Logo for University of Central Florida Pressbooks

Chapter 3: The mind-body problem

The mind-body problem

Matthew Van Cleave

Introduction: A pathway through this chapter

What is the relationship between the mind and the body? In contemporary philosophy of mind, there are a myriad of different, nuanced accounts of this relationship. Nonetheless, these accounts can be seen as falling into two broad categories: dualism and physicalism. [1] According to dualism , the mind cannot be reduced to a merely physical thing, such as the brain. The mind is a wholly different kind of thing than physical objects. One simple way a dualist might try to make this point is the following: although we can observe your brain (via all kinds of methods of modern neuroscience), we cannot observe your mind. Your mind seems inaccessible to third-person observation (that is, to people other than you) in a way that your brain isn’t. Although neuroscientists could observe activation patterns in your brain via functional magnetic resonance imagining, they could not observe your thoughts. Your thoughts seem to be accessible only in the first person—only you can know what you are thinking or feeling directly. Insofar as other can know this, they can only know it indirectly, though your behaviors (including what you say and how you act ). Readers of previous chapters will recognize that dualism is the view held by the 17th century philosopher, René Descartes, and that I have referred to in earlier chapters as the Cartesian view of mind . In contrast with dualism, physicalism is the view that the mind is not a separate, wholly different kind of thing from the rest of the physical world. The mind is constituted by physical things. For many physicalists, the mind just is the brain. We may not yet understand how mind/brain works, but the spirit of physicalism is often motivated by something like Ockham’s razor : the principle that all other things being equal, the simplest explanation is the best explanation. Physicalists think that all mind related phenomena can be explained in terms of the functioning of the brain. So a theory that posits both the brain and another sui generis entity (a nonphysical mind or mental properties) violates Ockham’s razor: it posits two kinds of entities (brains and minds) whereas all that is needed to explain the relevant phenomena is one (brains).

The mind-body problem is best thought of not as a single problem but as a set of problems that attach to different views of the mind. For physicalists, the mind-body problem is the problem of explaining how conscious experience can be nothing other than a brain activity—what has been called “ the hard problem .” For dualists, the mind-body problem manifests itself as “ the interaction problem ”—the problem of explaining how nonphysical mental phenomena relate to or interact with physical phenomena, such as brain processes. Thus, the mind-body problem is that no matter which view of the mind you take, there are deep philosophical problems. The mind, no matter how we conceptualize it, seems to be shrouded in mystery. That is the mind-body problem. Below we will explore different strands of the mind-body problem, with an emphasis on physicalist attempts to explain the mind. In an era of neuroscience, it seems increasingly plausible that the mind is in some sense identical to the brain. But there are two putative properties of minds—especially human minds—that appear to be recalcitrant to physicalist explanations. The two properties of minds that we will focus on in this chapter are “original intentionality” (the mind’s ability to have meaningful thoughts) and “qualia” (the qualitative aspects of our conscious experiences).

We noted above the potential use of Ockham’s razor as an argument in favor of physicalism. However, this simplicity argument works only if physicalism can explain all of the relevant properties of the mind. A common tactic of the dualist is to argue that physicalism cannot explain all of the important aspects of the mind. We can view several of the famous arguments we will explore in this chapter—the “Chinese room” argument, Nagel’s “what is it like to be a bat” argument, and Jackson’s “knowledge argument”—as manifestations of this tactic. If the physicalist cannot explain aspects of the mind like “original intentionality” and “qualia” then the simplicity argument fails. In contrast, a tactic of physicalists is to either try to meet this explanatory challenge or to deny that these properties ultimately exist. This latter tactic can be clearly seen in Daniel Dennett’s responses to these challenges to physicalism since he denies that original intentionality and qualia ultimately exist. This kind of eliminativist strategy, if successful, would keep in place Ockham simplicity argument.

Representation and the mind

One aspect of mind that needs explaining is how the mind is able to represent things. Consider the fact that I can think about all kinds of different things— about this textbook I am trying to write, about how I would like some Indian food for lunch, about my dog Charlie, about how I wish I were running in the mountains right now. Medieval philosophers referred to the mind as having intentionality —the curious property of “aboutness”—that is, the property of an object to be able to be about some other object. In a certain sense, the mind seems to function kind of like a mirror does—it reflects things other than itself. But unlike a mirror, whose reflected images are not inherently meaningful, minds seem to have what contemporary philosopher John Searle calls “ original intentionality .” In contrast, the mirror has only “ derived intentionality ”—its image is meaningful only because something else gives it meaning or sees it as meaningful. Another thing that has derived intentionality is words, for example the word “tree.” “Tree” refers to trees, of course, but it is not as if the physical marks on a page inherently refer to trees. Rather, human beings who speak English use the word “tree” to refer to trees. Spanish speakers use the word “arbol” to refer to trees. But in neither case do those physical marks on the page (or sound waves in the air, in the case of spoken words) inherently mean anything. Rather, those physical phenomena are only meaningful because a human mind is representing those physical phenomena as meaningful. Thus, words are only meaningful because a human mind represents them in a meaningful way. Although we speak of the word itself as carrying meaning, this meaning has only derived intentionality. In contrast, the human mind has original intentionality because only the mind is the ultimate creator of meaningful representations. We can explain the meaningfulness of words in terms of thoughts, but then how do we explain the meaningfulness of the thoughts themselves? This is what philosophers are trying to explain when they investigate the representational aspect of mind.

There are many different attempts to explain what mental representation is but we will only cursorily consider some fairly rudimentary ideas as a way of building up to a famous thought experiment that challenges a whole range of physicalist accounts of mental representation. Let’s start with a fairly simple, straightforward idea—that of mental images. Perhaps what my mind does when it represents my dog Charlie is that it creates a mental image of Charlie. This account seems to fit our first person experience, at least in certain cases, since many people would describe their thoughts in terms of images in their mind. But whatever a mental image is, it cannot be like a physical image because physical images require interpretation in terms of something else. When I’m representing my dog Charlie it can’t be that my thoughts about Charlie just are some kind of image or picture of Charlie in my head because that picture would require a mind to interpret it! But if the image is suppose to represent the thing that has “original intentionality,” then if our explanation requires some other thing that has that has original intentionality in order to interpret it, then the mental image isn’t really the thing that has original intentionality. Rather, the thing interpreting the image would have original intentionality. There’s a potential problem that looms here and threatens to drive the mental image view of mental representation into incoherence: the object in the world is represented by a mental image but that mental image itself requires interpretation in terms of something else. It would be problematic for the mental image proponent to then say that there is some other inner “understander” that interprets the mental image. For how does this inner understander understand? By virtue of another mental image in its “head”? Such a view would create what philosophers call an infinite regress : a series of explanations that require further explanations, thus, ultimately explaining nothing. The philosopher Daniel Dennett sees explanations of this sort as committing what he calls “ the homuncular fallacy ,” after the Latin term, homunculus , which means “little man.” The problem is that if we explain the nature of the mind by, in essence, positing another inner mind, then we haven’t really explained anything. For that inner mind itself needs to be explained. It should be obvious why positing a further inner mind inside the first inner mind enters us into an infinite regress and why this is fatal to any successful explanation of the phenomenon in question—mental representation or intentionality.

Within the cognitive sciences, one popular way of understanding the nature of human thought is to see the mind as something like a computer. A computer is a device that takes certain inputs (representations) and transforms those inputs in accordance with certain rules (the program) and then produces a certain output (behavior). The idea is that the computer metaphor gives us a satisfying way of explaining what human thought and reasoning is and does so in a way that is compatible with physicalism. The idea, popular in philosophy and cognitive science since the 1970s, is that there is a kind of language of thought which brain states instantiate and which is similar to a natural language in that it possesses both a grammar and a semantics, except that the representations in the language of thought have original intentionality, whereas the representations in natural languages (like English and Spanish) have only derived intentionality. One central question in the philosophy of mind concerns how these “words” in the language of thought get their meaning? We have seen above that these representations can’t just be mental images and there’s a further reason why mental images don’t work for the computer metaphor of the mind: mental images don’t have syntax like language does. You can’t create meaningful sentences by putting together a series of pictures because there are no rules for how those pictures create a holistic meaning out of the parts. For example, how could pictures represent the thought, Leslie wants to go out in the rain but not without an umbrella with a picture (or pictures)? How do I represent with a picture someone’s desire? Or how do I represent the negation of something with only a picture? True, there are devices that we can use within pictures, such as the “no” symbol on no smoking signs. But those symbols are already not functioning purely as pictorial representations that seem to represent in virtue of their similarity. There is no pictorial similarity between the purely logical notion “not” and any picture we could draw. So whatever the words of the language of thought (that is, mental representations) are, their meaning cannot derive from a pictorial similarity to what they represent. So we need some other account. Philosophers have given many such accounts, but most of those accounts attempt to understand mental representation in terms of a causal relationship between objects in the world and representations. That is, whatever types of objects cause (or would cause) certain brain states to “light up,” so to speak, are what those brain states represent. So if there’s a particular brain state that lights up any time I see (or think about) a dog, then that is what those mental representations stand for. Delving into the nuances of contemporary theories of representation is beyond the scope of this chapter, but the important point is that the language of thought idea that these theories support is supposed to be compatible with physicalism as well as the computer analogy of explaining the mind. On this account, the “words” of the language of thought have original intentionality and thinking is just the manipulation of these “words” using certain syntactic rules (the “program”) that are hard-wired into the brain (either innately or by learning) and which are akin to the grammar of a natural language.

There is a famous objection to the computer analogy of human thought that comes from the philosopher John Searle, who thinks that it shows that human thought and understanding cannot be reduced to the kind of thing that a computer can do. Searle’s thought experiment is called the Chinese Room . Imagine that there is a room with a man inside of it. What the man does is take slips of paper that are passed into the room via a slit. The slips of paper have writing on them that look like this:

the mind body problem essay

The room also contains a giant bookshelf with many different volumes of books. Those books are labeled something like this:

the mind body problem essay

The man writes the symbols and then passes it back through the slit in the wall. From the perspective of the man in the room, this is what he does. Nothing more nothing less. The man inside the room doesn’t understand what these symbols mean; they are just meaningless squiggles on a page to him. He sees the difference between the different symbols merely in terms of their shapes. However, from outside the room Chinese speakers who are writing questions on the slips of paper and passing them through the slot in the room come to believe that the Chinese room (or something inside it) understands Chinese and is thus intelligent.

The Chinese room is essentially a scenario in which a computer program passes the Turing Test . In paper published in 1950, Alan Turing proposed a test for how we should determine whether or not a machine can think. Basically, the test is whether or not the machine can make a human investigator believe that the machine is a human. The human investigator is able to ask the machine any questions they can think of (which Turing imagined would be conducted via types responses on a keyboard). Imagine what some of the questions might be. Here is one such potential question one might ask:

Rotate a capital letter “D” 90 degrees counterclockwise and place it atop a capital letter “J.” What kind of weather does this make you think of?

A computer that could pass the Turing Test would be able to answer questions such as this and thus would make a human investigator believe that the computer was actually another human being. Turing thought that if a machine could do this, we should count that machine as having intelligence. The Chinese Room thought experiment is supposed to challenge Turing’s claim that something that can pass the Turing Test is thereby intelligent. The essence of a computer is that of a syntactic machine —a machine that takes symbols as inputs, manipulates symbols in accordance with a series of rules (the program), and gives the outputs that the rules dictate. Importantly, we can understand what syntactic machines do without having to say that they interpret or understand their inputs/outputs. In fact, a syntactic machine cannot possibly understand the symbols because there’s nothing there to understand. For example, in the case of modern-day computers, the symbols being processed are strings of 1s and 0s, which are physically instantiated in the CPU of a computer as a series of on/off voltages (that is, transistors). Note that a series of voltages are no more inherently meaningful than a series of different fluttering patterns of a flag waving in the wind, or a series of waves hitting a beach, or a series of footsteps on a busy New York City subway platform. They are merely physical patterns, nothing more, nothing less. What a computer does, in essence, is “reads” these inputs and gives outputs in accordance with the program. This simple theoretical (mathematical) device is called a “ Turing machine ,” after Alan Turing. A calculator is an example of a simple Turing machine. In contrast, a modern day computer is an example of what is called a “ universal Turing machine ”— universal because it can run any number of different programs that will allow it to compute all kinds of different outputs. In contrast, a simple calculator is only running a couple different simple programs—ones that correspond to the different kinds of mathematical functions the calculator has (+, −, ×, ÷). The Chinese room has all the essential parts of the computer and is functioning exactly as a computer does: he “reads” these symbols and produces outputs using symbols, in accordance with what the program dictates. If the program is sufficiently well written, then the man’s responses (the room’s output) will be able to convince someone outside the room that the room (or something inside it) understands Chinese.

But the whole point is that the there is nothing inside the room that understands Chinese. The man in the room doesn’t understand Chinese—they are just meaningless symbols to him. The written volumes don’t understand Chinese either—how could they?—books don’t understand things. Furthermore, Searle argues that the understanding of Chinese doesn’t just magically emerge from the combination of all the parts of the Chinese room: if no one of the parts of the room has any understanding of Chinese, then neither does the whole room. Thus, the Chinese room thought experiment is supposed to be a counterexample to the Turing Test: the Chinese room passes the Turing Test but the Chinese room doesn’t understand Chinese. Rather, it just acts as if it understands Chinese. Without understanding, there can be no thought. The Chinese room, impressive as it is for passing the Turing Test, lacks any understanding and therefore is not really thinking. Likewise, a computer cannot think because a computer is merely a syntactic machine that does not understand the inputs or the outputs. Rather, from the perspective of the computer, the strings of 1s and 0s are just meaningless symbols. [2] The people outside the Chinese room might ascribe thought and understanding of Chinese to the room, but there is neither thought nor understanding involved. Likewise, at some point in the future, someone may finally create a computer program that would pass the Turing Test [3] and we might think that machine has thought and understanding, but the Chinese room is supposed to show that we would be wrong to think this. No merely syntactic machine could ever think because no merely syntactic machine could ever understand. That is the point of the Chinese room thought experiment.

We could put this point in terms of the distinction between original vs. derived intentionality: no amount of derived intentionality will ever get you original intentionality. Computers have only derived intentionality and since genuine thought requires original intentionality, it follows that computers could never think. Here is a reconstructed version of the Chinese room argument:

  • Computers are merely syntactic machines.
  • Therefore, computers lack original intentionality (from 1)
  • Thought requires original intentionality.
  • Therefore, computers cannot think (from 2-3)

How should we assess the Chinese room argument? One thing to say is that it seems to make a lot of simplifying assumptions about his Chinese room. For example, the philosopher Daniel Dennett suggests that in order to pass the Turing Test a computer would need something on the order of 100 billion lines of code. That would take the man inside the room many lifetimes to hand simulate the code in the way that we are invited to imagine. Searle thinks that these practical kinds of considerations can be dismissed—for example, we can just imagine that the man inside the room can operate faster than the speed of light. Searle thinks that these kinds of assumptions are not problematic, for why should mere speed of operation make any difference to the theoretical point he is trying to make—which is that the merely syntactic processing of a digital computer could not achieve understanding? Dennett, on the other hand, thinks that such simplifying assumptions should alert us that there is something fishy going on with the Chinese room thought experiment. If we were really, truly imagining a computer program that could pass the Turing Test, Dennett thinks, then it wouldn’t sound nearly as absurd to say that the computer had thought.

There’s a deeper objection to the Chinese room argument. This response is sometimes referred to as the “other minds reply.” The essence of the Chinese room rebuttal of the Turing Test involves, so to speak, looking at the guts of what is going on inside of a computer. When you look at it “up close,” it certainly doesn’t seem like all of that syntactic processing adds up to intelligent thought. However, one can make exactly the same point about the human brain (something that Searle believes is undoubtedly capable of thought): the functioning of neurons, or even whole populations of neurons in neuronal spike trains, do not look like what we think of as intelligent thought. Far from it! But of course it doesn’t follow that human brains aren’t thinking! The problem is that in both cases we are looking at the wrong level of description. In order for us to be able to “see” the thought, we must be looking in the right place.

Zooming in and looking at the mechanics of the machines up close is not going to enable us to see the thought and intelligence. Rather, we have to zoom out to the level of behavior and observe the responses in their context. Thought isn’t something we can see up close; rather, thought is something that we attribute to something whose behavior is sufficiently intelligent. Dennett suggests the following cartoon as a reductio ad absurdum of the Chinese room argument:

image

In the cartoon, Dennett imagines someone going inside the Chinese room to see what is going on inside the room. Once inside they see the man responding to the questions of Chinese speakers outside the room. The woman tells the man (perhaps someone she knows), “I didn’t know you knew Chinese!” In response the man explains that he doesn’t and that he is just looking up the relevant strings Chinese characters to write in response to the inputs he receives. The woman’s interpretation of this is: “I see! You use your understanding of English in order to fake understanding Chinese!” The man’s response is: “What makes you think I understand English?” The joke is that the woman’s evidence for thinking that the man inside the room understands English is her evidence of his spoken behavior. This is exactly the same evidence that the Chinese speakers have of the Chinese room. So if the evidence is good enough for the woman inside the room to say that the man inside the room understands Chinese, why is the evidence of the Chinese speakers outside the room any different? We can make the problem even more acute. Suppose that we were to look inside the man inside the room’s brain. We would see all kinds of neural activity and then we could say, “Hey, this doesn’t look like thought; it’s just bunches of neurons sending chemical messages back and forth and those chemical signals have no inherent meaning.” Dennett’s point is that this response makes the same kind of mistake that Searle makes in supposing a computer can’t think: in both cases, we are focusing on the wrong level of detail. Neither the innards of the brain nor the innards of a computer looks like there’s thinking going on. Rather, thinking only emerges at the behavioral level; it only emerges when we are listening to what people are saying and, more generally, observing what they are doing . This is what is called the other minds reply to the Chinese room argument.

Interlude: Interpretationism and Representation

The other minds reply points us towards a radically different account of the nature of thought and representation. A common assumption in the philosophy of mind (and one that Searle also makes) is that thought (intentionality, representation) is something to be found within the inner workings of the thinking thing, whether we are talking about human minds or artificial minds. In contrast, on the account that Dennett defends, thought is not a phenomenon to be observed at the level of the inner workings of the machine. Rather, thought is something that we attribute to people in order to understand and predict their behaviors. To be sure, the brain is a complex mechanism that causes our intelligent behaviors (as well as our unintelligent ones), but to try to look inside the brain for some language-like representation system is to look in the wrong place. Representations aren’t something we will find in the brain, they are just something that we attribute to certain kinds of intelligent things (paradigmatically human beings) in order to better understand those beings and predict their behaviors. This view of the nature of representation is called interpretationism and can be seen as a kind of instrumentalism . Instrumentalists about representation believe that representations aren’t, in the end, real things.

Rather, they are useful fictions that we attribute in order to understand and predict certain behaviors. For example, if I am playing against the computer in a game of chess, I might explain the computer’s behavior by attributing certain thoughts to it such as, “The computer moved the pawn in front of the king because it thought that I would put the king in check with my bishop and it didn’t want to be in check.” I might also attribute thoughts to the computer in order to predict what it will do next: “Since the computer would rather lose its pawn than its rook, it will move the pawn in front of the king rather than the rook.” None of this requires that there be internal representations inside the computer that correspond to the linguistic representations we attribute. The fundamental insight about representation, according to interpretationism, is that just as we merely interpret computers as having internal representations (without being committed to the idea that they actually contain those representations internally), so too we merely interpret human beings as having internal representations (without being committed to whether or not they contain those internal representations). It is useful (for the purposes of explaining behavior) to interpret humans as having internal representations, even if they don’t actually have internal representations.

Interpretationist accounts of representation raise deep questions about where meaning and intentionality reside, if not in the brain, but we will not be able to broach those questions here. Suffice it to say that the disagreement between Searle and Dennett regarding Searle’s Chinese room thought experiment traces back to what I would argue is the most fundamental rift within the philosophy of mind: the rift between the Cartesian view of the mind, on the one hand, and the behaviorist tradition of the mind, on the other. Searle’s view of the mind, specifically his notion of “original intentionality,” traces back to a Cartesian view of the mind. On this view, the mind contains something special—something that cannot be capture merely by “matter in motion” or by any kind of physical mechanism. The mind is sui generis and is set apart from the rest of nature. For Searle, meaning and understand have to issue back to an “original” mean-er or understand-er. And that understand-er cannot be a mindless mechanism (which is why Searle thinks that computers can’t think). For Searle, like Descartes, thinking is reserved for a special (one might say, magical) kind of substance. Although Searle himself rejects Descartes’s conclusion that the mind is nonphysical, he retains the Cartesian idea that thinking is carried out by a special, quasi-magical kind of substance. Searle thinks that this substance is the brain, an object that he thinks contains special causal powers and that cannot be replicated or copied in any other kind of physical object (for example, an artificial brain made out of metal and silicon). Dennett’s behaviorist view of the mind sees the mind as nothing other than a complex physical mechanism that churns out intelligent behaviors that we then classify using a special mental vocabulary—the vocabulary of “minds,” “thoughts,” “representations,” and “intentionality.” The puzzle for Dennett’s behaviorist view is: How can there meaning and understanding without any original meaner/understander? How can there be only derived intentionality and no original intentionality?

Consciousness and the mind

Interpretationism sees the mind as a certain kind of useful fiction: we attribute representational states (thoughts) to people in virtue of their intelligent behavior and we do so in order to explain and predict their behavior. The causes of one’s intelligent behavior are real, but the representational states that we attribute need not map neatly onto any particular brain states. Thus, there need not be any particular brain state that represents the content, “Brittney Spears is a washed up pop star,” for example.

But there another aspect of our mental lives that seems more difficult to explain away in the way interpretationism explains away representation and intentionality. This aspect of our mind is first-person conscious experience . To borrow a term from Thomas Nagel, conscious experience refers to the “what it’s like” of our first person experience of the world. For example, I am sitting here at my table with a blue thermos filled with coffee. The coffee has a distinctive, qualitative smell which would be difficult to describe to someone who has never smelled it before. Likewise, the blue of the thermos has a distinctive visual quality—a “what it’s like”—that is different from what it’s like to see blue. These experiences—the smell of the coffee, the look of the blue—are aspects of my conscious experience and they have a distinctive qualitative dimension—there is something it’s like to smell coffee and to see blue. This qualitative character seems in some sense to be ineffable—that is, it would be very difficult if not impossible to convey what it is like to someone who had never smelled coffee or to someone who had never seen the color blue. Imagine someone who was colorblind. How would you explain what blue was to them? Sure, you could tell them that it was the color of the ocean, but that would not convey to them the particular quality that you (someone who is not color blind) experience when you look at a brilliant blue ocean or lake. Philosophers have coined a term that they use to refer to the qualitative aspects of our conscious experience: qualia . It seems that our conscious experience is real and cannot be explained away in the way that representation can. Maybe there needn’t be anything similar to sentences in my brain, but how could there not be colors, smells, feels? The feeling of stubbing your toe and the feeling of an orgasm are very different feels (thank goodness), but it seems that they are both very much real things. That is, if neuroscientists were to be able to explain exactly how your brain causes you to respond to stubbing your toe, such an explanation would seem to leave something out if it neglected the feeling of the pain. From our first person perspective, our experiences seem to be the most real thing there are, so it doesn’t seem that we could explain their reality away.

Physicalists need not disagree that conscious experiences are real; they would simply claim that they are ultimately just physical states of our brain. Although that might seem to be a plausible position, there are well known problems with claiming that conscious experiences are nothing other than physical states of our brain. The problem is that it does not seem that our conscious experience could just reduce to brain states—that is, to our neurons in our brain sending lots and lots of chemical messages back and forth simultaneously. The 17th century philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) was no brain scientist (that would take another 250 to develop) but he put forward a famous objection to the idea that consciousness could be reduced to any kind of mechanism (and the brain is one giant, complex mechanism). Leibniz’s objection is sometimes referred to as “ Leibniz’s mill .” In 1714, Leibniz wrote:

Moreover, we must confess that perception , and what depends on it, is inexplicable in terms of mechanical reasons , that is, through shapes and motions. If we imagine that there is a machine whose structure makes it think, sense, and have perceptions, we could conceive it enlarged, keeping the same proportions, so that we could enter into it, as one enters into a mill. Assuming that, when inspecting its interior, we will only find parts that push one another, and we will never find anything to explain a perception ( Monadology , section 17).

Leibniz uses a famous form of argument here called reductio ad absurdum : He assumes for the sake of the argument that thinking is a mechanical process and then shows how that leads to the conclusion that thinking cannot be a mechanical process.We could put Leibniz’s exact same point into the language of 21st century neuroscience: imagine that you could enlarge the size of the brain (in a sense, we can already do with the help of the tools of modern neuroscience). If we were to enter into the brain (perhaps by shrinking ourselves down) we would see all kinds of physical processes going on (billions of neurons sending chemical signals back and forth). However, to observe all of these processes would not be to observe the conscious experiences of the person whose brain we were observing. That means that conscious experiences cannot reduce to physical brain mechanics. The simple point being made is that in conscious experience there exist all kinds of qualitative properties (qualia)—red, blue, the smell of coffee, the feeling of getting your back scratched—but none of these properties would be the properties observed in observing someone’s brain. All you will find on the inside is “parts that push one another” and never the properties that appear to us in first-person conscious experience.

The philosopher David Chalmers has coined a term for the problem that Leibniz was getting at. He calls it the hard problem of consciousness and contrasts it with easy problems of consciousness . The “easy” problems of mind science involve questions about how the brain carries out functions that enable certain kinds of behaviors—functions such as discriminating stimuli, integrating information, and using the information to control behavior. These problems are far from easy in any normal sense—in fact, they are some of the most difficult problems of science. Consider, for example, how speech production occurs. How is it that I decide what exactly to say in response to a criticism someone has just made of me? The physical processes involved are numerous and include the sounds waves of the person’s question hitting my eardrum, those physical signals being carried to the brain, that information being integrated with the rest of my knowledge and, eventually, my motor cortex sending certain signals to my vocal chords that then produce the sounds, “I think you’re misunderstanding what I mean when I said…” or whatever I end up saying. We are still a long way from understanding how this process works, but it seems like the kind of problem that can be solved by doing more of the same kinds of science that we’ve been doing. In short, solving easy problems involves understanding the complex causal mechanisms of the brain. In contrast, the hard problem is the problem of explaining how physical processes in the brain give rise to first- person conscious experience. The hard problem does not seem to be the kind of problem that could be solved by simply investigating in more detail the complex causal mechanism that is the brain. Rather, it seems to be a conceptual problem: how could it be that the colors, and sounds, the smells that constitute our first-person conscious experience of the world are nothing other than neurons firing electrical-chemical signals back and forth? As Leibniz pointed out over 250 years ago, the one seems to be a radically different kind of thing than the other.

In fact, it seems that a human being could have all of the functioning of normal human being and yet lack any conscious experience. There is a term for such a being: a philosophical zombie . Philosophical zombies are by definition being that are functionally indistinguishable from you or I but who lack any conscious experience. If we assume that it’s the functioning of the brain that causes all of our intelligent behaviors, then it isn’t clear what conscious experience could possibly add to our repertoire of intelligent behaviors. Philosophical zombies can help illustrate the hard problem of consciousness since if such creatures are theoretically possible then consciousness doesn’t seem to reduce to any kind of brain functioning. By hypothesis the brain of the normal human being and the brain of the philosophical zombie are identical. It’s just that the latter lacks consciousness whereas the former doesn’t. If this is possible then it does indeed seems to make consciousness seem like quite a mysterious thing for the physicalist.

There are two other famous thought experiments that illustrate the hard problem of consciousness: Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument and Thomas Nagel’s what it’s like to be a bat argument.

Nagel’s argument against physicalism turns on a colorful example: Could we (human beings) imagine what it would be like to be a bat? Although bats are still mammals, and thus not so different than human beings phylogenetically, their experience would seem to be radically different than ours. Bats echolocate around in the darkness, they eat bugs at night, and they sleep while hanging upside down. Human beings could try to do all these things, but even if they did, they would arguably not be experiencing these activities like a bat does. And yet it seems pretty clear that bats (being mammals) have some kind of subjective experience of the world—a “what it’s like” to be a bat. The problem is that although we can figure out all kinds of physical facts about bats—how they echolocate, how they catch insects in the dark, and so on—we cannot ever know what it’s like to be a bat. For example, although we could understand enough scientifically to be able to send signals to the bat that would trick it into trying to land on what it perceived as a ledge, we could not know what it’s like for the bat to perceive an object as a ledge. That is, we could understand the causal mechanisms that make the bat do what the bat does , but that would not help us to answer the question of what it’s like to experience the world the way a bat experiences the world . Nagel notes that it is characteristic of science to study physical facts (such as how the brain works) that can be understood in a third-person kind of way. That is, anyone with the relevant training can understand a scientific fact. If you studied the physics of echolocation and also a lot of neuroscience of bat brains, you would be able to understand how a bat does what a bat does. But this understanding would seem to bring you no closer to what it’s like to be a bat—that is, to the first-person perspective of the bat. We can refer to the facts revealed in first-person conscious experience as phenomenal facts . Phenomenal facts are things like what it’s like to see blue or smell coffee or experience sexual pleasure…or echolocate around the world in total darkness. Phenomenal facts are qualia, to use our earlier term. Nagel’s point is that if the phenomenal facts of conscious experience are only accessible from a first-person perspective and scientific facts are always third-person, then it follows that phenomenal facts cannot be grasped scientifically. Here is a reconstruction of Nagel’s argument:

  • The phenomenal facts presented in conscious experience are knowable only from the first-person (subjective) perspective.
  • Physical facts can always be known from third-person (objective) perspective.
  • Nothing that is knowable only from the first person perspective could be the same as (reduce to) something that is knowable from the third-person perspective.
  • Therefore, the phenomenal facts of conscious experience are not the same as physical facts about the brain. (from 1-3)
  • Therefore, physicalism is false. (from 4)

Nagel uses an interesting analogy to explain what’s wrong with physicalism—the claim that conscious states are nothing other than brain states. He imagines an ancient Greek saying that “matter is energy.” It turns out that this statement is true (Einstein’s famous E = mc 2 ) but an ancient Greek person could not have possibly understood how it could be true. The problem is that the ancient Greek person could not have had the conceptual resources needed for being able to understand what this statements means. Nagel claims that we are in the same position today when we say something like “conscious states are brain states” is true. It might be true, we just cannot understand what that could possibly mean yet because we don’t have the conceptual resources for understanding how this could be true. And the conceptual problem is what Nagel is trying to make clear in the above argument. This is another way at getting at the hard problem of consciousness.

Frank Jackson’s famous knowledge argument is similar and makes a similar point. Jackson imagines a super scientist, whom he dubs “Mary,” knows all the physical facts about color vision. Not only is she the world’s expert on color vision, she knows all there is to know about color vision. She can explain how certain wavelengths of light strike the cones in the retina and send signals via the optic nerve to the brain. She understands how the brain interprets these signals and eventually communicates with the motor cortex that sends signals to produce speech such as, “that rose is a brilliant color of red.” Mary understands all the causal processes of the brain that are connected to color vision. However, Mary understands this without ever having experienced any color. Jackson imagines that this is because she has been kept in a black and white room and has only ever had access to black and white things. So the books she reads and the things she investigates of the outside world (via a black and white monitor in her black and white room) are only ever black and white, never any other color. Now what will happen when Mary is released from the room and sees color for the first time? Suppose she is released and sees a red rose. What will she say? Jackson’s claim was that Mary will be surprised because she will learn something new: she will learn what it’s like to see red. But by hypothesis, Mary already knew all the physical facts of color vision. Thus, it follows that this new phenomenal fact that Mary learns (specifically, what it’s like to see red) is not the same as the physical facts about the brain (which by hypothesis she already knows).

  • Mary knows all the physical facts about color vision.
  • When Mary is released from the room and sees red for the first time, she learns something new—the phenomenal fact of what it’s like to see red.
  • Therefore, phenomenal facts are not physical facts. (from 1-2)
  • Therefore, physicalism is false. (from 3)

The upshot of both Nagel and Jackson’s arguments is that the phenomenal facts of conscious experience—qualia—are not reducible to brain states. This is the hard problem of consciousness and it is the mind-body problem that arises in particular for physicalism. The hard problem is the reason why physicalists can’t simply claim a victory over dualism by invoking Ockham’s razor. Ockham’s razor assumes that the two competing explanations equally explain all the facts but that one does so in a simpler way than the other. The problem is that if physicalism cannot explain the nature of consciousness—in particular, how brain states give rise to conscious experience—then there is something that physicalism cannot explain and, therefore, physicalists cannot so simply invoke Ockham’s razor.

Two responses to the hard problem

We will consider two contemporary responses to the hard problem: David Chalmers’s panpsychism and Daniel Dennett’s eliminativism . Although both Chalmers and Dennett exist within a tradition of philosophy that privileges scientific explanation and is broadly physicalist, they have two radically different ways of addressing the hard problem. Chalmers’s response accepts that consciousness is real and that solving the hard problem will require quite a radical change in how we conceptualize the world. On the other hand, Dennett’s response attempts to argue that the hard problem isn’t really a problem because it rests on a misunderstanding of the nature of consciousness. For Dennett, consciousness is a kind of illusion and isn’t ultimately real, whereas for Chalmers consciousness is the most real thing we know. The disagreement between these two philosophers returns as, again, to the most fundamental divide within the philosophy of mind: that between Cartesians, on the one hand, and behaviorists, on the other.

To understand Chalmers’s response to the hard problem , we must first understand what he means by a “basic entity.” A basic entity is one that science posits but that cannot be further analyzed in terms of any other kind of entity. Can you think of what kinds of entities would fit this description? Or which science you would look to in order to find basic entities? If you’re thinking physics, then you’re correct. Think of an atom. Originally, atoms were thought of as the most basic building blocks of the universe; the term “atom” literally means “uncuttable” (from the Greek “a” = not + “tomos” = cut ). So atoms were originally thought of as basic entities because there was nothing smaller. As we now know, this turned out to be incorrect because there were even smaller particles such as electrons, protons, quarks, and so on. But eventually physics will discover those basic entities that cannot be reduced to anything further. Mental states are not typically thought of as basic entities because they are studied by a higher order science—psychology and neuroscience. So mental states, such as my perception of the red rose, are not basic entities. For example, brain states are ultimately analyzable in terms of brain chemistry and chemistry, in turn, is ultimately analyzable in terms of physics (not that anyone would care to carry out that analysis!). But Chalmers’s radical claim is that consciousness is a basic entity. That is, the qualia—what it’s like to see red, smell coffee, and so on—that constitute our first-person conscious experience of the world cannot be further analyzed in terms of any other thing. They are what they are and nothing else. This doesn’t mean that our conscious experiences don’t correlate with the existence of certain brain states, according to Chalmers. Perhaps my experience of the smell of coffee correlates with a certain kind of brain state. But Chalmers’s point is that that correlation is basic; the coffee smell qualia are not the same thing as the brain state with which they might be correlated. Rather, the brain state and the conscious experience are just two radically different things that happen to be correlated. Whereas brain states reduce to further, more basic, entities, conscious states don’t. As Chalmers sees it, the science of consciousness should proceed by studying these correlations. We might discover all kinds of things about the nature of consciousness by treating the science of consciousness as irreducibly correlational. Chalmers suggests as an orienting principle the idea that consciousness emerges as a function of the “informational integration” of an organism (including artificially intelligent “organisms”). What is informational integration? In short, informational integration refers to the complexity of the organism’s control mechanism—its “brain.” Simple organisms have very few inputs from the environment and their “brains” manipulate that information in fairly simple ways. Take an ant, for example. We pretty much understand exactly how ants work and as far as animals go, they are pretty simple. We can basically already duplicate the level of intelligence of an ant with machines that we can build. So an informational integration of an ant’s brain is pretty low. A thermostat has some level of informational integration, too. For example, it takes in information about the ambient temperature of a room and then sends a signal to either turn the furnace on or off depending on the temperature reading. That is a very simple behavior and the informational integration inside the “brain” of a thermostat is very simple. Chalmers’s idea is that complex consciousness like our emerges when the informational integration is high—that is, when we are dealing with a very complex brain. The less complex the brain, the less rich the conscious experience. Here is a law that Chalmers suggests could orient the scientific study of consciousness:

image

This graph just says that as informational integration increases, so does the complexity of the associated conscious experience. Again, the conscious experience doesn’t reduce to informational integration, since that would only run headlong into the hard problem—a problem that Chalmers thinks is unsolvable.

The graph also says something else. As drawn, it looks like even information processing systems whose informational integration is low (for example, a thermostat or tree) also has some non-negligible level of conscious experience. That is a strange idea; no one really thinks that a thermostat is conscious and the idea that plants might have some level of conscious experience will seem strange to most. This idea is sometimes referred to as panpsychism (“pan” = all, “psyche” = mind)—there is “mind” distributed throughout everything in the world. Panpsychism is a radical departure from traditional Western views of the mind, which sees minds as the purview of animals and, on some views, of human beings alone . Chalmers’s panpsychism still draws a line between objects that process information (things like thermostats, sunflowers, and so on) and those that don’t (such as rocks), but it is still quite a radical departure from traditional Western views. It is not, however, a radical departure from all sorts of older, prescientific and indigenous views of the natural world according to which everything in the natural world, including plants and streams, as possessing some sort of spirit—a mind of some sort. In any case, Chalmers thinks that there are other interpretations of his view that don’t require the move to panpsychism. For example, perhaps conscious experience only emerges once information processing reaches a certain level of complexity. This interpretation would be more consistent with traditional Western views of the mind in the sense that one could specify that only organisms with a very complex information processing system, such as the human brain, possess conscious experience. (Graphically, based on the above graph, this would mean the lowest level of conscious experience wouldn’t start until much higher up the y-axis.)

Daniel Dennett’s response to the hard problem fundamentally differs from Chalmers’s. Whereas Chalmers posits qualia as real aspects of our conscious experience, Dennett attempts to deny that qualia exist. Rather, Dennett thinks that consciousness is a kind of illusion foisted upon us by our brain. Dennett’s perennial favorite example to begin to illustrate the illusion of consciousness concerns our visual field. From our perspective, the world presented to us visually looks to be unified in color and not possessing any “holes.” However, we know that this is not actually the case. The cones in the retina do not exist on the periphery and, as a result, you are not actually seeing colors in the objects at the periphery of your visual field. (You can test this by having someone hold up a new object on one side of your visual field and moving it back and forth until you are able to see the motion. Then try to guess the color of the object. Although you’ll be able to see the object’s motion, you won’t have a clue as to its color, if you do it correctly.) Although it seems to us as if there is a visual field that is wholly colored, it isn’t really that way. This is the illusion of consciousness that Dennett is trying to get us to acknowledge; things are not really as they appear. There’s another aspect of this illusion of our visual field: our blind spot. The location where the optic nerve exits the retina does not convey any visual information since there are no photoreceptors; this is known as the blind spot. There are all kinds of illustrations to reveal your blind spot . However, the important point that Dennett wants to make is that from our first-person conscious experience it never appears that there is any gap in our picture of the world. And yet we know that there is. This again is an illustration of what Dennett means by the illusion of conscious experience. Dennett does more than simply give fun examples that illustrate the strangeness of consciousness; he has also famously attacked the idea that there are qualia. Recall that qualia are the purely qualitative aspects of our conscious experiences—for example, the smell of coffee, the feeling of a painful sunburn (as opposed to the pain of a headache), or the feeling of an orgasm. Qualia are what are supposed to create problems for the physicalist since it doesn’t seem that that purely qualitative feels could be nothing more than the buzzing of neurons in the brain. Since qualia are what create the trouble for the physicalism and since Dennett is a physicalist, one can understand why Dennett targets qualia and tries to convince us that they don’t exist.

If you’re going to argue against something’s existence, the best way to do that is first precisely define what it is you are trying to deny. Then you argue that as defined such things cannot exist. This is exactly what Dennett does with qualia. [4] He defines qualia as the qualitative aspects of our first-person conscious experience that are a) irreducibly first-person (meaning that they are inaccessible to third-person, objective investigation) and b) intrinsic properties of one’s conscious experience (meaning that they are what they are independent of anything else). Dennett argues that these two properties (irreducibly first person and intrinsic) are in tension with each other—that is, there can’t be an entity which possesses both of these properties. But since both of these properties are part of the definition of qualia, it follows that qualia can’t exist—they’re like a square circle.

Change blindness is a widely studied phenomenon in cognitive psychology. Some of the demonstrations of it are quite amazing and have made it into the popular media many times over the last couple of decades. One of the most popular research paradigms to study change blindness is called the flicker paradigm. In the flicked paradigm, two images that are the same with the exception of some fairly obvious difference are exchanged in a fairly rapid succession, with a “mask” (black or white screen) between them. What is surprising is that it is very difficult to see even fairly large differences between the two images. So let’s suppose that you are viewing these flickering images and trying to figure out what the difference between them is but that you haven’t yet figured it out yet. As Dennett notes, there are of course all kinds of changes going on in your brain as these images flicker. For example, the photoreceptors are changing with the changing images. In the case of a patch of color that is changing between the two images, the cones in your retina are conveying different information for each image. Dennett asks: “Before you noticed the changing color, were your color qualia changing for that region?” The problem is that any way you answer this question spells defeat for the defender of qualia because either they have to give up (a) their irreducible subjectiveness or their intrinsicness (b). So suppose the answer to Dennett’s question is that your qualia are changing. In that case, you do not have any special or privileged access to your qualia, in which case they aren’t irreducibly subjective, since subjective phenomena are by definition something we alone have access to. So it seems that the defender of qualia should reject this answer. Then suppose, on the other hand, that your qualia aren’t changing. In that case, your qualia can’t change unless you notice them changing. But that makes it looks like qualia aren’t really intrinsic, after all since their reality is constituted by whether you notice them or not. And “noticings” are relational properties, not intrinsic properties. Furthermore, Dennett notes that if the existence of qualia depend on one’s ability to notice or report them, then even philosophical zombies would have qualia, since noticings/reports are behavioral or functional properties and philosophical zombies would have these by definition. So it seems that the qualia defender should reject this answer as well. But in that case, there’s no plausible answer that the qualia defender can give to Dennett’s question. Dennett’s argument has the form of a classic dilemma , as illustrated below:

image

Dennett thinks that the reason there is no good answer to the question is that the concept of qualia is actually deeply confused and should be rejected. But if we reject the existence qualia it seems that we reject the existence of the thing that was supposed to have caused problems for physicalism in the first place. Qualia are a kind of illusion and once we realize this, the only task will be to explain why we have this illusion rather than trying to accommodate them in our metaphysical view of the world. The latter is Chalmers’s approach whereas the former is Dennett’s.

Study questions

  • True or false: One popular way of thinking about how the mind works is by analogy with how a computer works: the brain is a complex syntactic engine that uses its own kind of language—a language that has original intentionality.
  • True or false: One good way of explaining how the mind understands things is to posit a little man inside the head that does the understanding.
  • True or false: The mind-body problem is the same, exact problem for both physicalism and dualism.
  • True or false: John Searle agrees with Alan Turing that the relevant test for whether a machine can think is the test of whether or not the machine behaves in a way that convinces us it is intelligent.
  • True or false: One good reply to the Chinese Room argument is just to note that we have exactly the same behavioral evidence that other people have minds as we would of a machine that passed the Turing Test.
  • True or false: According to interpretationism, mental representations are things we attribute to others in order to help us predict and explain their behaviors, and therefore it follows that mental representations must be real.
  • True or false: This chapter considers two different aspects of our mental lives: mental representation (or intentionality) and consciousness. But the two really reduce to the exact same philosophical problem of mind.
  • True or false: The hard problem is the problem of understanding how the brain causes intelligent behavior.
  • True of false: The knowledge argument is an argument against physicalism.
  • True or false: Dennett’s solution to the hard problem turns out to be the same as Chalmers’s solution.

For deeper thought

  • How does the hard problem differ from the easy problems of brain science?
  • If the Turing Test isn’t the best test for determining whether a machine is thinking, can you think of a better test?
  • According to physics, nothing in the world is really red in the way we perceive it. Rather, redness is just a certain wavelength of light that our senses interpret in a particular way (some other creature’s sensory system might interpret that same physical phenomenon in a very different way). By the same token, redness does not exist in the brain: if you are seeing red then I cannot also see the red by looking at your brain. In this case, where is the redness if it isn’t in the world and it also isn’t in the brain? And does this prove that redness is not a physical thing, thus vindicating dualism? Why or why not?
  • Could someone be in pain and yet not know it? If so, how would we be able to tell they were in pain? If not, then aren’t pain qualia real? And so wouldn’t that prove that qualia are real (if pain is)?
  • According to Chalmers’s view, is it theoretically possible for a machine to be conscious? Why or why not?
  • Readers who are familiar with the metaphysics of minds will notice that I have left out an important option: monism , the idea that there is ultimately only one kind of thing in the world and thus the mental and the physical do not fundamentally differ. Physicalism is one version of monism, but there are many others. Bishop George Berkeley’s idealism is a kind of monism as is the panpsychism of Leibniz and Spinoza . I have chosen to focus on physicalism for pedagogical reasons, because of its prominence in contemporary philosophy of mind, because of its intuitive plausibility to those living in an age of neuroscience, and because the nuances of the arguments for monism are beyond the scope of this introductory treatment of the problem. ↵
  • We could actually retell the Chinese room thought experiment in such a way that what the man inside the room was manipulating was strings of 1s and 0s (what is called “binary code”). The point remains the same in either case: whether the program is defined over Chinese characters or strings of 1s and 0s, from the perspective of the room, none of it has any meaning and there’s no understanding required in giving the appropriate outputs. ↵
  • Nothing has yet, claims to the contrary notwithstanding. ↵
  • Daniel Dennett, Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness. MIT Press. 2006. ↵

Introduction to Philosophy Copyright © by Matthew Van Cleave is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book

1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology

1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology

Philosophy, One Thousand Words at a Time

The Mind-Body Problem: What Are Minds?

Yellow-Red-Blue, 1925 by Wassily Kandinsky

Author: Jacob Berger Category: Philosophy of Mind and Language , Metaphysics Word count: 998

We have minds. We see the world around us; we feel happiness or sorrow; we can think, doubt, believe, remember, wonder, and hope. We also have bodies, which include our brains.

But what are minds? And what (if anything) is the relationship of the mind to the body/brain—or to anything in nature?

These questions constitute the so-called “mind-body problem,” a core issue in the philosophy of mind , the area of philosophy that studies phenomena such as thought, perception, emotion, memory, agency, and consciousness.

This essay introduces some of the most influential answers to these questions.

Yellow-Red-Blue, 1925 by Wassily Kandinsky

1. Varieties of Dualism

One popular reply to the mind-body problem is dualism , which holds that the mental is fundamentally distinct from anything physical. [1] There are several versions of dualism.

Substance dualism holds that minds are mental substances, whereas bodies are physical substances. A substance is something that can exist on its own. Physical substances take up space and time: tables, stars, atoms, and human bodies are physical substances. Substance dualism proposes that minds are substances that think, feel, and experience, but do not take up space and could exist without bodies. The view is akin to the religious idea of immaterial and immortal souls. [2]

Property dualism instead holds that the mental and the physical are different types of properties. A property is a way an object can be; a brown dog has the property of being brown. But properties cannot exist without something to modify: brownness cannot exist on its own. Property dualism holds that creatures may have distinct mental and physical properties, although they perhaps cannot have mental features without also having physical ones. [3]

Many considerations support some form of dualism. “Conceivability arguments,” for example, claim that we can imagine examples of minds without bodies, as in cases of non-physical ghosts, or examples of bodies without minds, such as philosophical zombies : creatures that are physically just like us, but lack conscious experience. If what we can imagine is a good guide to what’s possible, then it seems some type of dualism follows. But such inferences are questionable, since arguably not everything we can imagine is possible. For instance, one might imagine proving a mathematical theorem, even if it’s actually unprovable. [4]

There are also reasons to doubt dualism. A well-known objection to at least substance dualism is the “problem of interaction.” It is easy to understand causal interactions between physical things that take up space and can contact one another: a baseball can break a window. But minds and bodies interact too. For example, stubbing your toe is something physical in your body that causes you to feel pain in your mind, and your mental pain causes you to physically wince. But it is unclear how these mind-body interactions could occur, if mental states do not take up space and so cannot be in contact with the body. [5]

Many therefore defend views that hold that the mind is related to the body insofar as both are physical. [6]

2. The Identity Theory

A notable view that holds the mind is physical is the identity theory , which answers the mind-body problem by claiming that mental states are identical to—or the same things as—states of our brains. Brain-scan technology reveals that mentality is tightly correlated with the firing of neurons. The identity theory simply identifies these, holding that a headache is nothing more than a pattern of nociceptor activity, just as water is nothing but H 2 O. [7]

The identity theory avoids the problem of interaction, since it’s clear how the brain can impact one’s body and vice versa . But difficulties nonetheless arise. For example, it seems our mental states are what philosophers call “multiply realizable”: different sorts of physical systems can all exhibit the same types of mental states. After all, many people believe that things that have no brains at all , such as forms of alien life or artificial intelligence, might one day not only act as though they feel pleasure or fear, but genuinely experience those things. But if so, then such states can’t be identical with patterns of neural activity.

3. Functionalism

The identity theory explains minds in terms of what they are physically made of. But if we ask, “What is a shoe?” a response in terms of physical make-up is no help since shoes are multiply realizable by leather, plastic, or wood. It is better to characterize shoes functionally: shoes are items whose function is, among other things, to protect our feet when we walk. Functionalism likewise claims that mental states should be understood in terms of their function, that is, their characteristic causes and effects. [8]

Functionalism thereby answers the mind-body problem by maintaining that mental states are whatever states—be they bodily or otherwise—that play the relevant roles in whatever type of organism. Pains are states typically caused by bodily harms, and in turn typically cause behaviors such as wincing. Functionalism is compatible with mental states’ being nonphysical, but simplicity recommends that in humans such states are realized by brain activity. And if we one day build an artificially intelligent robot that experiences genuine pain, pains would be realized by states of its central processing unit that perform the functions of pain.

Functionalism allows for multiple realizability, but it faces problems. Many think, for example, that even if we knew all the physical and functional facts about some creatures such as bats—everything about their physiology and behavior—we still would not know what it’s like to be a bat. Only bats, it seems, can know what the bat experience of echolocation is like. But if that’s the case, then functionalism, which holds that we can understand minds wholly in terms of their functions, is false. [9]

Most contemporary philosophers of mind endorse some variety of dualism, identity theory, or functionalism. [10] But there are other theories of mind, [11] not to mention many versions of each of the above accounts, which have various advantages and disadvantages—too many for a short essay to explore! The mind-body problem thus remains one of the enduring puzzles of human thought. [12]

[1] For further discussion of both substance and property dualism and the arguments for and against them, see Calef (n.d.) and Robinson (2020).

[2] The most famous proponent of substance dualism in the history of philosophy is René Descartes; see Marc Bobro’s Descartes’ Meditations 1-3  and  Descartes’ Meditations 4-6 . 

[3] For a defense of property dualism, see, e.g., Chalmers (1996).

[4] For discussion of the relationship between conceivability and possibility in general, see Bob Fischer’s Modal Epistemology: Knowledge of Possibility & Necessity .

[5] This objection was arguably first raised for dualism by Descartes’ own student, Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia; see Princess Elizabeth and Descartes (1643-9/2019).

[6] It’s worth noting that some have instead endorsed idealism , the view that the mind and body are related insofar as both are actually mental . On that view, everything is a construction of perceptions and ideas–and so there are no physical bodies, at least as traditionally understood. But idealism remains a minority position. For discussion of it, see Addison Ellis’s Idealism Pt. 1: Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism .

[7] For a classic statement of identity theory, see, e.g., Smart (1959). For further discussion of the identity theory and the arguments for and against it, see Schneider (n.d.) and Smart (2007).

[8] For a classic statement of functionalism, see, e.g., Lewis (1972). For further discussion of functionalism and the arguments for and against it, see Polger (n.d) and Levin (2023).

[9] For this much-discussed argument, see Nagel (1974). For a similar argument against not only functionalism, but any view on which the mind is physical, see Tufan Kıymaz’s The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism .

[10] See, for example, Bourget & Chalmers (n.d.), which indicates which theories in the philosophy of mind respondents are sympathetic with.

[11] For example, an issue faced by many theories is that it is unclear why anything physical, including suitably developed brains, would be associated with (much less be identical with) mental phenomena. If atoms don’t have minds, then it is not obvious why any collection of them would have minds either. To avoid this problem, some endorse panpsychism —the view that all physical objects, from atoms to tables, exhibit mental properties; for more, see, e.g., the essays in Goff and Moran (2022). Similarly, some endorse neutral monism —the theory that both mental and physical phenomena are properties of a more fundamental neutral substance; for more, see, e.g., the essays in Alter and Nagasawa (2015).

And other accounts take starker views of the mind. A view that was popular in the early 20th Century was behaviorism , on which there are no “inner” mental states; mental states are nothing but observable behaviors or dispositions of bodies to act. Feeling happy, for example, simply is (the disposition to perform) the act of smiling. For a classic statement of behaviorism, see Ryle (1949). And eliminative materialism maintains that there is no mind-body relationship because there simply are no minds at all: “mental states” are things we should no longer think exist like witches or phlogiston. For a statement of the view, see Churchland (1981).

[12] The mind-body problem is also highly relevant to many other areas of philosophy and ethics. For example, views on the the metaphysical issue of “personal identity”–how (and whether) we exist as the same being over time, despite the many changes that occur to us—are often informed by views on what the mind is and its relation to the body: see Chad Vance’s Personal Identity and Kristin Seemuth Whaley’s Psychological Approaches to Personal Identity: Do Memories and Consciousness Make Us Who We Are? . And whether a being has a mind—and what this means–is often thought to be highly relevant to many ethical issues: see Jonathan Spelman’s Theories of Moral Considerability: Who and What Matters Morally? and Nathan Nobis’s The Ethics of Abortion .

Alter, T. & Nagasawa, Y. (eds.) (2015). Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism . Oxford University Press.

Bourget, D. & Chalmers, D. (n.d.). Consciousness: panpsychism, dualism, eliminativism, identity theory, or functionalism? Survey2020.philpeople.org.

Calef, Scott. (n.d.). Dualism and mind. Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy .

Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory . Oxford University Press.

Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

Goff, P. & Moran, R. (2022). Is consciousness everywhere? Essays on panpsychism . Imprint Academic.

Levin, Janet. (2023). Functionalism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.).

Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy , 50(3), 249–258.

Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83 (4), 435–450.

Polger, Thomas. (n.d.). Functionalism. Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy .

Princess Elizabeth and Descartes, R. (1643-9/2019). Correspondence. In Ariew, R. & Watkins, E. (eds.), Modern philosophy: An anthology of primary sources . Hackett Publishing.

Robinson, Howard. (2020). Dualism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.).

Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind . Hutchinson.

Schneider, Steven. (n.d.) Identity theory. Internet Encylopedia of Philosophy .

Smart, J. J. C. (2007). The mind/brain identity theory. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.).

Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. The Philosophical Review , 68 (2), 141–156.

Related Essays

Descartes’ Meditations 1-3  and  Descartes’ Meditations 4-6  by Marc Bobro 

Idealism Pt. 1: Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism  by Addison Ellis

The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism  by Tufan Kıymaz

Modal Epistemology: Knowledge of Possibility & Necessity by Bob Fischer

Artificial Intelligence: The Possibility of Artificial Minds by Thomas Metcalf

Personal Identity by Chad Vance

Psychological Approaches to Personal Identity: Do Memories and Consciousness Make Us Who We Are? by Kristin Seemuth Whaley

Theories of Moral Considerability: Who and What Matters Morally? by Jonathan Spelman

The Ethics of Abortion by Nathan Nobis

Translation

Pdf download.

Download this essay in PDF . 

About the Author

Jacob Berger is an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Lycoming College. He received his Ph.D. in Philosophy with a concentration in Cognitive Science at The Graduate Center of the City University of New York in 2013. His areas of specialization are philosophy of mind and cognitive science. jfberger.wixsite.com/home

Follow 1000-Word Philosophy on Facebook and Twitter and subscribe to receive email notifications of new essays at 1000WordPhilosophy.com

Share this:, 14 thoughts on “ the mind-body problem: what are minds ”.

  • Pingback: Objects and their Parts: The Problem of Material Composition – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Intentionality – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Artificial Intelligence: The Possibility of Artificial Minds – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Online Philosophy Resources Weekly Update - Daily Nous
  • Pingback: The Ethics of Abortion – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Theories of Moral Considerability: Who and What Matters Morally? – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Idealism Pt. 1: Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Modal Epistemology: Knowledge of Possibility & Necessity – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Descartes’ Meditations 1-3 – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Descartes’ Meditations 4-6 – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Animalism and Personal Identity: Are We Animals? – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Psychological Approaches to Personal Identity: Do Memories and Consciousness Make Us Who We Are? – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: Personal Identity: How We Exist Over Time – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology
  • Pingback: The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism – 1000-Word Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology

Comments are closed.

The Mind-Body Problem 3.0

  • First Online: 03 December 2020

Cite this chapter

the mind body problem essay

  • Marco J. Nathan 9  

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 17))

809 Accesses

This essay identifies two shifts in the conceptual evolution of the mind-body problem since it was molded into its modern form. The “mind-body problem 1.0” corresponds to Descartes’ ontological question: what are minds and how are they related to bodies? The “mind-body problem 2.0” reflects the core issue underlying much discussion of brains and minds in the twentieth century: can mental states be reduced to neural states? While both issues are no longer central to scientific research, the philosophy of mind ain’t quite done yet. In an attempt to recast a classic discussion in a more contemporary guise, I present a “mind-body problem 3.0.” In a slogan, this can be expressed as the question: how should we pursue psychology in the age of neuroscience?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

the mind body problem essay

Introduction

the mind body problem essay

Joseph Priestley: An Instructive Eighteenth Century Perspective on the Mind-Body Problem

the mind body problem essay

Mind and Body. Whose? Philosophy of Mind and the Systemic Approach

It is not trivial to find explicit statements of this assumption, partly because the mind-body problem is well-known and contemporary authors seldom bother to present it in full detail. Here are some representative quotes: “[T]he persuasive imagery of the Cartesian Theater [the idea of a centered locus of consciousness in the brain] keeps coming back to haunt us—laypeople and scientists alike—even after its ghostly dualism has been denounced and exorcized” (Dennett 1991 , p. 107). “The mind-body problem was posed in its modern form only in the seventeenth century, with the emergence of the conception of the physical world on which we are now all brought up” (Nagel 1995 , p. 97). “What exactly are the relations between the mental and the physical, and in particular how can there be causal relations between them? (…) This is the most famous problem that Descartes left us, and it is usually called the ‘mind-body problem”’ (Searle 2004 , p. 11).

Descartes’s conception of substance was strikingly nuanced (Rodriguez-Pereyra 2008 ).

To be sure, psychologists and philosophers had different agendas. To reflect this divergence, it is common to distinguish two strands of behaviorism (Fodor 1981 ). First, “philosophical” (also known as “logical” or “analytic”) behaviorism is associated with a thesis about the nature of mind and the meaning of mental states. Second, “psychological” or “methodological,” behaviorism emerged from an influential scientific methodology applied to psychology. For the sake of simplicity, I shall not distinguish between the two variants.

Again, I am unabashedly clashing together several variants of functionalism, such as Putnam’s “psycho-functionalism” and Armstrong’s “a priori functionalism” (Block 1978 ).

As Matteo Colombo has brought to my attention, the mind-body problem 1.0 could also be framed as a matter of reduction. On this reading, Descartes may be interpreted as providing a negative argument: minds cannot be reduced to bodies because they are altogether different substances. This is an effective strategy to bring Descartes into modern debates, finding some narrative continuity in the last four hundred years of philosophy of mind. Still, this operation should be understood, from our contemporary perspective. From historical standpoint, Descartes’ target was not reduction. He was interested in ontological questions about the nature of minds and their interactions with bodies. Relatedly, eliminative materialists prefer to talk about “elimination” as opposed to “reduction.” Yet, the former concept can be straightforwardly treated as a limiting case of the latter.

To be sure, Nagel’s own conception of reduction was subtler, and its proper interpretation remains a matter of controversy (Fazekas 2009 ; Klein 2009 ). Nevertheless, for present purposes I am less interested in Nagel’s actual views, and more in how his model of reduction was received and discussed within philosophy (Fodor 1974 ; Kitcher 2003 ).

An analogous, equally heated debate emerged in the philosophy of science. Putnam’s square-peg example was developed and extended to real-life scientific scenarios in biology (Kitcher 2003 ), psychology (Fodor 1974 ), and the social sciences (Garfinkel 1981 ). Post-positivist neo-reductionists disagreed. Authors such as Waters ( 1990 ), Sober ( 1999 , 2000 ), Rosenberg ( 2006 ), and Strevens ( 2008 ) stressed that, while micro-explanations are often unnecessarily complex or anti-economical, they do emphasize crucial details that are typically presupposed implicitly or taken for granted at the macro-level.

Chemero and Silberstein motivate their provocative claim as follows: “The two main debates in the philosophy of mind over the last few decades about the essence of mental states (they are physical, functional, phenomenal, etc.) and over mental context have run their course. Positions have hardened; objections are repeated; theoretical filigrees are attached. These relatively armchair discussions are being replaced by empirically oriented debates in philosophy of cognitive and neural sciences” ( 2008 , p. 1).

“The scientific practices based on the two-level view (functional/cognitive /computational’ vs. neural/mechanistic/implementation) are being replaced by scientific practices based on the view that there are many levels of mechanistic organization. No one level has a monopoly on cognition proper. Instead, different levels are more or less cognitive depending on their specific properties. The different levels and the disciplines that study them are not autonomous from one another. Instead, the different disciplines contribute to the common enterprise of constructing multilevel mechanistic explanations of cognitive phenomena. In other words, there is no longer any meaningful distinction between cognitive psychology and the relevant portions of neuroscience—they are merging to form cognitive neuroscience” (Boone and Piccinini 2016b , p. 1510).

Armstrong, D. M. (1981). The nature of mind . Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Google Scholar  

Baetu, T. M. (2015). The completeness of mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 82 , 775–786.

Article   Google Scholar  

Batterman, R. W., & Rice, C. C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81 , 349–376.

Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research (2nd ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account . Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. In C. Savage (Ed.), Perception and Cognition (pp. 261–325). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016a). Mechanistic abstraction. Philosophy of Science, 83 , 686–697.

Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016b). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193 , 1509–1534.

Burge, T. (2007). Foundations of mind . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Burge, T. (2013). Modest dualism. In Cognition through understanding. Philosophical essays (Vol. 3, pp. 471–488). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Chapter   Google Scholar  

Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search for a fundamental theory . New York: Oxford University Press.

Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75 , 1–27.

Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191 , 127–153.

Chomsky, N. (2000). New horizons in the study of language and mind . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Chomsky, N. (2002). On nature and language . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78 (2), 67–90.

Churchland, P. (1986). Neurophilosophy . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience . New York: Oxford University Press.

Craver, C. F., & Kaplan, D. M. (2018). Are more details better? On the norms of completeness for mechanistic explanation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71 (1), 287–319.

Davidson, D. (1970). Mental events. In L. Foster & J. Swanson (Eds.), Experience and theory (pp. 79–101). London: Duckworth.

Del Pinal, G., & Nathan, M. J. (2013). There and up again: On the uses and misuses of neuroimaging in psychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 30 (4), 233–252.

Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained . Boston: Little Brown and Co..

Dupré, J. (2012). Processes of life: Essays in the philosophy of biology . New York: Oxford University Press.

Fazekas, P. (2009). Reconsidering the role of bridge laws in inter-theoretic relations. Erkenntnis, 71 , 303–322.

Fodor, J. A. (1968). Psychological explanation . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28 , 97–115.

Fodor, J. A. (1981). The mind-body problem. Scientific American, 244 , 114–123.

Garfinkel, A. (1981). Forms of explanation . New Haven: Yale University Press.

Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2013). Genetics and philosophy: An introduction . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Heil, J. (2013). Philosophy of mind: A contemporary introduction . New York: Routledge.

Hornsby, J. (1997). Simple mindedness: In defense of naive naturalism in the philosophy of mind . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. The Philosophical Quarterly, 32 , 127–136.

Jaworski, W. (2016). Structure and the metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind-body problem . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Kim, J. (1999). Mind in a physical world . Cambridge: MIT Press.

Kim, J. (2011). Philosophy of Mind . Boulder: Westview.

Kitcher, P. (2003). In Mendel’s mirror. Philosophical reflections on biology . New York: Oxford University Press.

Klein, C. (2009). Reduction without reductionism: A defense of Nagel on connectability. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59 (234), 39–53.

Koslicki, K. (2018). Form, matter, substance . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Krickel, B., & Kohar, M. (this volume). Compare and contrast: How to assess the completeness of mechanistic explanation .

Levy, A. (2014). What was Hodgkin and Huxley’s achievement? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65 , 469–492.

Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information . New York: Freeman.

Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science . New York: Harcourt Brace.

Nagel, T. (1995). Searle: Why we are not computers. In Other minds (pp. 96–110). New York: Oxford University Press.

Nathan, M. J. (2012). The varieties of molecular explanation. Philosophy of Science, 79 (2), 233–254.

Nathan, M. J. (under contract). Black boxes: How science turns ignorance into knowledge . New York: Oxford University Press.

Nathan, M. J., & Del Pinal, G. (2016). Mapping the mind: Bridge laws and the psycho-neural interface. Synthese, 193 (2), 637–657.

Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47 , 44–50.

Putnam, H. (1965). Brains and behaviour. In R. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 24–36). Oxford: Blackwell.

Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. Capitan & D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophy and our mental life. In Mind, language, and reality (pp. 291–303). New York: Cambridge University Press.

Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2008). Descartes’ substance dualism and his independence notion of substance. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 46 (1), 69–90.

Rosenberg, A. (2006). Darwinian reductionism: Or how to stop worrying and love molecular biology . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind . London: Hutchinson & Co..

Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J. R. (2004). Mind: A brief introduction . New York: Oxford University Press.

Smart, J. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68 , 141–156.

Sober, E. (1999). The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 66 , 542–564.

Sober, E. (2000). Philosophy of biology (2nd ed.). Boulder: Westview.

Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. An account of scientific explanation . Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Waters, C. K. (1990). Why the anti-reductionist consensus won’t survive: The case of classical Mendelian genetics. Proceedings to the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association , 125–39.

Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101 , 254–280.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is grateful to Bill Anderson, John Bickle, Fabrizio Calzavarini, Matteo Colombo, Guie Del Pinal, Carrie Figdor, Matteo Grasso, Philipp Haueis, Mika Smith, Marco Viola, and two reviewers for constructive comments on various versions of this essay, and to Stefano Mannone for designing the image. Earlier drafts were presented at the University of Milan, Mississippi State University, the University of Turin Neural Mechanisms Webinar Series, and the University of Denver. All audiences provided valuable feedback.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

University of Denver, Denver, CO, USA

Marco J. Nathan

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco J. Nathan .

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Department of Letter, Philosophy, Communication, University of Bergamo LLC, Turin, Italy

Fabrizio Calzavarini

Department of Philosophy and Education, University of Turin, Turin, Italy

Marco Viola

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Nathan, M.J. (2021). The Mind-Body Problem 3.0. In: Calzavarini, F., Viola, M. (eds) Neural Mechanisms. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 17. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_12

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-54092-0_12

Published : 03 December 2020

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-030-54091-3

Online ISBN : 978-3-030-54092-0

eBook Packages : Religion and Philosophy Philosophy and Religion (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

Descartes and the Discovery of the Mind-Body Problem

the mind body problem essay

Consider the human body, with everything in it, including internal and external organs and parts — the stomach, nerves and brain, arms, legs, eyes, and all the rest. Even with all this equipment, especially the sensory organs, it is surprising that we can consciously perceive things in the world that are far away from us. For example, I can open my eyes in the morning and see a cup of coffee waiting for me on the bedside table. There it is, a foot away, and I am not touching it, yet somehow it is making itself manifest to me. How does it happen that I see it? How does the visual system convey to my awareness or mind the image of the cup of coffee?

Jacket cover for "The Mind-Body Problem" by Jonathan Westphal

The answer is not particularly simple. Very roughly, the physical story is that light enters my eyes from the cup of coffee, and this light impinges on the two retinas at the backs of the eyes. Then, as we have learned from physiological science , the two retinas send electrical signals past the optic chiasm down the optic nerve. These signals are conveyed to the so-called visual cortex at the back of the brain. And then there is a sort of a miracle. The visual cortex becomes active, and I see the coffee cup. I am conscious of the cup, we might even say, though it is not clear what this means and how it differs from saying that I see the cup.

One minute there are just neurons firing away, and no image of the cup of coffee. The next, there it is; I see the cup of coffee, a foot away. How did my neurons contact me or my mind or consciousness, and stamp there the image of the cup of coffee for me?

It’s a mystery. That mystery is the mind-body problem.

Our mind-body problem is not just a difficulty about how the mind and body are related and how they affect one another. It is also a difficulty about how they can be related and how they can affect one another. Their characteristic properties are very different, like oil and water, which simply won’t mix, given what they are.

There is a very common view which states that the French philosopher René Descartes discovered, or invented, this problem in the 17th century. According to Descartes, matter is essentially spatial, and it has the characteristic properties of linear dimensionality. Things in space have a position, at least, and a height, a depth, and a length, or one or more of these. Mental entities, on the other hand, do not have these characteristics. We cannot say that a mind is a two-by-two-by-two-inch cube or a sphere with a two-inch radius, for example, located in a position in space inside the skull. This is not because it has some other shape in space, but because it is not characterized by space at all.

The difficulty is not merely that mind and body are different. It is that they are different in such a way that their interaction is impossible.

What is characteristic of a mind, Descartes claims, is that it is conscious , not that it has shape or consists of physical matter. Unlike the brain, which has physical characteristics and occupies space, it does not seem to make sense to attach spatial descriptions to it. In short, our bodies are certainly in space, and our minds are not, in the very straightforward sense that the assignation of linear dimensions and locations to them or to their contents and activities is unintelligible. That this straightforward test of physicality has survived all the philosophical changes of opinion since Descartes, almost unscathed, is remarkable.

This issue aroused considerable interest following the publication of Descartes’s 1641 treatise “ Meditations on First Philosophy ,” the first edition of which included both Objections to Descartes, written by a group of distinguished contemporaries, and the philosopher’s own Replies . Though we do find in the “Meditations” itself the distinction between mind and body, drawn very sharply by Descartes, in fact he makes no mention of our mind-body problem. Descartes is untroubled by the fact that, as he has described them, mind and matter are very different: One is spatial and the other not, and therefore one cannot act upon the other. Descartes himself writes in his Reply to one of the Objections:

The whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the soul and the body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents them from being able to act on each other.

Descartes is surely right about this. The “nature” of a baked Alaska pudding, for instance, is very different from that of a human being, since one is a pudding and the other is a human being — but the two can “act on each other” without difficulty, for example when the human being consumes the baked Alaska pudding and the baked Alaska in return gives the human being a stomachache.

the mind body problem essay

The difficulty, however, is not merely that mind and body are different. It is that they are different in such a way that their interaction is impossible because it involves a contradiction. It is the nature of bodies to be in space, and the nature of minds not to be in space, Descartes claims. For the two to interact, what is not in space must act on what is in space. Action on a body takes place at a position in space, however, where the body is. Apparently Descartes did not see this problem. It was, however, clearly stated by two of his critics, the philosophers Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and Pierre Gassendi. They pointed out that if the soul is to affect the body, it must make contact with the body, and to do that it must be in space and have extension. In that case, the soul is physical, by Descartes’s own criterion.

In a letter dated May 1643, Princess Elisabeth wrote to Descartes,

I beg you to tell me how the human soul can determine the movement of the animal spirits in the body so as to perform voluntary acts—being as it is merely a conscious substance. For the determination of the movement seems always to come about from the moving body’s being propelled—to depend on the kind of impulse it gets from what it sets in motion, or again, on the nature and shape of this latter thing’s surface. Now the first two conditions involve contact, and the third involves that the impelling [thing] has extension; but you utterly exclude extension from your notion of soul, and contact seems to me incompatible with a thing’s being immaterial.

Propulsion and “the kind of impulse” that set the body in motion require contact, and “the nature and shape” of the surface of the site at which contact is made with the body require extension. We need two further clarifications to grasp this passage.

The first is that when Princess Elisabeth and Descartes mention “animal spirits” (the phrase is from the ancient Greek physician and philosopher Galen) they are writing about something that plays roughly the role of signals in the nerve fibers of modern physiology. For Descartes, the animal spirits were not spirits in the sense of ghostly apparitions, but part of a theory that claimed that muscles were moved by inflation with air, the so-called balloonist theory. The animal spirits were fine streams of air that inflated the muscles. (“Animal” does not mean the beasts here, but is an adjective derived from “anima,” the soul.)

The second clarification is that when Princess Elisabeth writes that “you utterly exclude extension from your notion of soul,” she is referring to the fact that Descartes defines mind and matter in such a way that the two are mutually exclusive. Mind is consciousness, which has no extension or spatial dimension, and matter is not conscious, since it is completely defined by its spatial dimensions and location. Since mind lacks a location and spatial dimensions, Elisabeth is arguing, it cannot make contact with matter. Here we have the mind-body problem going at full throttle.

It was Descartes’ critics who discovered the problem, right in his solution to it.

Descartes himself did not yet have the mind-body problem ; he had something that amounted to a solution to the problem. It was his critics who discovered the problem, right in Descartes’s solution to the problem, although it is also true that it was almost forced on them by Descartes’s sharp distinction between mind and body. The distinction involved the defining characteristics or “principal attributes,” as he called them, of mind and body, which are consciousness and extension.

Though Descartes was no doubt right that very different kinds of things can interact with one another, he was not right in his account of how such different things as mind and body do in fact interact. His proposal, in “The Passions of the Soul,” his final philosophical treatise, was that they interact through the pineal gland, which is, he writes, “the principal seat of the soul” and is moved this way and that by the soul so as to move the animal spirits or streams of air from the sacs next to it. He had his reasons for choosing this organ, as the pineal gland is small, light, not bilaterally doubled, and centrally located. Still, the whole idea is a nonstarter, because the pineal gland is as physical as any other part of the body. If there is a problem about how the mind can act on the body, the same problem will exist about how the mind can act on the pineal gland, even if there is a good story to tell about the hydraulics of the “pneumatic” (or nervous) system.

We have inherited the sharp distinction between mind and body, though not exactly in Descartes’s form, but we have not inherited Descartes’s solution to the mind-body problem. So we are left with the problem, minus a solution. We see that the experiences we have, such as experiences of color, are indeed very different from the electromagnetic radiation that ultimately produces them, or from the activity of the neurons in the brain. We are bound to wonder how the uncolored radiation can produce the color, even if its effects can be followed as far as the neurons in the visual cortex. In other words, we make a sharp distinction between physics and physiology on the one hand, and psychology on the other, without a principled way to connect them. Physics consists of a set of concepts that includes mass , velocity , electron , wave , and so on, but does not include the concepts red , yellow , black , and the like. Physiology includes the concepts neuron , glial cell , visual cortex , and so on, but does not include the concept of color. In the framework of current scientific theory, “red” is a psychological term, not a physical one. Then our problem can be very generally described as the difficulty of describing the relationship between the physical and the psychological, since, as Princess Elisabeth and Gassendi realized, they possess no common relating terms.

Was there really no mind-body problem before Descartes and his debate with his critics in 1641? Of course, long before Descartes, philosophers and religious thinkers had spoken about the body and the mind or soul, and their relationship. Plato, for example, wrote a fascinating dialogue, the Phaedo, which contains arguments for the survival of the soul after death, and for its immortality. Yet the exact sense in which the soul or mind is able to be “in” the body, and also to leave it, is apparently not something that presented itself to Plato as a problem in its own right. His interest is in the fact that the soul survives death, not how, or in what sense it can be in the body. The same is true of religious thinkers. Their concern is for the human being, and perhaps for the welfare of the body, but mainly for the welfare and future of the human soul. They do not formulate a problem with the technical precision that was forced on Princess Elisabeth and Gassendi by Descartes’s neatly formulated dualism.

Something important clearly had changed in our intellectual orientation during the mid-17th century. Mechanical explanations had become the order of the day, such as Descartes’s balloonist explanation of the nervous system, and these explanations left unanswered the question of what should be said about the human mind and human consciousness from the physical and mechanical point of view.

What happens, if anything, for example, when we decide to do even such a simple thing as to lift up a cup and take a sip of coffee? The arm moves, but it is difficult to see how the thought or desire could make that happen. It is as though a ghost were to try to lift up a coffee cup. Its ghostly arm would, one supposes, simply pass through the cup without affecting it and without being able to cause it or the physical arm to go up in the air.

It would be no less remarkable if merely by thinking about it from a few feet away we could cause an ATM to dispense cash. It is no use insisting that our minds are after all not physically connected to the ATM, and that is why it is impossible to affect the ATM’s output — for there is no sense in which they are physically connected to our bodies. Our minds are not physically connected to our bodies! How could they be, if they are nonphysical? That is the point whose importance Princess Elisabeth and Gassendi saw more clearly than anyone had before them, including Descartes himself.

Jonathan Westphal is a Permanent Member of the Senior Common Room at University College, Oxford, and the author of “ The Mind-Body Problem ,” from which this article is adapted.

Plato's cave metaphor illustrates the cognitive trap of ignorance, where we may be unaware of the limitations of our understanding.

|

The author of “Whiteness” traces the evolution of race as a social and political instrument, from its beginnings in ancient hierarchies through European colonial expansion and into contemporary times.

|

To look up at the sky and see a road for the gods, a great river, or the final resting place of your ancestors is deeply human.

|

Dennett's classic story raises deep philosophical questions about identity and consciousness.

|

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction

Psychophysical monism

Property dualism, psychophysical dualism.

Benedict de Spinoza

mind-body problem

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • Table Of Contents

Benedict de Spinoza

mind-body problem , in the philosophy of mind and metaphysics , the problem of explaining how mental events arise from or interact with physical events. Historically, three types of theory have been most influential: psychophysical monism, property dualism, and psychophysical dualism.

According to psychophysical monism, the physical and mental properties of human beings are properties of the same thing: of their bodies or of parts of their bodies, such as the cerebral cortex or the nervous system . Psychophysical monists also believe that the mental properties of a thing are completely determined by its physical properties. Thus, a perfect physical duplicate of a thinking, feeling human being would, of necessity, have exactly the same mental properties as that human being. Psychophysical monists are almost all proponents of identity theory , according to which mental events (i.e., the gain or loss of a mental property) are the same as or identical to physical events (i.e., the gain or loss of a physical property).

the mind body problem essay

Property dualists agree with psychophysical monists that the physical and mental properties of human beings are properties of the same things (human bodies or their parts) but reject the other thesis of the monists, that the physical properties of a thing necessarily determine its mental properties. They hold that it is at least metaphysically possible to assume that there are two beings with identical physical properties but different mental properties. That possibility, moreover, implies that mental properties are nonphysical properties—hence the term property dualism . The so-called double-aspect theory of the Dutch philosopher Benedict de Spinoza (1632–77) and the German philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) is probably best categorized as a form of property dualism.

According to psychophysical dualism, the physical properties of human beings are properties of their bodies and the mental properties of human beings are properties of their minds or souls —a person’s mind or soul being an immaterial substance wholly distinct from the physical substance that is that person’s body.

Among psychophysical dualists, dualistic interactionists hold that the body and the mind interact—that the mind causally affects the body and the body causally affects the mind. Dualistic interactionists seem to be committed to the position that the physical world is not causally closed—i.e., that physical events cannot always be completely explained by reference to earlier physical events and the laws of physics . That position, however, would seem to be inconsistent with the conservation laws (e.g., conservation of energy and conservation of momentum ) that are fundamental to modern physics.

Other psychophysical dualists, known as occasionalists , have maintained that the apparent causal interaction between mind and body is only apparent: mental and physical changes are coordinated by the direct action of God. (Thus, the act of willing to move one’s arm is an “occasion,” but not a cause, of the movement of one’s arm.) Like interactionists, however, occasionalists seem to be committed to the thesis that there are physical events that cannot be explained in terms of earlier physical events.

the mind body problem essay

The theory of preestablished harmony , due to the German rationalist philosopher Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716), in some ways resembles occasionalism but avoids the problem of inconsistency with the closure of the physical world by postulating separate physical and mental realms, each of which unfolds deterministically with the passage of time according to its own laws; the two realms do not interact but have been created (by God) in such a way that they are in perfect harmony with each other.

the mind body problem essay

The rather unclear position called epiphenomenalism is sometimes categorized as a form of psychophysical dualism according to which the body affects the mind but the mind does not affect the body. Thus, when a human being wills a certain bodily movement and that movement occurs, the movement is caused entirely by prior physical states of the body. The corresponding act of will, however, is also caused by prior physical states. As a result, the act of will seems to its subject to be the cause of the movement. It is, however, probably better to think of epiphenomenalism not as a form of psychophysical dualism but as a form of property dualism according to which both mental events (the gain or loss of a mental property) and physical events (the gain or loss of a physical property) are entirely caused by physical events. Partly because few philosophers have thought of themselves as epiphenomenalists, it is difficult to categorize that view under any familiar type of philosophical theory of mind. The best-known modern epiphenomenalist was the English biologist Thomas Henry Huxley (1825–95).

  • Advanced Search
  • All Categories
  • Metaphysics and Epistemology
  • Epistemology
  • Metaphilosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Value Theory
  • Applied Ethics
  • Meta-Ethics
  • Normative Ethics
  • Philosophy of Gender, Race, and Sexuality
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Value Theory, Miscellaneous
  • Science, Logic, and Mathematics
  • Logic and Philosophy of Logic
  • Philosophy of Biology
  • Philosophy of Cognitive Science
  • Philosophy of Computing and Information
  • Philosophy of Mathematics
  • Philosophy of Physical Science
  • Philosophy of Social Science
  • Philosophy of Probability
  • General Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Science, Misc
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy
  • Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy
  • 17th/18th Century Philosophy
  • 19th Century Philosophy
  • 20th Century Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy, Misc
  • Philosophical Traditions
  • African/Africana Philosophy
  • Asian Philosophy
  • Continental Philosophy
  • European Philosophy
  • Philosophy of the Americas
  • Philosophical Traditions, Miscellaneous
  • Philosophy, Misc
  • Philosophy, Introductions and Anthologies
  • Philosophy, General Works
  • Teaching Philosophy
  • Philosophy, Miscellaneous
  • Other Academic Areas
  • Natural Sciences
  • Social Sciences
  • Cognitive Sciences
  • Formal Sciences
  • Arts and Humanities
  • Professional Areas
  • Other Academic Areas, Misc
  • About PhilArchive
  • Frequently Asked Questions
  • OAI Handler
  • Journal policies
  • Code of conduct
  • Create an account

The Mind-Body Problem

Author's profile.

the mind body problem essay

Archival history

Reprint years.

Phiosophy Documentation Center

  • [email protected]

PSYCHOLOGY4U

mind over body, eastern body western mind

The Mind-Body Problem. Essay

The relationship between the mind and the body has been an essentially philosophical question since the rise of philosophy. Dualism was a primary subject of interest for such philosophers as Aristotle, Plato, Descartes, Avicenna, and so forth. Muslim philosophers (Avicenna, Ibn Tufayl) claim that the human’s mind and body are distinct substances and can exist separately. Avicenna demonstrates such an assumption with the help of his famous flying man’ thought experiment, while Ibn Tufayl shares this knowledge as an axiom. 

Muslim physicians might be considered the most influential philosopher-scientists of the medieval world. One of them, Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā)  proposed to imagine a person created by God in mid-air: “in good condition but with his sight veiled and his limbs outstretched so that he is touching nothing, not even his own body” (Adamson). Furthermore, this person has no restored memories, i.e., his memory is empty yet. According to Avicenna, this person would not be blank and entirely devoid of sensory experience. Avicenna presumes that such a human being would be still self-aware.

Moreover, it seems that the concept of self-awareness is prominent in Avicenna’s philosophical ideas. Philosopher claims that all human beings are always self-aware, even when they are asleep or focused on something else (Adamson). It is quite possible that Avicenna conducted this experiment to show his disagreement with Aristotle’s concept of the soul as a part of the body. Aristotle claims the inseparability of the soul and the mind from the body. Furthermore, the philosopher is convinced that the soul relates to vegetative and animal functions. Therefore, if someone is not able to experience the body and its sensations, he or she will not have any access to the soul. On the contrary, Avicenna’s main thought is that bodies can be discovered only by senses, while the soul can be perceived at any time through self-awareness and various mental activities. Avicenna claims that the flying man would always have access to    

Avicenna made his famous “flying man” assumption to set a challenge to materialists: “show me how a body could be aware of itself without using sensation to do so” (Adamson). Mind and  soul are parts of the human body, but they can exist even if the body does not feel any sensations. The mind can be aware of its existence, think about different concepts, and create abstract models without sensations of the body. Furthermore, mind hypothetically can perceive its presence when it has no stored memories. As a result, Avicenna’s experiment slightly reminds Descartes’ concept of material and mental substances that exist separately and independently. 

Another mentioning of the mind-problem question in Muslim philosophy is connected to Ibn Tufayl’s, who wrote a philosophical romance  Hayy ibn Yaqzan . Ibn Tufayl does not claim that the soul is distinct from the human body. Instead, he takes the independence of the human soul for granted. He also poses a range of questions concerning the moment when a human’s soul should leave the body. Furthermore, it seems that Ibn Tufayl presumes that the soul has power over the body. 

Mentioned Muslim philosophers were convinced that the soul and the body are two separate elements.

Picture of Anton Kurapov

Anton Kurapov

PhD, a professor assistant at Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv. Fascinated by the role of psychology in lives of people and simply astonished by the complexity of the brain and its functions.

Share this post:

the mind body problem essay

How CBT Helps in Grieving: Incredible Real-Life Success Stories

the mind body problem essay

Cognitive-Behavioral Approaches to Professional Identity Crisis

the mind body problem essay

CBT Strategies for Overcoming Complicated Grief: Here Is How It Works Now

the mind body problem essay

Professional Identity Crisis: Recognizing and Overcoming Challenges

dmts therapy

DTMS Therapy vs. Traditional Methods: Which is Better?

detox from weed fast

Detox from Weed Fast & Safely Now: Secrets to Avoid Common Pitfalls

CBT to Cope with the Loss of a Loved One

Use CBT to Cope with the Loss of a Loved One Now: The Real Power of CBT for Grief

the mind body problem essay

Explore the Components of Professional Identity: Key Elements

Write for us Guest posts

Privacy Policy Terms of Conditions  

Breadcrumbs Section. Click here to navigate to respective pages.

History of the Mind-Body Problem

History of the Mind-Body Problem

DOI link for History of the Mind-Body Problem

Get Citation

History of the Mind-Body Problem is a collection of new essays by leading contributors on the various concerns that have given rise to and informed the mind-body problem in philosophy. The essays in this stellar collection discuss famous philosophers such as Aristotle, Aquinas and Descartes and cover the subjects of the origins of the qualia and intentionality.

TABLE OF CONTENTS

Chapter | 12  pages, introduction, chapter 1 | 21  pages, the musical, the magical, and the mathematical soul, chapter 2 | 36  pages, the soul’s relation to the body: thomas aquinas, siger of brabant and the parisian debate on monopsychism m . w. f . stone, chapter 3 | 41  pages, how cartesian was descartes, chapter 4 | 20  pages, the emergence of the cartesian mind, chapter 5 | 17  pages, intentionality or phenomenology descartes and the objects of thought, chapter 6 | 21  pages, ‘a tumbling-ground for whimsies’ the history and contemporary role of the conscious/unconscious contrast, chapter 7 | 26  pages, the origins of qualia, chapter 8 | 37  pages, beyond dispute: sense-data, intentionality and the mind–body problem m . g . f . martin.

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms & Conditions
  • Cookie Policy
  • Taylor & Francis Online
  • Taylor & Francis Group
  • Students/Researchers
  • Librarians/Institutions

Connect with us

Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067 5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG © 2024 Informa UK Limited

The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology Essay

  • To find inspiration for your paper and overcome writer’s block
  • As a source of information (ensure proper referencing)
  • As a template for you assignment

Introduction

The views of philosophers, the views of physicians, the views of psychologists from various schools of thought, the author’s views.

The mind-body problem is a very old one. In Western culture, its roots go back in history to the philosophical theories of Ancient Greece. The crux of the problem is evident from its name: what is the relationship between the mind and the body? How do they correlate and work together? The reasons for the problem’s emergence are not hard to imagine. There is a large qualitative gap between what we see as our physical bodies, and what we experience happening in our heads. And, once the question was asked, numerous thinkers attempted to answer it.

In this paper, we will briefly describe the history of the problem by discussing what various prominent philosophers and physicians thought about it. After that, we will discuss the views of the most important schools of psychological thought on this problem. We will also state what the author of this paper believes regarding this problem.

Ancient Greek philosophers already were trying to answer a question similar to the mind-body problem. However, for them it was formulated in different terms; they asked not about the mind, but rather about the soul (ψυχή, psyche), something that made a thing alive. The soul was perceived as something extremely light and associated with breath. For instance, Thales associated it with air, while Heraclitus thought of it as of fire (Copleston, 1993).

More complicated theories emerged with Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. Socrates’ opinions are known to us only thanks to the writings of other philosophers; in Plato’s Phaedo , Socrates talks to his friends and convinces them that a human’s soul is immortal. Plato believed that the soul is an immortal substance which is, in fact, imprisoned in the body (Plato, n.d.). Aristotle paid somewhat more attention to the problem of the soul. His treatise, On the Soul , discusses the issue. Aristotle believed the soul to be a principle of all the living things; even plants had souls.

However, unlike Plato, he thought it to be dependent on the body (Aristotle, n.d.). For a well-known Neo-Platonist Plotinus, who somewhat combined the teachings of Plato and Aristotle, the universe consisted of the One, a source of everything in the world, the Mind, all the eternal truths, and the Soul, which was a manifestation of the Mind in living beings (Copleston, 1993). Therefore, the Ancient Greek philosophy already associated the soul and the mind.

The medieval philosophy, strongly aligned with Christian theology, paid much attention to the issues of the soul. A prominent medieval philosopher Thomas Aquinas ties the issue of the body and the soul to the issue of the matter and form. For him, the body and the soul are united – as much like the seal and the wax are; the mind does not interact with the body, because they are one. Regardless, the soul is immortal and capable of existing without the body (McInerny & O’Callaghan, 2014).

Rene Descartes, one of the most prominent representatives of the 17 th -century rationalism, had strictly distinguished the soul and the body. His expression, “cogito ergo sum,” “I think, therefore I am,” is known to many. He believed that the soul is an immortal substance created by God, completely immaterial, responsible for all the cognitive activity of a person. At the same time, he believed the soul to interact with the body by pushing a part of the pineal gland in the brain (Lokhorst, 2013).

John Locke was the one to bring the notion of consciousness as an important one, defining a person as a conscious, thinking thing. He believed that, at birth, a person’s mind was a tabula rasa, but then it was filled with numerous ideas coming from our experience. The body, however, was also important, and it interacted with the mind (Uzgalis, 2012).

For David Hume, the mind’s contents came from perceptions, but a priori ideas were also possible. The mind was apparently a set of perceptions. However, the mind existed within the body, and without the body, there was no mind. This dualism is incomplete, however; for instance, he asked what led people to the very conviction that the body exists (Flage, 1983).

For Immanuel Kant, the mind perceived the outer world through the prism of innate, a priori forms of sensibility, such as space and time. The body was a spatial object, but, given that space was a form of sensibility, any spatial object, including the body, was a phenomenon, and it could never be known whether this object really existed and what it was like; it remained an inaccessible thing-in-itself (Rohlf, 2010).

It is also important to consider the attitudes of influential physicians towards the mind-body problem. A prominent Ancient Greek physician, Galen, believed that the mind and the body were a single unit, not separate things. He was convinced that individual parts of the body were responsible for different functions and that the mind was among such functions (Hankinson, 1991).

Hermann von Helmholtz, an influential German physician and physicist of the 19 th century, had a strictly materialistic view on the mind-body problem. He, along with his colleagues, believed that a living body was a machine that only worked according to the laws of physics. For him, no distinct types of energy were responsible for the existence of life (Bowler & Morus, 2005, p. 177-178). Another important figure of the 19 th century, an English biologist Thomas Huxley, had rather similar views.

He was an epiphenomenalist, i.e., he believed that the mind was produced by the brain, so all the emotions, wishes, feelings were reflections of the needs of the physical body (Huxley, 1874). A prominent Russian physician of the 19-20 th centuries Ivan Pavlov also aligned towards the monistic solution of the mind-body problem, believing that the mind and the body were identical and that the mind originated in the higher nervous activity (Windholz, 1997).

The establishment of psychology as an academic discipline is associated with the creation of a laboratory in Germany in 1879 by Wilhelm Wundt. Wundt began the psychological school of voluntarism. Voluntarists believed that consciousness could be broken down into separate components without the whole being lost. For them, the mind interacted with the body, but the nature of this interaction was difficult to grasp (Hergenhahn & Henley, 2014).

Edward Titchener, a Wundt’s student who created the school of structuralism, believed that the mind was comprised only of experience gathered throughout a person’s life and that this experience was organized into a structure of some kind; he wished to describe its elements. Titchener and structuralists also adopted the voluntarists’ stance on the mind-body problem, holding to dualism, a view that the mind and the body are two different entities. However, they were not interested in studying the relationship between them (Wertheimer, 2012).

Another school of psychology, functionalism, was interested in the study of the functions of the mind and consciousness. For them, the mind was a set of functions, and the mental states were performed by the body. Therefore, they did not hold to the traditional mind-body dualism (Hergenhahn & Henley, 2014).

The representatives of the school of behaviourism believed that a person’s (or, in fact, any organism’s) behaviour was a response to the physical stimuli they received from the outside. In fact, they rejected the need to study consciousness at all. The mind-body problem was not relevant to them, for they believed consciousness was a physical process accompanying behaviour (Hergenhahn & Henley, 2014).

Psychoanalysis, on the other hand, is interested in studying the human’s subconsciousness to help the mentally ill. They believe the unconscious mind to be the cause of behaviours and mental conditions. For psychoanalysts, bodies “cannot be reduced to mere collections of chemicals”; mind and body are mutually permeating entities (Brearley, 2002, p. 442-443). However, the mind still remains the main area of psychoanalysts’ interest.

The school of humanistic psychology emerged in the 1960s to combine the problems researched by deterministic psychoanalysts and behaviourists while leaving space for free will and the spirit. For them, mind, body, and spirit were aspects of a single person, and no split between mind and body existed (Schneider, Pierson, & Bugental, 2015, p. 656-657).

The school of psychobiology combined the principles of behaviourism and psychoanalysis and developed the idea that the mind and psychological phenomena are grounded in the physiological causes. The representatives of this school realize the mutual dependence of mind and body and strive to exactly determine the relationship between the two by using both psychological and biological variables in their studies (for instance, see Kemeny (2003) or Stein (2009)).

Finally, the school of cognitive psychology, one of the newest schools of thought, studies the cognitive processes of the brain (such as attention, memory, concept formation, reasoning, etc.), and employs the achievements of numerous academic disciplines such as neuroscience, information technologies and artificial intelligence, linguistics, philosophy and anthropology. Their view on the mind-body problem can be called similar to that of psychobiology; the mind is grounded in the biological causes (Hergenhahn & Henley, 2014).

The author of this paper is inclined towards the point of view of the schools of psychobiology and cognitive psychology. We believe that the mind is grounded in the body. In fact, it is our opinion that they are a single entity, even though it is not (yet) understood how exactly mental processes emerge from the body. Distinguishing between mind and body is required because it is necessary to denote different aspects of this entity.

As it was possible to see, the mind-body problem was studied as early as in the times of Ancient Greece. Ancient Greek philosophers relied on speculative reasoning alone to explain the nature of ψυχή, the soul that was responsible not only for the mind but was believed to make a creature alive. The philosophers of the Middle Ages perceived the issue through the prism of Christian theology. Descartes and the rationalism of the 17 th century proclaimed a strict mind-body dualism; still, the notions of consciousness and perceptions were made important by Locke and Hume.

The psychologists adopted different stances towards the problem; for voluntarists and functionalists, mind and body were two different entities that interacted, but the nature of this interaction was not interesting to them. Behaviourists and psychoanalysts had almost opposing views, believing that either the body and behaviour or the mind and the unconscious were of primal importance, respectively. Humanistic psychologists believed that mind, body, and spirit were a single entity. Finally, psychobiology and cognitive psychology perceive the mind as emerging from the body but believe that essentially they are one.

Aristotle. (n.d.). On the soul . Web.

Brearley, M. (2002). Psychoanalysis and the body-mind problem. Ratio, 15 (4), 429-443. Web.

Bowler, P. J., & Morus, I. R. (2005). Making modern science: A historical survey . Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Copleston, F. (1993). A history of philosophy. Volume 1: Greece and Rome: from the pre-Socratics to Plotinus . New York, NY: Image Books, Doubleday. Web.

Flage, D. E. (1983). Review of “Hume’s philosophy of mind.” Hume Studies, 9 (1), 82-88. Web.

Hankinson, R. J. (1991). Galen’s Anatomy of the Soul. Phronesis, 36 (2), 197-233. Web.

Hergenhahn, B. R., & Henley, T. B. (2014). An introduction to the history of psychology (7th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.

Huxley, T. H. (1874). On the hypothesis that animals are automata, and its history . Web.

Kemeny, M. E. (2003). The psychobiology of stress. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12 (4), 124-129. Web.

Lokhorst, G.-J. (2013). Descartes and the pineal gland . Web.

McInerny, R., & O’Callaghan, J. (2014). Saint Thomas Aquinas . Web.

Plato. (n.d.). Phaedo . Web.

Rohlf, M. (2010). Immanuel Kant . Web.

Schneider, K. J., Pierson, J. F., & Bugental, J. F. T. (Eds.). (2015). The handbook of humanistic psychology: Theory, research, and practice (2nd ed.). London, UK: SAGE Publications.

Stein, D. J. (2009). The psychobiology of resilience. CNS Spectrums, 14 (2, Suppl. 3), 41-47.

Uzgalis, W. (2012). John Locke . Web.

Wertheimer, M. (2012). A brief history of psychology (5th ed.). New York, NY: Psychology Press, Taylor & Francis Group.

Windholz, G. (1997). Pavlov and the mind-body problem . Integrative Physiological and Behavioral Science, 32 (2), 149-159. Web.

  • Psychological Environment: Getho’s Case
  • Depressive Food Intake Disorder
  • Monistic Views on the Mind-Body Debate
  • Cartesian Dualism and The Mind-Body Problem
  • Descartes’ Mind-Body Problem
  • Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder: Gender Variations
  • Stress, Its Causes and Effects Relationship
  • Stress Impacts on the Human Development
  • Biological Psychology: Development and Theories
  • Working Memory Concept: Psychological Views
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2020, June 10). The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-mind-body-problem-in-the-history-of-psychology/

"The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology." IvyPanda , 10 June 2020, ivypanda.com/essays/the-mind-body-problem-in-the-history-of-psychology/.

IvyPanda . (2020) 'The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology'. 10 June.

IvyPanda . 2020. "The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology." June 10, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-mind-body-problem-in-the-history-of-psychology/.

1. IvyPanda . "The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology." June 10, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-mind-body-problem-in-the-history-of-psychology/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology." June 10, 2020. https://ivypanda.com/essays/the-mind-body-problem-in-the-history-of-psychology/.

IvyPanda uses cookies and similar technologies to enhance your experience, enabling functionalities such as:

  • Basic site functions
  • Ensuring secure, safe transactions
  • Secure account login
  • Remembering account, browser, and regional preferences
  • Remembering privacy and security settings
  • Analyzing site traffic and usage
  • Personalized search, content, and recommendations
  • Displaying relevant, targeted ads on and off IvyPanda

Please refer to IvyPanda's Cookies Policy and Privacy Policy for detailed information.

Certain technologies we use are essential for critical functions such as security and site integrity, account authentication, security and privacy preferences, internal site usage and maintenance data, and ensuring the site operates correctly for browsing and transactions.

Cookies and similar technologies are used to enhance your experience by:

  • Remembering general and regional preferences
  • Personalizing content, search, recommendations, and offers

Some functions, such as personalized recommendations, account preferences, or localization, may not work correctly without these technologies. For more details, please refer to IvyPanda's Cookies Policy .

To enable personalized advertising (such as interest-based ads), we may share your data with our marketing and advertising partners using cookies and other technologies. These partners may have their own information collected about you. Turning off the personalized advertising setting won't stop you from seeing IvyPanda ads, but it may make the ads you see less relevant or more repetitive.

Personalized advertising may be considered a "sale" or "sharing" of the information under California and other state privacy laws, and you may have the right to opt out. Turning off personalized advertising allows you to exercise your right to opt out. Learn more in IvyPanda's Cookies Policy and Privacy Policy .

Pardon Our Interruption

As you were browsing something about your browser made us think you were a bot. There are a few reasons this might happen:

  • You've disabled JavaScript in your web browser.
  • You're a power user moving through this website with super-human speed.
  • You've disabled cookies in your web browser.
  • A third-party browser plugin, such as Ghostery or NoScript, is preventing JavaScript from running. Additional information is available in this support article .

To regain access, please make sure that cookies and JavaScript are enabled before reloading the page.

Home — Essay Samples — Philosophy — Rene Descartes — Descartes and Dualism: An Analysis of Mind-Body Problem

test_template

Descartes and Dualism: an Analysis of Mind-body Problem

  • Categories: Rene Descartes

About this sample

close

Words: 784 |

Published: Sep 7, 2023

Words: 784 | Pages: 2 | 4 min read

Table of contents

Introduction, descartes' dualism, interaction between mind and body, criticisms and challenges, contemporary views.

Image of Dr. Charlotte Jacobson

Cite this Essay

To export a reference to this article please select a referencing style below:

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr Jacklynne

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Philosophy

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

2 pages / 1039 words

4.5 pages / 1955 words

3 pages / 1324 words

2.5 pages / 1168 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Rene Descartes

The statement "Cogito, ergo sum" in Latin, or "I think, therefore I am" in English, is one of the most famous and enduring philosophical phrases in history. Coined by the French philosopher René Descartes in the 17th century, it [...]

The famous philosophical proposition "Cogito, ergo sum," or "I think, therefore I am," is arguably one of the most enduring and influential ideas in the history of philosophy. Coined by the French philosopher René Descartes in [...]

In his Allegory of the Cave, Plato asks us to consider that the world we are living is the equivalent of a cave; in order for us to enter into this “sensible realm” of truth and knowledge we must actively pursue these values. In [...]

Rene Descartes presents in his Meditations on First Philosophy the idea of dualism, the belief that the body and the soul exist separately from each other. Physical human bodies are composed of cells, tissue, blood, organs, [...]

The synopsis of The Matrix and the readings from Platos and Descartes all have similarities as well as differences. One thing that all three of these writings have in common is the topic. The synopsis of The Matrix and the [...]

In Rene Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy, he argues that the senses do not accurately help us understand the world. Descartes writes that he has begun to doubt all of his ideas. He decides that all those ideas come [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

the mind body problem essay

Department of Philosophy, The University of Chicago

The Mind/Body Problem

Phil 21726 the mind/body problem.

What are minds, what are bodies, and what is the relation between minds and bodies? The reason these questions represent a problem is that a. the questions are of fundamental significance but that b. no answer to them is easy to defend. In this course we will try to understand this problem, and to arrive at some answers. To help us toward this goal we will read important philosophical work on the subject--some older writings (Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hume), but with a focus on work in the last eighty years (including Wittgenstein, Ryle, Anscombe, Davidson, Smart, Place, Armstrong, Kripke, Putnam, Searle, Lewis, Nagel, Dennett, Dretske, The Churchlands, Jackson, McGinn, Block, Kim, Chalmers).

IMAGES

  1. Mind-Body Problem Essay

    the mind body problem essay

  2. The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology

    the mind body problem essay

  3. Mind body problem essay

    the mind body problem essay

  4. Mind Body Problem in Philosophical Works

    the mind body problem essay

  5. Mind Body Problem Functionalism Essay

    the mind body problem essay

  6. Sensation and Perception: The Mind-Body Problem

    the mind body problem essay

VIDEO

  1. The Mind-Body Problem Explained

  2. Mind-body problem

  3. Mind body problem part two

  4. Introducing Philosophy

  5. 201, mind-body problem group 2, city

  6. Exploring the Mind-Body Problem

COMMENTS

  1. PDF The mind-body problem

    THE MIND-BODY PROBLEM Tim Crane Department of Philosophy, University College London. The mind-body problem is the problem of explaining how our mental states, events and processes—like beliefs, actions and thinking—are related to the physical states, events and processes in our bodies. A question of the form, 'how is A related to B ...

  2. The mind-body problem

    The mind-body problem is best thought of not as a single problem but as a set of problems that attach to different views of the mind. For physicalists, the mind-body problem is the problem of explaining how conscious experience can be nothing other than a brain activity—what has been called " the hard problem.".

  3. PDF The Mind-Body-Body Problem

    Introduction. There are at least three distinct philosophical problems about the mind and the body: (1) the Traditional Mind-Body Problem; (2) the Body Problem; and (3) the Mind-Body-Body Problem. The Traditional Mind-Body Problem is how to account for the existence and character of the mental—specifically, consciousness, in the sense of ...

  4. The Mind-Body Problem: What Are Minds?

    These questions constitute the so-called "mind-body problem," a core issue in the philosophy of mind, the area of philosophy that studies phenomena such as thought, perception, emotion, memory, agency, and consciousness. This essay introduces some of the most influential answers to these questions. Yellow-Red-Blue, 1925 by Wassily Kandinsky. 1.

  5. The Mind-Body Problem 3.0

    The mind-body problem is typically presented as a single, monolithic, perduring puzzle that has framed discussions of mental states, at least, since Descartes molded the question into its current form. 1 This essay examines, and, ultimately, rejects this presupposition. Over time, the content of the mind-body problem has shifted substantially.

  6. Descartes and the Discovery of the Mind-Body Problem

    The French philosopher René Descartes is often credited with discovering the mind-body problem, a mystery that haunts philosophers to this day. The reality is more complicated than that. Consider the human body, with everything in it, including internal and external organs and parts — the stomach, nerves and brain, arms, legs, eyes, and all ...

  7. Mind-body problem

    Mind-body problem, in the philosophy of mind and metaphysics, the problem of explaining how mental events arise from or interact with physical events. Historically, three types of theory have been most influential: psychophysical monism, property dualism, and psychophysical dualism. According to.

  8. Mind in a Physical WorldAn Essay on the Mind-Body Problem and Mental

    This book, based on Jaegwon Kim's 1996 Townsend Lectures, presents the philosopher's current views on a variety of issues in the metaphysics of the mind—in particular, the mind-body problem, mental causation, and reductionism. Kim construes the mind-body problem as that of finding a place for the mind in a world that is fundamentally physical.

  9. Tim Crane, The Mind-Body Problem

    Abstract. The mind-body problem is the problem of explaining how our mental states, events and processes—like beliefs, actions and thinking—are related to the physical states, events and processes in our bodies. A question of the form, 'how is A related to B?' does not by itself pose a philosophical problem.

  10. Mind-body problem

    The mind-body problem is a philosophical problem concerning the relationship between thought and consciousness in the human mind and body. [1][2] It is not obvious how the concept of the mind and the concept of the body relate. For example, feelings of sadness (which are mental events) cause people to cry (which is a physical state of the ...

  11. Mind in a physical world : an essay on the mind-body problem and mental

    This book, based on Jaegwon Kim's 1996 Townsend Lectures, presents the philosopher's current views on a variety of issues in the metaphysics of the mind - in particular, the mind-body problem, mental causation, and reductionism. Kim construes the mind-body problem as that of finding a place for the mind in a world that is fundamentally physical.

  12. The Mind-Body Problem. Essay

    Essay - Psychology4u. The relationship between the mind and the body has been an essentially philosophical question since the rise of philosophy. Dualism was a primary subject of interest for such philosophers as Aristotle, Plato, Descartes, Avicenna, and so forth. Muslim philosophers (Avicenna, Ibn Tufayl) claim that the human's mind and ...

  13. The mind-body problem

    Abstract. The mind-body problem is the problem of explaining how the happenings of our mental lives are related to physical states, events and processes. Proposed solutions to the problem vary by whether and how they endorse physicalism, the claim that mental states are ultimately "nothing over and above" physical states, and by how they ...

  14. The Mind-body Problem: The Enigma of Consciousness

    One of the classical approaches to the mind-body problem is dualism, famously championed by René Descartes. Dualism posits that the mind and body are fundamentally distinct entities. According to Descartes, the mind is a non-physical, immaterial substance, while the body is composed of physical matter. This view implies that mental phenomena ...

  15. Mind-body problem essay

    Essay about the mind body problem and dualism hibdon riley hibdon professor kroll november 17, 2021 (revised) the problem there is an philosophical issue that. Skip to document. ... The mind-body problem is such an obscure topic to analyze, because the mind itself is so complex, that trying to break it down is just flat out exhausting. ...

  16. History of the Mind-Body Problem

    History of the Mind-Body Problem is a collection of new essays by leading contributors on the various concerns that have given rise to and informed the mind-body problem in philosophy. The essays in this stellar collection discuss famous philosophers such as Aristotle, Aquinas and Descartes and cover the subjects of the origins of the qualia and intentionality.

  17. The Mind-Body Problem in the History of Psychology Essay

    A prominent medieval philosopher Thomas Aquinas ties the issue of the body and the soul to the issue of the matter and form. For him, the body and the soul are united - as much like the seal and the wax are; the mind does not interact with the body, because they are one. Regardless, the soul is immortal and capable of existing without the ...

  18. The Mind-Body Problem Essay (docx)

    2 The Mind-Body Problem: A Philosophical Essay The mind-body problem has perplexed philosophers and scientists for centuries, diving into the fundamental nature of human consciousness and the relationship between our mental experiences and the physical world (Mason, 2023). This philosophical mystery raises many questions about the very essence of our existence.

  19. Descartes and Dualism: an Analysis of Mind-body Problem

    The mind-body problem remains a fascinating and complex area of philosophical inquiry, and Descartes' dualism, despite its criticisms, has played a pivotal role in shaping the discourse surrounding it.Whether through substance dualism, property dualism, materialism, or idealism, philosophers continue to grapple with the profound questions surrounding the nature of consciousness and its ...

  20. Mind body problem essay

    The mind-body problem is one of the most prominent issues in the philosophy of mind. T ill this day, scholars debate the veracity of opposing stances on the relationship between one' s. thoughts and consciousness to the physical body. T he mind-body problem seeks to answer the. question of whether the mind and body are truly distinct entities.

  21. The Mind/Body Problem

    PHIL 21726 The Mind/Body Problem. What are minds, what are bodies, and what is the relation between minds and bodies? The reason these questions represent a problem is that a. the questions are of fundamental significance but that b. no answer to them is easy to defend. In this course we will try to understand this problem, and to arrive at ...

  22. The Mind-Body Distinction

    René Descartes: The Mind-Body Distinction. One of the deepest and most lasting legacies of Descartes' philosophy is his thesis that mind and body are really distinct—a thesis now called "mind-body dualism." He reaches this conclusion by arguing that the nature of the mind (that is, a thinking, non-extended thing) is completely different from that of the body (that is, an extended, non ...

  23. Mind-Body Problem Essay

    The Mind/Body Problem The mind is about mental processes, thought and consciousness. The body is about the physical aspects of the brain-neurons and how the brain is structured. The mind-body problem is about how these two interact. In this paper I am going to talk about whether the mind and body are separate or the same thing.