, as Nick goes on to describe Daisy as "High in a white palace the king's daughter, the golden girl," he also seems to literally describe Daisy as a prize, much like the princess at the end of a fairy tale (or even Princess Peach at the end of a Mario game!).

But Daisy, of course, is only human—flawed, flighty, and ultimately unable to embody the huge fantasy Gatsby projects onto her. So this, in turn, means that the American Dream itself is just a fantasy, a concept too flimsy to actually hold weight, especially in the fast-paced, dog-eat-dog world of 1920s America.

Furthermore, you should definitely consider the tension between the fact that Daisy represents Gatsby's ultimate goal, but at the same time (as we discussed above), her actual life is the opposite of the American Dream : she is born with money and privilege, likely dies with it all intact, and there are no consequences to how she chooses to live her life in between.

Can Female Characters Achieve the American Dream?

Finally, it's interesting to compare and contrast some of the female characters using the lens of the American Dream.

Let's start with Daisy, who is unhappy in her marriage and, despite a brief attempt to leave it, remains with Tom, unwilling to give up the status and security their marriage provides. At first, it may seem like Daisy doesn't dream at all, so of course she ends up unhappy. But consider the fact that Daisy was already born into the highest level of American society. The expectation placed on her, as a wealthy woman, was never to pursue something greater, but simply to maintain her status. She did that by marrying Tom, and it's understandable why she wouldn't risk the uncertainty and loss of status that would come through divorce and marriage to a bootlegger. Again, Daisy seems to typify the "anti-American" dream, in that she was born into a kind of aristocracy and simply has to maintain her position, not fight for something better.

In contrast, Myrtle, aside from Gatsby, seems to be the most ambitiously in pursuit of getting more than she was given in life. She parlays her affair with Tom into an apartment, nice clothes, and parties, and seems to revel in her newfound status. But of course, she is knocked down the hardest, killed for her involvement with the Buchanans, and specifically for wrongfully assuming she had value to them. Considering that Gatsby did have a chance to leave New York and distance himself from the unfolding tragedy, but Myrtle was the first to be killed, you could argue the novel presents an even bleaker view of the American Dream where women are concerned.

Even Jordan Baker , who seems to be living out a kind of dream by playing golf and being relatively independent, is tied to her family's money and insulated from consequences by it , making her a pretty poor representation of the dream. And of course, since her end game also seems to be marriage, she doesn't push the boundaries of women's roles as far as she might wish.

So while the women all push the boundaries of society's expectations of them in certain ways, they either fall in line or are killed, which definitely undermines the rosy of idea that anyone, regardless of gender, can make it in America. The American Dream as shown in Gatsby becomes even more pessimistic through the lens of the female characters.  

body_lens.jpg

Common Essay Questions/Discussion Topics

Now let's work through some of the more frequently brought up subjects for discussion.

#1: Was Gatsby's dream worth it? Was all the work, time, and patience worth it for him?

Like me, you might immediately think "of course it wasn't worth it! Gatsby lost everything, not to mention the Wilsons got caught up in the tragedy and ended up dead!" So if you want to make the more obvious "the dream wasn't worth it" argument, you could point to the unraveling that happens at the end of the novel (including the deaths of Myrtle, Gatsby and George) and how all Gatsby's achievements are for nothing, as evidenced by the sparse attendance of his funeral.

However, you could definitely take the less obvious route and argue that Gatsby's dream was worth it, despite the tragic end . First of all, consider Jay's unique characterization in the story: "He was a son of God--a phrase which, if it means anything, means just that--and he must be about His Father's Business, the service of a vast, vulgar and meretricious beauty" (6.7). In other words, Gatsby has a larger-than-life persona and he never would have been content to remain in North Dakota to be poor farmers like his parents.

Even if he ends up living a shorter life, he certainly lived a full one full of adventure. His dreams of wealth and status took him all over the world on Dan Cody's yacht, to Louisville where he met and fell in love with Daisy, to the battlefields of WWI, to the halls of Oxford University, and then to the fast-paced world of Manhattan in the early 1920s, when he earned a fortune as a bootlegger. In fact, it seems Jay lived several lives in the space of just half a normal lifespan. In short, to argue that Gatsby's dream was worth it, you should point to his larger-than-life conception of himself and the fact that he could have only sought happiness through striving for something greater than himself, even if that ended up being deadly in the end.

#2: In the Langston Hughes poem "A Dream Deferred," Hughes asks questions about what happens to postponed dreams. How does Fitzgerald examine this issue of deferred dreams? What do you think are the effects of postponing our dreams? How can you apply this lesson to your own life?

If you're thinking about "deferred dreams" in The Great Gatsby , the big one is obviously Gatsby's deferred dream for Daisy—nearly five years pass between his initial infatuation and his attempt in the novel to win her back, an attempt that obviously backfires. You can examine various aspects of Gatsby's dream—the flashbacks to his first memories of Daisy in Chapter 8 , the moment when they reunite in Chapter 5 , or the disastrous consequences of the confrontation of Chapter 7 —to illustrate Gatsby's deferred dream.

You could also look at George Wilson's postponed dream of going West, or Myrtle's dream of marrying a wealthy man of "breeding"—George never gets the funds to go West, and is instead mired in the Valley of Ashes, while Myrtle's attempt to achieve her dream after 12 years of marriage through an affair ends in tragedy. Apparently, dreams deferred are dreams doomed to fail.

As Nick Carraway says, "you can't repeat the past"—the novel seems to imply there is a small window for certain dreams, and when the window closes, they can no longer be attained. This is pretty pessimistic, and for the prompt's personal reflection aspect, I wouldn't say you should necessarily "apply this lesson to your own life" straightforwardly. But it is worth noting that certain opportunities are fleeting, and perhaps it's wiser to seek out newer and/or more attainable ones, rather than pining over a lost chance.

Any prompt like this one which has a section of more personal reflection gives you freedom to tie in your own experiences and point of view, so be thoughtful and think of good examples from your own life!

Want to write the perfect college application essay?   We can help.   Your dedicated PrepScholar Admissions counselor will help you craft your perfect college essay, from the ground up. We learn your background and interests, brainstorm essay topics, and walk you through the essay drafting process, step-by-step. At the end, you'll have a unique essay to proudly submit to colleges.   Don't leave your college application to chance. Find out more about PrepScholar Admissions now:

#3: Explain how the novel does or does not demonstrate the death of the American Dream. Is the main theme of Gatsby indeed "the withering American Dream"? What does the novel offer about American identity?

In this prompt, another one that zeroes in on the dead or dying American Dream, you could discuss how the destruction of three lives (Gatsby, George, Myrtle) and the cynical portrayal of the old money crowd illustrates a dead, or dying American Dream . After all, if the characters who dream end up dead, and the ones who were born into life with money and privilege get to keep it without consequence, is there any room at all for the idea that less-privileged people can work their way up?

In terms of what the novel says about American identity, there are a few threads you could pick up—one is Nick's comment in Chapter 9 about the novel really being a story about (mid)westerners trying (and failing) to go East : "I see now that this has been a story of the West, after all--Tom and Gatsby, Daisy and Jordan and I, were all Westerners, and perhaps we possessed some deficiency in common which made us subtly unadaptable to Eastern life" (9.125). This observation suggests an American identity that is determined by birthplace, and that within the American identity there are smaller, inescapable points of identification.

Furthermore, for those in the novel not born into money, the American identity seems to be about striving to end up with more wealth and status. But in terms of the portrayal of the old money set, particularly Daisy, Tom, and Jordan, the novel presents a segment of American society that is essentially aristocratic—you have to be born into it. In that regard, too, the novel presents a fractured American identity, with different lives possible based on how much money you are born with.

In short, I think the novel disrupts the idea of a unified American identity or American dream, by instead presenting a tragic, fractured, and rigid American society, one that is divided based on both geographic location and social class.

#4: Most would consider dreams to be positive motivators to achieve success, but the characters in the novel often take their dreams of ideal lives too far. Explain how characters' American Dreams cause them to have pain when they could have been content with more modest ambitions.

Gatsby is an obvious choice here—his pursuit of money and status, particularly through Daisy, leads him to ruin. There were many points when perhaps Gatsby ;could have been happy with what he achieved (especially after his apparently successful endeavors in the war, if he had remained at Oxford, or even after amassing a great amount of wealth as a bootlegger) but instead he kept striving upward, which ultimately lead to his downfall. You can flesh this argument out with the quotations in Chapters 6 and 8 about Gatsby's past, along with his tragic death.

Myrtle would be another good choice for this type of prompt. In a sense, she seems to be living her ideal life in her affair with Tom—she has a fancy NYC apartment, hosts parties, and gets to act sophisticated—but these pleasures end up gravely hurting George, and of course her association with Tom Buchanan gets her killed.

Nick, too, if he had been happy with his family's respectable fortune and his girlfriend out west, might have avoided the pain of knowing Gatsby and the general sense of despair he was left with.

You might be wondering about George—after all, isn't he someone also dreaming of a better life? However, there aren't many instances of George taking his dreams of an ideal life "too far." In fact, he struggles just to make one car sale so that he can finally move out West with Myrtle. Also, given that his current situation in the Valley of Ashes is quite bleak, it's hard to say that striving upward gave him pain.

#5: The Great Gatsby is, among other things, a sobering and even ominous commentary on the dark side of the American dream. Discuss this theme, incorporating the conflicts of East Egg vs. West Egg and old money vs. new money. What does the American dream mean to Gatsby? What did the American Dream mean to Fitzgerald? How does morality fit into achieving the American dream?

This prompt allows you to consider pretty broadly the novel's attitude toward the American Dream, with emphasis on "sobering and even ominous" commentary. Note that Fitzgerald seems to be specifically mocking the stereotypical rags to riches story here—;especially since he draws the Dan Cody narrative almost note for note from the work of someone like Horatio Alger, whose books were almost universally about rich men schooling young, entrepreneurial boys in the ways of the world. In other words, you should discuss how the Great Gatsby seems to turn the idea of the American Dream as described in the quote on its head: Gatsby does achieve a rags-to-riches rise, but it doesn't last.

All of Gatsby's hard work for Dan Cody, after all, didn't pay off since he lost the inheritance. So instead, Gatsby turned to crime after the war to quickly gain a ton of money. Especially since Gatsby finally achieves his great wealth through dubious means, the novel further undermines the classic image of someone working hard and honestly to go from rags to riches.

If you're addressing this prompt or a similar one, make sure to focus on the darker aspects of the American Dream, including the dark conclusion to the novel and Daisy and Tom's protection from any real consequences . (This would also allow you to considering morality, and how morally bankrupt the characters are.)

#6: What is the current state of the American Dream?

This is a more outward-looking prompt, that allows you to consider current events today to either be generally optimistic (the American dream is alive and well) or pessimistic (it's as dead as it is in The Great Gatsby).

You have dozens of potential current events to use as evidence for either argument, but consider especially immigration and immigration reform, mass incarceration, income inequality, education, and health care in America as good potential examples to use as you argue about the current state of the American Dream. Your writing will be especially powerful if you can point to some specific current events to support your argument.

What's Next?

In this post, we discussed how important money is to the novel's version of the American Dream. You can read even more about money and materialism in The Great Gatsby right here .

Want to indulge in a little materialism of your own? Take a look through these 15 must-have items for any Great Gatsby fan .

Get complete guides to Jay Gatsby , George Wilson and Myrtle Wilson to get even more background on the "dreamers" in the novel.

Like we discussed above, the green light is often seen as a stand-in for the idea of the American Dream. Read more about this crucial symbol here .

Need help getting to grips with other literary works? Take a spin through our analyses of The Crucible , The Cask of Amontillado , and " Do not go gentle into this good night " to see analysis in action. You might also find our explanations of point of view , rhetorical devices , imagery , and literary elements and devices helpful.

Want to improve your SAT score by 160 points or your ACT score by 4 points?   We've written a guide for each test about the top 5 strategies you must be using to have a shot at improving your score. Download them for free now:

Trending Now

How to Get Into Harvard and the Ivy League

How to Get a Perfect 4.0 GPA

How to Write an Amazing College Essay

What Exactly Are Colleges Looking For?

ACT vs. SAT: Which Test Should You Take?

When should you take the SAT or ACT?

Get Your Free

PrepScholar

Find Your Target SAT Score

Free Complete Official SAT Practice Tests

How to Get a Perfect SAT Score, by an Expert Full Scorer

Score 800 on SAT Math

Score 800 on SAT Reading and Writing

How to Improve Your Low SAT Score

Score 600 on SAT Math

Score 600 on SAT Reading and Writing

Find Your Target ACT Score

Complete Official Free ACT Practice Tests

How to Get a Perfect ACT Score, by a 36 Full Scorer

Get a 36 on ACT English

Get a 36 on ACT Math

Get a 36 on ACT Reading

Get a 36 on ACT Science

How to Improve Your Low ACT Score

Get a 24 on ACT English

Get a 24 on ACT Math

Get a 24 on ACT Reading

Get a 24 on ACT Science

Stay Informed

Get the latest articles and test prep tips!

Follow us on Facebook (icon)

Anna scored in the 99th percentile on her SATs in high school, and went on to major in English at Princeton and to get her doctorate in English Literature at Columbia. She is passionate about improving student access to higher education.

Ask a Question Below

Have any questions about this article or other topics? Ask below and we'll reply!

Find anything you save across the site in your account

Two Paths for Jewish Politics

An illustration of a woman covering her eyes with two Seder candles shaped like Roman columns burning in front of her.

My first and only experience of antisemitism in America came wrapped in a bow of care and concern. In 1993, I spent the summer in Tennessee with my girlfriend. At a barbecue, we were peppered with questions. What brought us south? How were we getting on? Where did we go to church? We explained that we didn’t go to church because we were Jewish. “That’s O.K.,” a woman reassured us. Having never thought that it wasn’t, I flashed a puzzled smile and recalled an observation of the German writer Ludwig Börne: “Some reproach me with being a Jew, others pardon me, still others praise me for it. But all are thinking about it.”

Thirty-one years later, everyone’s thinking about the Jews. Poll after poll asks them if they feel safe. Donald Trump and Kamala Harris lob insults about who’s the greater antisemite. Congressional Republicans, who have all of two Jews in their caucus , deliver lectures on Jewish history to university leaders. “I want you to kneel down and touch the stone which paved the grounds of Auschwitz,” the Oregon Republican Lori Chavez-DeRemer declared at a hearing in May, urging a visit to D.C.’s Holocaust museum. “I want you to peer over the countless shoes of murdered Jews.” She gave no indication of knowing that one of the leaders she was addressing had been a victim of antisemitism or that another was the descendant of Holocaust survivors.

It’s no accident that non-Jews talk about Jews as if we aren’t there. According to the historian David Nirenberg , talking about the Jews—not actual Jews but Jews in the abstract—is how Gentiles make sense of their world, from the largest questions of existence to the smallest questions of economics. Nirenberg’s focus is “anti-Judaism,” how negative ideas about Jews are woven into canons of Western thought. But as I learned that summer in Tennessee, and as we’re seeing today, concern can be as revealing as contempt. Often the two go hand in hand.

Consider the Antisemitism Awareness Act , which the House of Representatives recently passed by a vote of 320–91. The act purports to be a response to rising antisemitism in the United States. Yet the murder of Jews, synagogue shootings, and cries of “Jews will not replace us” are clearly not what the bill is designed to address. Nearly half of Republicans believe in the “great replacement theory,” after all, and their leader draws from the same well .

The bill will instead outfit the federal government with a new definition of antisemitism that would shield Israel from criticism and turn campus activism on behalf of Palestinians into acts of illegal discrimination. (Seven of the definition’s eleven examples of antisemitism involve opposition to the State of Israel.) Right-wingers who vocally oppose the bill—Marjorie Taylor Greene, Matt Gaetz , Tucker Carlson , and Charlie Kirk—have little problem with its Zionist agenda. They just worry that it will implicate those who believe the Jews are Christ killers.

The G.O.P. is not the only party whose solicitude for the Jews betrays an underlying unease. President Biden has said repeatedly that without Israel no Jew in the world is safe. It sounds like a statement of solidarity, but it’s really a confession of bankruptcy, a disavowal of the democratic state’s obligation to protect its citizens equally. As Biden told a group of Jewish leaders in 2014, nine months before Trump announced his Presidential campaign, “You understand in your bones that no matter how hospitable, no matter how consequential, no matter how engaged, no matter how deeply involved you are in the United States . . . there is really only one absolute guarantee, and that’s the State of Israel.” I’ve lived most of my life in the United States; three of my four grandparents were born here. If the President of my country—a liberal and a Democrat, no less—is saying that my government can’t protect me, where am I supposed to go? I’m Jewish, not Israeli.

Some Jews might feel cheered by Republican crusades against antisemitism or Democratic affirmations of Israel. But there is a long history to these special provisions and professions of concern. Repeating patterns from the ancient and medieval world—and abandoning the innovations pioneered by Jews in the United States—they are bad for democracy. And bad for the Jews.

Contrary to popular myth, the history of Jews and Gentiles is not one of unremitting hostility or eternal antisemitism. It is a chronicle of oscillation, Hannah Arendt argued , a cycle of “special discrimination” and “special favor,” with sovereigns bestowing—then revoking—power and privilege upon the Jews. Jewish leaders, lacking sovereignty of their own, eager to defend their brethren from twitchy neighbors, made themselves indispensable, providing resources to Popes and emperors, lords and kings. They used their favored status to create autonomous communities for their people. Despite their success, or perhaps because of it, they never erased the fine line that separates persecution from protection.

Texts sacred and secular tell the story. A seldom discussed chapter in Genesis lets slip that long before the Israelites were enslaved by Pharaoh, Joseph was ensconced in Pharaoh’s court. As Pharaoh’s right-hand man, Joseph compelled Egypt’s farmers to sell their land for food during a famine, effectively rendering them serfs of the state. Not long after, Exodus opens with a report that “there arose a new king over Egypt, who did not know Joseph.” This new king turned the Egyptians against the Israelites.

After the Greeks conquered Egypt, the Jews of Alexandria were largely denied citizenship in the Hellenic empire. They still managed to curry favor with rulers, which placed them above native Egyptians in the social hierarchy. Centuries later, after the Romans took over, the new regime continued this tradition, adding the envy of the Greeks to the hatred of the Egyptians, stirring up a riotous stew.

Christianity, the child of Judaism, introduced a dangerously Oedipal ingredient to the mix. Despite Christian teaching that the Jews were responsible for Christ’s death, Augustine explained that the Jews should be treated as a people of witness, suitable for preservation rather than punishment. Alive, they testified to the truth of the Hebrew Bible, the Gospels’ predecessor. Dispersed and miserable, they proved the peril of refusing Christ. It was the obligation of Christian rulers to look after the Jews, Augustine claimed , to maintain them “separate in their observance and unlike the rest of the world.”

By providing a theological gloss on an old idea, Augustine put Jews in the crosshairs of Christian politics. At moments of calm, they received privileges and charters granting them levels of autonomy, access, and security that not all groups enjoyed. In thirteenth-century Poland, the historian David Myers writes , Christians could even be fined if they “failed to heed the cries of Jews in the middle of the night.” At moments of change, they were targets of persecution and slaughter. Either way, their fortunes were tied to that of the sovereign, who could be accused of granting the Jews too much protection or not enough.

That left Jewish leaders forever scanning the horizon for trouble—usually from the sovereign or the Gentiles surrounding them, and sometimes from their own people, who were suspicious of their contacts outside the community. As they came to play the role of the “court Jew,” advising the rulers of the medieval era and financing the treasuries of early modern states, they accumulated power and incurred resentment. But with the consolidation of modern nation-states, which claimed to speak for peoples rather than through kings, the hard-won lessons of Jewish élite politics grew increasingly obsolete. Across the Atlantic, a new, more democratic, model beckoned.

Not a single Jew signed the Declaration of Independence or deliberated at the Constitutional Convention. That probably had more to do with numbers—they were a mere twenty-five hundred of 2.5 million people—than with animus. For long before America’s revolutionaries affixed their names to the ideals of freedom, equality, and republican governance, Jews in America had been learning the arts of democracy.

Throughout the eighteenth century, Jews petitioned colonial governments for the democratic rights of membership and participation, responding to leaders like Roger Williams, the founder of Rhode Island, who saw the polity as “a receptacle for people of several Sorts and Opinions.” They built a coalition with the Huguenots of South Carolina to demand their rights. Even before the Revolution, they secured the right, with Quakers, to affirm their allegiance to the government without taking an oath of Christian faith. After the Revolution, they were primed to convert that victory into the right to hold government office. They avowed no special virtues, disavowed no special vices, invoked no high connections. They simply stood by the Constitution, which prohibits religious tests for federal office, and their service to the revolutionary cause.

In Europe, emancipation was often conditioned on cleaving the citizen from the Jew. “The Jews should be refused everything as a nation,” one delegate to the French National Assembly declared, “but granted everything as individuals.” Many American Jews sought to avoid that separation. Instead of abandoning Judaism or relegating it to the private sphere, they designed their institutions in the image of the democracy they were helping to build. As the historian Hasia Diner has shown , synagogues wrote their own constitutions, with democratic procedures, a bill of rights, and provisions for amendment. Government officials were invited to address congregations rather than negotiate with individual élites. Where Jews in modern Europe worked with states to anoint one body to represent them all, continuing the medieval tradition of a single interceding voice between sovereign and Jewry, Jews in America created a multiplicity of organizations, some more democratic than others, none with the power or authority to speak for the whole.

The climax of this distinctively modern approach to Jewish politics came not in defense of the Jews but in support of the New Deal and the Black Freedom struggle. This may seem paradoxical, instances of Jewish do-gooders acting on behalf of others. The protagonists saw things differently. As the Jewish Community Relations Council of Cincinnati declared in 1963, “The society in which Jews are most secure, is itself secure, only to the extent that citizens of all races and creeds enjoy full equality.” This was the opposite of the lesson that Jews had learned across the European millennia.

Although struggles for reform in the United States could provoke antisemitic backlashes, American Jews understood that only in a full and complete democracy could they live full and complete lives. After decades of splitting their votes between Democrats and Republicans, more than ninety per cent of Jewish voters cast their ballots for Franklin Delano Roosevelt in 1944. Orthodox and Reform Jews alike united to welcome the Brown decision, declaring integration, in the words of one Jewish leader, “a veritable fulfillment of our own Jewish purpose and our American dream of destiny.”

In recent years, it’s become fashionable to argue that democracy cannot withstand antisemitism. At moments of intense polarization or economic insecurity, anxious voters look for scapegoats—immigrants, Blacks, Jews—and racist demagogues to get rid of them. In keeping with this waning faith in democracy, influential Jews have reverted to the European model. Instead of organizing or joining democratic movements to fight racism, defend immigration, and build social democracy, Jewish leaders and donors supplicate sovereigns or would-be sovereigns who are antisemitic , or aligned with antisemitism , yet promise special protection for the Jews at home or in Israel. The result is a curious coalition of Jew-lovers and Jew-haters, reminding us that, as Arendt wrote, “society always reacted first to a strong antisemitic movement with marked preference for Jews.”

A forgotten episode from the most polarizing moment in American history, compactly reconstructed by the historian Jonathan Sarna , suggests that democracy has more to offer us than special dispensations from the sovereign. On December 17, 1862, in the midst of the Civil War, General Ulysses S. Grant ordered the expulsion of all Jews living in his zone of command, which spanned parts of Tennessee, Mississippi, and Kentucky. “The most sweeping anti-Jewish regulation in all American history,” Grant’s order had the potential to affect thousands of Jewish men, women, and children in the region, many of them recent immigrants.

Jews had reasons to worry. Wars seldom go well for the Jews, and this one had stirred up all sorts of antisemitism, notably in the North. Jews held prominent positions in the Confederacy. Long identified with money and greed, they were associated in the northern mind with cotton speculators, gold smugglers, corruption, and illegal trade. Grant had his own demons when it came to the Jews, but, even if he hadn’t, he had a penchant for collective punishment. Expelling Jews as a wartime measure against smuggling—and that is what General Orders No. 11 was—was the least of it. Everything seemed primed for a repeat of expulsions past: from ancient Israel; from medieval England, France, and Spain; from cities and towns in Central and Eastern Europe; and now from the “Department of the Tennessee.”

But then that rarest thing in Jewish history happened: nothing. With a few exceptions, Grant’s order was hardly enforced. At least one commander initially defied it, claiming that “he was an officer of the army and not of a church.” As soon as President Lincoln learned of it, on January 3, 1863, he ordered it revoked, which Grant did three days later. “To condemn a class,” Lincoln said, “is, to say the least, to wrong the good with the bad. I do not like to hear a class or nationality condemned on account of a few sinners.”

Of course, a lot happened between December 17th and January 6th, but it belongs to the history of democratic action, rather than Jewish suffering. As soon as a Union captain tried to implement Grant’s order, in Paducah, Kentucky, the Jews mobilized. A group of Paducah locals sent an angry telegram to Lincoln. They went to the national press, which reported the story, and many newspapers editorialized against the order. Isaac Mayer Wise, one of America’s leading rabbis, reminded his fellow-citizens that the order was “everybody’s business,” not just the Jews’. As a final step, the Jews marched on Washington (really, they just travelled in small delegations to the capital). With the help of a sympathetic former congressman, they met with Lincoln, who assured them of his opposition to the order.

It’s no accident that Lincoln’s revocation of Grant’s order came two days after he issued the Emancipation Proclamation. The war turned the battle against slavery into a more general struggle for freedom and equality, which continued long after the fighting was done. In 1868, the Presidential election pitted the Republican Grant against the Democrat Horatio Seymour, whose running mate was a firm opponent of Black equality. Though Reconstruction and Black suffrage were the main issues on the ballot, Jews played an unprecedented role in the election. Anticipating a close result, particularly in battleground states in the Midwest, both parties courted the Jewish vote. Democrats reminded Jewish voters that Grant had shown his true colors with General Orders No. 11. They also warned that Jews would be replaced by Black freedmen, who were Christian. Countering these narrow appeals to Jewish particularity, Jewish Republicans pointed out that Grant had atoned for his order, and that his party’s belief that “all men of all races should be equal” made him “the best man for us Israelites.”

After Grant won, he aggressively pursued the twin causes of Black and Jewish equality, which he saw as the cornerstones of human rights. He stood fast against various efforts to make the United States a Christian nation, pushing for a constitutional amendment that would create free public schools with no teaching of religion. His eight years in office saw the building of many new and beautiful synagogues. Grant appointed more Jews to government office than any President before him. Simon Wolf—who declared a triple identity for himself as “German by birth, an Israelite by faith, and . . . a thorough American by adoption”—was named Recorder of Deeds for the District of Columbia. Affirming that “a Jew must not have any prejudice,” Wolf proclaimed to have appointed the first Black man to a clerkship in his office; that man was the son of Frederick Douglass. After James Garfield was elected President in 1880, he made Douglass Recorder of Deeds, a position continuously held by a Black person until 1952.

History seldom offers any lessons, but this one is clear. American Jews pioneered a new way of being Jewish and democratic. They did it in coalition with other subjugated groups. In the twentieth century, their lodestar was a multiracial egalitarian society. The fading of that vision is a symptom not of rising fascism or even increasing antisemitism but of regression—to an early, eerie, European way of doing things. It’s not good for democracy. And it’s never been good for the Jews. ♦

New Yorker Favorites

The hottest restaurant in France is an all-you-can-eat buffet .

How to die in good health .

Was Machiavelli misunderstood ?

A heat shield for the most important ice on Earth .

A major Black novelist made a remarkable début. Why did he disappear ?

Andy Warhol obsessively documented his life, but he also lied constantly, almost recreationally .

Sign up for our daily newsletter to receive the best stories from The New Yorker .

By signing up, you agree to our User Agreement and Privacy Policy & Cookie Statement . This site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google Privacy Policy and Terms of Service apply.

Are Hollywood’s Jewish Founders Worth Defending?

COMMENTS

  1. Sigmund Freud Dream Theory

    Based on this dream, Freud (1900) proposed that a major function of dreams was the fulfillment of wishes. Freud's Interpretation of Dreams. The Interpretation of Dreams is a seminal work by Sigmund Freud, published in 1899, that introduced his theory of psychoanalysis and dream interpretation. Here's a summary of its key points:

  2. The Interpretation of Dreams by Sigmund Freud

    Freud was an incredibly prolific writer, publishing more than 320 different books, articles, and essays. ... While Freud believed that dreams were primarily about wish fulfillment and expressions of the unconscious, researchers today believe that dreams serve to consolidate memory and learning. The often fragmented and confusing content of ...

  3. Why Do We Dream? Understanding Dream Theory

    At a Glance. There is no single dream theory that fully explains all of the aspects of why we dream. The most prominent theory is that dreams help us to process and consolidate information from the previous day. However, other theories have suggested that dreams are critical for emotional processing, creativity, and self-knowledge.

  4. Wish Fulfilment

    Anna's strict nanny blamed her sickness not on strawberries as such, but on the excess of them, on eating too many strawberries. In doing so, she introduces rules of strawberry-eating. Strawberries became subject to a kind of prohibition, and as a result became the forbidden fruit! Freud's basic claim is that a dream is the fulfilment of a wish.

  5. PDF III A Dream is the Fulfilment of a Wish

    The dream of this poor sufferer seems almost like a concrete representation of a phrase that sometimes forces its way on to people's lips in unpleasant. 1 [This dream was reported by Freud in a letter to Fliess, dated March 4, 1895 (Freud, 1950a, Letter 22)—the earliest recorded hint at the wish-fulfilment theory.]

  6. Sigmund Freud's The Interpretation of Dreams

    Sigmund Freud says that "a dream is a disguised fulfillment of a repressed wish". What he means is that every dream represents a wish fulfillment. Dreams represent the imaginary fulfillment of a wish or impulse in early childhood, before such wishes have been repressed. The dream images represent the unconscious wishes or thought disguised ...

  7. Dream Fulfillment: Lessons From Inspiring Individuals

    Making a Difference. Dream fulfillment goes beyond personal success; it is also about making a difference in the lives of others and leaving a positive impact on the world. Successful individuals understand the importance of using their talents, resources, and influence to contribute to the greater good.

  8. The Interpretation of Dreams

    The Interpretation of Dreams (German: Die Traumdeutung) is an 1899 book by Sigmund Freud, the founder of psychoanalysis, in which the author introduces his theory of the unconscious with respect to dream interpretation, and discusses what would later become the theory of the Oedipus complex.Freud revised the book at least eight times and, in the third edition, added an extensive section which ...

  9. III. The Dream Is the Fulfilment of a Wish

    Contents-BIBLIOGRAPHIC RECORD. Sigmund Freud (1856-1939). The Interpretation of Dreams. 1913. III. The Dream Is the Fulfilment of a Wish. W HEN after passing a defile one has reached an eminence where the ways part and where the view opens out broadly in different directions, it is permissible to stop for a moment and to consider where one is to turn next.

  10. A Deep Dive Into Freud's Wish Fulfillment Theory in

    Sigmund Freud's "wish fulfillment" theory suggests that our dreams are not random but expressions of our deepest, often suppressed desires. Freud's innovative approach to dream analysis involves understanding two types of content in dreams - the manifest (what we remember upon waking) and the latent (the hidden, symbolic meaning).

  11. (PDF) Dreams and Psychology

    dreams is related to wish fulfillment. Freud believed that the manifest content of a dream, or. the actual imagery and eve nts of the dream, serve d to disguise the latent content or the ...

  12. Essays About Dreams In Life: 14 Examples And Topic Ideas

    Check out these essays about dreams and sleep. 2. My Dream, My Future By Deborah Massey. "At the time when I have my job and something to make them feel so proud of me, I would like to give them the best life. I would like to make them feel comfortable and see sweet smiles on their faces.

  13. Freud's Dream Theory

    This dream led Freud to develop his theory of dream analysis. He proposed that all dreams are a form of wish-fulfillment of repressed wishes or the representation of wish-fulfillment. These ...

  14. Dreams and Dreaming

    This entry provides an overview of major themes in the philosophy of sleep and dreaming, with a focus on Western analytic philosophy, and discusses relevant scientific findings. 1. Dreams and epistemology. 1.1 Cartesian dream skepticism. 1.2 Earlier discussions of dream skepticism and why Descartes' version is special.

  15. Freud's Dream Interpretation: A Different Perspective Based on the Self

    Freud realized that dream content is derived from but not identical to real life; thus, he suggested that some transformation and connection must exist between these materials. He contended that these connections are not random but rather constrained by one's unconscious desires, such that "a dream is the fulfillment of a wish" (p. 122).

  16. Dream Essays: Samples & Topics

    Essay Samples on Dream. Essay Examples. Essay Topics. Explaining Why Dreams and Goals Are Valuable. Human existence is marked by an innate yearning for progress, fulfillment, and purpose. At the core of this drive lies the pursuit of dreams and goals, powerful constructs that transcend cultures, backgrounds, and ages. In this essay, we delve ...

  17. How to Fulfill Dreams

    2. Believe it is achievable. Unfortunately, too many people will never accomplish their dreams because they simply refuse to believe in themselves. Optimism is absolutely required for dream fulfillment and life enjoyment. If you don't have natural self-confidence, make finding it your first dream to accomplish.

  18. Dream Analysis

    Dream Analysis. Dream analysis is a therapeutic technique best known for its use in psychoanalysis. Sigmund Freud viewed dreams as "the royal road" to the unconscious and developed dream ...

  19. Hopes and Dreams: Nurturing Aspirations for a Fulfilling Life: [Essay

    In the pursuit of our dreams, we find fulfillment and a profound sense of accomplishment, rendering life's challenges worthwhile. Moreover, hopes and dreams serve as powerful motivators, especially in the face of adversity. When confronted with obstacles and setbacks, our aspirations provide the resilience and determination needed to endure and ...

  20. Best Analysis: The American Dream in The Great Gatsby

    Book Guides. The Great Gatsby is a tragic love story on the surface, but it's most commonly understood as a pessimistic critique of the American Dream. In the novel, Jay Gatsby overcomes his poor past to gain an incredible amount of money and a limited amount of social cache in 1920s NYC, only to be rejected by the "old money" crowd.

  21. Story

    I had fulfilled my dream. The next day, I received an outpouring of support from friends, family and fans. Everyone was thrilled that I had achieved my goal and they congratulated me on my success. I had finally achieved my dream, and it felt incredible. I had worked hard and I had overcome the obstacles that had been holding me back.

  22. Dream Fulfillment for the Human Equality Essay 1

    Fulfillment Of The Dream For Human Equality Essay. It is with tireless exertion and perseverance that the individual must work in unification with their fellow human to fulfill the destiny of living in a world that has realized the beauty and harmony of the truest form of human equality.

  23. Two Paths for Jewish Politics

    The Weekend Essay. Two Paths for Jewish Politics. ... "a veritable fulfillment of our own Jewish purpose and our American dream of destiny." ...