SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Dreams and Dreaming

Dreams and dreaming have been discussed in diverse areas of philosophy ranging from epistemology to ethics, ontology, and more recently philosophy of mind and cognitive science. This entry provides an overview of major themes in the philosophy of sleep and dreaming, with a focus on Western analytic philosophy, and discusses relevant scientific findings.

1.1 Cartesian dream skepticism

1.2 earlier discussions of dream skepticism and why descartes’ version is special, 1.3 dreaming and other skeptical scenarios, 1.4 descartes’ solution to the dream problem and real-world dreams, 2.1 are dreams experiences, 2.2 dreams as instantaneous memory insertions, 2.3 empirical evidence on the question of dream experience, 2.4 dreams and hallucinations, 2.5 dreams and illusions, 2.6 dreams as imaginative experiences, 2.7 dreaming and waking mind wandering, 2.8 the problem of dream belief, 3.1 dreaming as a model system and test case for consciousness research, 3.2 dreams, psychosis, and delusions, 3.3 beyond dreams: dreamless sleep experience and the concepts of sleep, waking, and consciousness, 4. dreaming and the self, 5. immorality and moral responsibility in dreams, 6.1 the meaning of dreams, 6.2 the functions of dreaming, 7. conclusions, other internet resources, related entries, 1. dreams and epistemology.

Dream skepticism has traditionally been the most famous and widely discussed philosophical problem raised by dreaming (see Williams 1978; Stroud 1984). In the Meditations , Descartes uses dreams to motivate skepticism about sensory-based beliefs about the external world and his own bodily existence. He notes that sensory experience can also lead us astray in commonplace sensory illusions such as seeing things as too big or small. But he does not think such cases justify general doubts about the reliability of sensory perception: by taking a closer look at an object seen under suboptimal conditions, we can easily avoid deception. By contrast, dreams suggest that even in a seemingly best-case scenario of sensory perception (Stroud 1984), deception is possible. Even the realistic experience of sitting dressed by the fire and looking at a piece of paper in one’s hands (Descartes 1641: I.5) is something that can, and according to Descartes often does, occur in a dream.

There are different ways of construing the dream argument. A strong reading is that Descartes is trapped in a lifelong dream and none of his experiences have ever been caused by external objects (the Always Dreaming Doubt ; see Newman 2019). A weaker reading is that he is just sometimes dreaming but cannot rule out at any given moment that he is dreaming right now (the Now Dreaming Doubt ; see Newman 2019). This is still epistemologically worrisome: even though some of his sensory-based beliefs might be true, he cannot determine which these are unless he can rule out that he is dreaming. Doubt is thus cast on all of his beliefs, making sensory-based knowledge slip out of reach.

Cartesian-style skeptical arguments have the following form (quoted from Klein 2015):

  • If I know that p , then there are no genuine grounds for doubting that p .
  • U is a genuine ground for doubting that p .
  • Therefore, I do not know that p .

If we apply this to the case of dreaming, we get:

  • If I know that I am sitting dressed by the fire, then there are no genuine grounds for doubting that I am really sitting dressed by the fire.
  • If I were now dreaming, this would be a genuine ground for doubting that I am sitting dressed by the fire: in dreams, I have often had the realistic experience of sitting dressed by the fire when I was actually lying undressed in bed!
  • Therefore, I do not know that I am now sitting dressed by the fire.

Importantly, both strong and weak versions of the dream argument cast doubt only on sensory-based beliefs, but leave other beliefs unscathed. According to Descartes, that 2+3=5 or that a square has no more than 4 sides is knowable even if he is now dreaming:

although, in truth, I should be dreaming, the rule still holds that all which is clearly presented to my intellect is indisputably true. (Descartes 1641: V.15)

By Descartes’ lights, dreams do not undermine our ability to engage in the project of pure, rational enquiry (Frankfurt 1970; but see Broughton 2002).

Dream arguments have been a staple of philosophical skepticism since antiquity and were so well known that in his objections to the Meditations , Hobbes (1641) criticized Descartes for not having come up with a more original argument. Yet, Descartes’ version of the problem, more than any other, has left its mark on the philosophical discussion.

Earlier versions tended to touch upon dreams just briefly and discuss them alongside other examples of sensory deception. For example, in the Theaetetus (157e), Plato has Socrates discuss a defect in perception that is common to

dreams and diseases, including insanity, and everything else that is said to cause illusions of sight and hearing and the other senses.

This leads to the conclusion that knowledge cannot be defined through perception.

Dreams also appear in the canon of standard skeptical arguments used by the Pyrrhonists. Again, dreams and sleep are just one of several conditions (including illness, joy, and sorrow) that cast doubt on the trusthworthiness of sensory perception (Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers; Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism) .

Augustine ( Against the Academics ; Confessions) thought the dream problem could be contained, arguing that in retrospect, we can distinguish both dreams and illusions from actual perception (Matthew 2005: chapter 8). And Montaigne ( The Apology for Raymond Sebond ) noted that wakefulness itself teems with reveries and illusions, which he thought were even more epistemologically worrisome than nocturnal dreams.

Descartes devoted much more space to the discussion of dreaming and cast it as a unique epistemological threat distinct from both waking illusions and evil genius or brain-in-a-vat-style arguments. His claim that he has often been deceived by his dreams implies he also saw dreaming as a real-world (rather than merely hypothetical) threat.

This is further highlighted by the intimate, first-person style of the Meditations . Their narrator is supposed to exemplify everyone’s epistemic situation, illustrating the typical defects of the human mind. Readers are further drawn in by Descartes’ strategy of moving from commonsense examples towards more sophisticated philosophical claims (Frankfurt 1970). For example, Descartes builds up towards dream skepticism by first considering familiar cases of sensory illusions and then deceptively realistic dreams.

Finally, much attention has been devoted to several dreams Descartes reportedly had as a young man. Some believe these dreams embodied theoretical doubts he developed in the Discourse and Meditations (Baillet 1691; Leibniz 1880: IV; Cole 1992; Keefer 1996). Hacking (2001:252) suggests that for Descartes, dream skepticism was not just a philosophical conundrum but a source of genuine doubt. There is also some discussion about the dream reports’ authenticity (Freud 1940; Cole 1992; Clarke 2006; Browne 1977).

In the Meditations , after discussing the dream argument, Descartes raises the possibility of an omnipotent evil genius determined to deceive us even in our most basic beliefs. Contrary to dream deception, Descartes emphasizes that the evil genius hypothesis is a mere fiction. Still, it radicalizes the dream doubt in two respects. One, where the dream argument left the knowability of certain general truths intact, these are cast in doubt by the evil genius hypothesis . Two, where the dream argument, at least on the weaker reading, involves just temporary deception, the evil genius has us permanently deceived.

One modernized version, the brain-in-a-vat thought experiment, says that if evil scientists placed your brain in a vat and stimulated it just right, your conscious experience would be exactly the same as if you were still an ordinary, embodied human being (Putnam 1981). In the Matrix -trilogy (Chalmers 2005), Matrixers live unbeknownst to themselves in a computer simulation. Unlike the brain-in-a-vat , they have bodies that are kept alive in pods, and flaws in the simulation allow some of them to bend its rules to their advantage.

Unlike dream deception, which is often cast as a regularly recurring actuality (cf. Windt 2011), brain-in-a-vat-style arguments are often thought to be merely logically or nomologically possible. However, there might be good reasons for thinking that we actually live in a computer simulation (Bostrom 2003), and if we lend some credence to radical skeptical scenarios, this may have consequences for how we act (Schwitzgebel 2017).

Even purely hypothetical skeptical scenarios may enhance their psychological force by capitalizing on the analogy with dreams. Clark (2005) argues that the Matrix contains elements of “industrial-strength deception” in which both sensory experience and intellectual functioning are exactly the same as in standard wake-states, whereas other aspects are more similar to the compromised reasoning and bizarre shifts that are the hallmark of dreams.

At the end of the Sixth Meditation , Descartes suggests a solution to the dream problem that is tied to a reassessment of what it is like to dream. Contrary to his remarks in the First Meditation , he notes that dreams are only rarely connected to waking memories and are often discontinuous, as when dream characters suddenly appear or disappear. He then introduces the coherence test:

But when I perceive objects with regard to which I can distinctly determine both the place whence they come, and that in which they are, and the time at which they appear to me, and when, without interruption, I can connect the perception I have of them with the whole of the other parts of my life, I am perfectly sure that what I thus perceive occurs while I am awake and not during sleep. (Meditation VI. 24)

For all practical purposes, he has now found a mark by which dreaming and waking can be distinguished (cf. Meditation I.7), and even if the coherence test is not fail-safe, the threat of dream deception has been averted.

Descartes’ remarks about the discontinuous and ad hoc nature of many dreams are backed up by empirical work on dream bizarreness (see Hobson 1988; Revonsuo & Salmivalli 1995). Still, many of his critics were not convinced this helped his case against the skeptic. Even if Descartes’ revised phenomenological description characterizes most dreams, one might occasionally merely dream of successfully performing the test (Hobbes 1641), and in some dreams, one might seem to have a clear and distinct idea but this impression is false (Bourdin 1641). Both the coherence test and the criterion of clarity and distinctness would then be unreliable.

How considerations of empirical plausibility impact the dream argument continues to be a matter of debate. Grundmann (2002) appeals to scientific dream research to introduce an introspective criterion: when we introspectively notice that we are able to engage in critical reflection, we have good reason to think that we are awake and not dreaming. However, this assumes critical reasoning to be uniformly absent in dreams. If attempts at critical reasoning do occur in dreams and if they generally tend to be corrupted, the introspective criterion might again be problematic (Windt 2011, 2015a). There are also cases in which even after awakening, people mistake what was in fact a dream for reality (Wamsley et al. 2014). At least in certain situations and for some people, dream deception might be a genuine cause of concern (Windt 2015a).

2. The ontology of dreams

In what follows, the term “conscious experience” is used as an umbrella term for the occurrence of sensations, thoughts, impressions, emotions etc. in dreams (cf. Dennett 1976). These are all phenomenal states: there is something it is like to be in these states for the subject of experience (cf. Nagel 1974). To ask about dream experience is to ask whether it is like something to dream while dreaming, and whether what it is like is similar to (or relevantly different from) corresponding waking experiences.

Cartesian dream skepticism depends on a seemingly innocent background assumption: that dreams are conscious experiences. If this is false, then dreams are not deceptive experiences during sleep and we cannot be deceived, while dreaming, about anything at all. Whether dreams are experiences is a major question for the ontology of dreams and closely bound up with dream skepticism.

The most famous argument denying that dreams are experiences was formulated by Norman Malcolm (1956, 1959). Today, his position is commonly rejected as implausible. Still, it set the tone for the analysis of dreaming as a target phenomenon for philosophy of mind.

For Malcolm, the denial of dream experience followed from the conceptual analysis of sleep: “if a person is in any state of consciousness it logically follows that he is not sound asleep” (Malcolm 1956: 21). Following some remarks of Wittgenstein’s (1953: 184; see Chihara 1965 for discussion), Malcolm claimed

the concept of dreaming is derived, not from dreaming, but from descriptions of dreams, i.e., from the familiar phenomenon that we call “telling a dream”. (Malcolm 1959:55)

Malcolm argued that retrospective dream reports are the sole criterion for determining whether a dream occurred and there is no independent way of verifying dream reports. While first-person, past-tense psychological statements (such as “I felt afraid”) can at least in principle be verified by independent observations (but see Canfield 1961; Siegler 1967; Schröder 1997), he argued dream reports (such as “in my dream, I felt afraid”) are governed by different grammars and merely superficially resemble waking reports. In particular, he denied dream reports imply the occurrence of experiences (such as thoughts, feelings, or judgements) in sleep:

If a man had certain thoughts and feelings in a dream it no more follows that he had those thoughts and feelings while asleep, than it follows from his having climbed a mountain in a dream that he climbed a mountain while asleep. (Malcolm 1959/1962: 51–52)

What exactly Malcolm means by “conscious experience” is unclear. Sometimes he seems to be saying that conscious experience is conceptually tied to wakefulness (Malcolm 1956); other times he claims that terms such as mental activity or conscious experience are vague and it is senseless to apply them to sleep and dreams (Malcolm 1959: 52).

Malcolm’s analysis of dreaming has been criticized as assuming an overly strict form of verificationism and a naïve view of language and conceptual change. A particularly counterintuitive consequence of his view is that there can be no observational evidence for the occurrence of dreams in sleep aside from dream reports. This includes behavioral evidence such as sleepwalking or sleeptalking, which he thought showed the person was partially awake; as he also thought dreams occur in sound sleep, such sleep behaviors were largely irrelevant to the investigation of dreaming proper. He also claimed adopting a physiological criterion of dreaming (such as EEG measures of brain activity during sleep) would change the concept of dreaming, which he argued was tied exclusively to dream reporting. This claim was particularly radical as it explicitly targeted the discovery of REM sleep and its association with dreaming (Dement & Kleitman 1957), which is commonly regarded as the beginning of the science of sleep and dreaming. Malcolm’s position was that the very project of a science of dreaming was misguided.

Contra Malcolm, most assume that justification does not depend on strict criteria with the help of which the truth of a statement can be determined with absolute certainty, but “on appeals to the simplicity, plausibility, and predictive adequacy of an explanatory system as a whole” (Chihara & Fodor 1965: 197). In this view, behavioral and/or physiological evidence can be used to verify dream reports (Ayer 1960) and the alleged principled difference between dream reports and other first-person, past-tense psychological sentences (Siegler 1967; Schröder 1997) disappears.

Putnam noted that Malcolm’s analysis of the concept of dreaming relies on the dubious idea that philosophers have access to deep conceptual truths that are hidden to laypeople:

the lexicographer would undoubtedly perceive the logical (or semantical) connection between being a pediatrician and being a doctor, but he would miss the allegedly “logical” character of the connection between dreams and waking impressions. […] this “depth grammar” kind of analyticity (or “logical dependence”) does not exist. (Putnam 1962 [1986]: 306)

Nagel argued that even if one accepts Malcolm’s analysis of the concept of dreaming,

it is a mistake to invest the demonstration that it is impossible to have experiences while asleep with more import than it has. It is an observation about our use of the word “experience”, and no more. It does not imply that nothing goes on in our minds while we dream. (Nagel 1959: 114)

Whether dream thoughts, feelings or beliefs should count as real instances of their kind now becomes an open question, and in any case there is no conceptual contradiction involved in saying one has experiences while asleep and dreaming.

To ask about dream experience is also to ask whether there is something it is like to dream during sleep as opposed to there just being something it is like to remember dreaming after awakening. Dennett’s (1976, 1979) cassette theory says dreams are the product of instantaneous memory insertion at the moment of the awakening, as if a cassette with pre-scripted dreams had been inserted into memory, ready for replay. Dennett claims the cassette theory and the view that dreams are experiences can deal equally well with empirical evidence for instance on the relationship between dreaming and REM sleep. The cassette theory is preferable because it is more parsimonious, positing only an unconscious dream composition process rather than an additional conscious presentation process in sleep. For Dennett, the important point is that it is impossible to distinguish between the two rival theories based on dream recall; the question of dream experience should be settled by independent empirical evidence.

While Dennett shares Malcolm’s skepticism about dream experience, this latter claim is diametrically opposed to Malcolm’s rejection of a science of dreaming. For Dennett, the unreliability of dream recall also is not unique, but exemplifies a broader problem with memory reports: we generally cannot use retrospective recall to distinguish conscious experience from memory insertion (Dennett 1991; see also Emmett 1978).

An earlier and much discussed (Binz 1878; Goblot 1896; Freud 1899; Hall 1981; Kramer 2007:22–24) version of Dennett’s cassette theory goes back to Maury’s (1861) description of a long and complex dream about the French revolution that culminated in his execution at the guillotine, at which point Maury suddenly awoke to find that the headboard had fallen on his neck. Because the dream seemed to systematically build up to this dramatic conclusion, which in turn coincided with a sudden external event, he suggested that such cases were best explained as instantaneous memory insertions experienced at the moment of awakening. Similarly, Gregory (1916) described dreams are psychical explosions occurring at the moment of awakening.

The trustworthiness of dream reports continues to be contentious. Rosen (2013) argues that dream reports are often fabricated and fail to accurately describe experiences occurring during sleep. By contrast, Windt (2013, 2015a) argues that dream reports can at least under certain conditions (such as in laboratory studies, when dreams are reported immediately after awakening by trained participants) be regarded as trustworthy sources of evidence with respect to previous experience during sleep.

Unlike Malcolm, many believe that whether dreams are experiences is an empirical question; and unlike Dennett, the predominant view is that the empirical evidence does indeed support this claim (Flanagan 2000; Metzinger 2003; Revonsuo 2006; Rosen 2013; Windt 2013, 2015a).

A first reason for thinking that dreams are experiences during sleep is the relationship between dreaming and REM (rapid eye movement) sleep. Researchers in the 1950s discovered that sleep is not a uniform state of rest and passivity, but there is a sleep architecture involving different stages of sleep that is relatively stable both within and across individuals (Aserinsky & Kleitman 1953, 1955; Dement & Kleitman 1957). Following sleep onset, periods of non-REM (or NREM) sleep including slow wave sleep (so called because of the presence of characteristic slow-wave, high-voltage EEG activity) are followed by periods of high-frequency, low-voltage activity during REM sleep. EEG measures from REM sleep strongly resemble waking EEG. REM sleep is additionally characterized by rapid eye movements and a near-complete loss of muscle tone (Dement 1999: 27–50; Jouvet 1999).

The alignment between conscious experience on the one hand and wake-like brain activity and muscular paralysis on the other hand would seem to support the experiential status of dreams as well as explain the outward passivity that typically accompanies them. Reports of dreaming are in fact much more frequent following REM (81.9%) than NREM sleep awakenings (43%; Nielsen 2000). REM reports tend to be more elaborate, vivid, and emotionally intense, whereas NREM reports tend to be more thought-like, confused, non-progressive, and repetitive (Hobson et al. 2000). These differences led to the idea that REM sleep is an objective marker of dreaming (Dement & Kleitman 1957; Hobson 1988: 154).

Attempts to identify dreaming with mental activity during REM sleep have not, however, been successful, and many now hold that dreams can occur in all stages of sleep (e.g., Antrobus 1990; Foulkes 1993b; Solms 1997, 2000; Domhoff 2003; Nemeth & Fazekas 2018). In recent years there has been renewed interest in NREM sleep for the study of dreaming (Noreika et al. 2009; Siclari et al. 2013, 2017). This suggests the inference from the physiology of REM sleep to the phenomenology of dreaming is not straightforward.

A second line of evidence comes from lucid dreams, or dreams in which one knows one is dreaming and often has some level of dream control (Voss et al. 2013; Voss & Hobson 2015; Baird et al. 2019). The term lucid dreaming was coined by van Eeden (1913), but Aristotle ( On Dreams ) already noted that one can sometimes be aware while dreaming that one is dreaming.

Scientific evidence that lucid dreaming is real and a genuine sleep phenomenon comes from laboratory studies (Hearne 1978; LaBerge et al. 1981) showing lucid dreamers can use specific, pre-arranged patterns of eye movements (e.g., right-left-right-left) to signal in real-time that they are now lucid and engaging in dream experiments. These signals are clearly identifiable on the EOG and suggest a correspondence between dream-eye movements and real-eye movements (as predicted by the so-called scanning hypothesis ; see Dement & Kleitman 1957; Leclair-Visonneau et al. 2010). Retrospective reports confirm that the dreamer really was lucid and signalled lucidity (Dresler et al. 2012; Stumbrys et al. 2014).

Signal-verified lucid dreams have been used to study muscular activity accompanying body movements in dreams (Erlacher et al. 2003; Dresler et al. 2011), for advanced EEG analysis of brain activity during lucid dreaming (Voss et al. 2009), and imaging studies (Dresler et al. 2011, 2012). Eye signals can also be used to measure the duration of different activities performed in lucid dreams; contrary to the cassette theory, lucid dreams have temporal extension and certain dream actions even seem to take slightly longer than in waking (Erlacher et al. 2014). There have also been attempts to induce lucidity through non-invasive electrical stimulation during sleep (Stumbrys et al. 2013; Voss et al. 2014). The combination of signal-verified lucid dreaming with volitional control over dream content, retrospective report, and objective sleep measures has been proposed to provide controlled conditions for the study of conscious experience in sleep and a new methodology for investigating the relationship between conscious experience and neurophysiological processes (Baird et al.2019).

A third line of evidence (Revonsuo 2006: 77) comes from dream-enactment behavior (Nielsen et al. 2009), most prominently in patients with REM-sleep behavior disorder (RBD; Schenck & Mahowald 1996; Schenck 2005; Leclair-Visonneau et al. 2010). Due to a loss of the muscular atonia that accompanies REM sleep in healthy subjects, these patients show complex, seemingly goal-directed outward behaviors such as running or fighting off an attacker during REM sleep. Retrospective dream reports often match these behaviors, suggesting that patients literally act out their dreams during sleep.

While persuasive, these lines of evidence might not satisfy skeptics about dream experience. They might worry that results from lucid dreaming and dream enactment do not generalize to ordinary, non-lucid dreams; they might also construe alternative explanations that do not require conscious experience in sleep. There are also methodological concerns, for instance about how closely sleep-behaviors actually match dream experience. A key issue is that to support the experiential status of dreams, evidence from sleep polysomnography, signal verified lucid dreams, or sleep behavior requires convergence with retrospective dream reports. This means trusting dream reports is built into any attempt to empirically resolve the question of dream experience – which then invites the familiar skeptical concerns. Again, an anti-skeptical strategy may be to appeal to explanatory considerations. In this view, the convergence of dream reports and objective polysomnographic or behavioral observations is best explained by the assumption that dreams are experiences in sleep, and this assumption is strengthened by further incoming findings. This strategy places dream reports at the center of scientific dream research while avoiding the contentious claim that their trustworthiness, and with it the experiential status of dreams, can be demonstrated conclusively by independent empirical means (Windt 2013, 2015a).

Even where philosophers agree dreams are experiences, they often disagree on how exactly to characterize dreaming relative to wake-state psychological terms. Often, questions about the ontology of dreaming intersect with epistemological issues. Increasingly, they also incorporate empirical findings.

The standard view is that dreams have the same phenomenal character as waking perception in that they seemingly put us in contact with mind-independent objects, yet no such object is actually being perceived. This means dreams count as hallucinations in the philosophical sense (Crane & French 2017; Macpherson 2013). Even if, in a particularly realistic dream, my visual experience was exactly as it would be if I were awake (I could see my bedroom, my hands on the bed sheets, etc.), as long as my eyes were closed during the episode, I would not, literally, be seeing anything.

There is some controversy in the psychological literature about whether dreams should be regarded as hallucinations. Some believe the term hallucination should be reserved for clinical contexts and wake-state pathologies (Aleman & Larøi 2008: 17; but see ffytche 2007; ffytche et al. 2010).

The view that dreams involve hallucinations is implicit in Descartes’ assumption that even when dreaming,

it is certain that I seem to see light, hear a noise, and feel heat; this cannot be false, and this is what in me is properly called perceiving ( sentire ). (Descartes 1641: II.9)

It also lies at the heart of Aristotle’s ( On Dreams ) assumption that dreams result from the movements of the sensory organs that continue even after the original stimulus has ceased. He believed that in the silence of sleep, these residual movements result in vivid sensory imagery that is subjectively indistinguishable from genuine perception (see also Dreisbach 2000; Barbera 2008).

The assumption of phenomenological equivalence between dream and waking experience can also be found in Berkeley’s (1710: I.18) idealist claim that the existence of external bodies is not necessary for the production of vivid, wake-like perceptual experience. Similarly, Russell defended sense-data theory by noting that in dreams,

I have all the experiences that I seem to have; it is only things outside my mind that are not as I believe them to be while I am dreaming. (Russell 1948: 149–150)

Elsewhere, he argued dreams and waking life

must be treated with equal respect; it is only by some reality not merely sensible that dreams can be condemned. (Russell 1914: 69)

Hume was less clear on this matter, proposing that dreams occupy an intermediate position between vivid and largely non-voluntary sensory impressions and ideas, or “the faint images of previous impressions in thinking and reasoning” (Hume 1739: 1.1.1.1). On the one hand, as mere creatures of the mind, Hume wanted to categorize dreams as ideas. On the other hand, he acknowledged that in sleep, “our ideas can approach the vivacity of sensory impressions” (Hume 1739: 1.1.1.1). Dreams do not fit comfortably into Hume’s attempt to draw a dichotomous distinction between impressions, including perception, and ideas, including sensory imagination (Ryle 1949; Waxman 1994; Broughton 2006).

Phenomenologists often focus not so much on the quality of dream imagery as on the overall character of experience, noting that dreams are experienced as reality; as in waking perception, we simply feel present in a world. This also sets dreams apart from waking fantasy and daydreams (Husserl 1904/1905; Uslar 1964; Conrad 1968; Globus 1987: 89.

At its strongest, the hallucination view claims that dreaming and waking experience are identical in both the quality of sensory imagery and their overall, self-in-a-world structure (Revonsuo 2006: 84). This claim is central to the virtual reality metaphor , according to which consciousness itself is dreamlike and waking perception a kind of online hallucination modulated by the senses (Llinás & Ribary 1994; Llinás & Paré 1991; Revonsuo 2006; Metzinger 2003, 2009).

This seems to be empirically supported. Neuroimaging studies (Dang-Vu et al. 2007; Nir & Tononi 2010; Desseilles et al. 2011) show that the predominance of visual and motor imagery as well as strong emotions in dreams is paralleled by high activation of the corresponding brain areas in REM sleep, which may exceed waking; at the same time, the cognitive deficits often thought to characterize dreams such as the loss of self-awareness, the absence of critical thinking, delusional reasoning, and mnemonic deficits fit in well with the comparative deactivation of frontal areas (Hobson et al. 2000). Hobson (1988, Hobson et al. 2000) has argued that the vivid, hallucinatory character of dreaming results from the fact that in REM sleep, the visual and motor areas are activated in the same way as in waking perception, the sole difference being dreams’ dependence on internal signal generation. Horikawa and colleagues (2013) used neuroimaging data from sleep onset to predict the types of objects described in mentation reports, which they took to support the perceptual equivalence between dreaming and waking.

Generally, versions of the hallucination view that suggest dreams replicate all aspects of waking perception are too vague to be informative. Especially for subtle perceptual activities (such as visual search), we might not know enough about dream phenomenology to make any strong claims (Nielsen 2010). Specifying points of similarity leads to a more informative and precise, but likely also more nuanced view. Dreams are heterogeneous, and some might be more perception-like while others resemble imagination (Windt 2015a). There might also be differences between or even within specific types of imagery. For example, visual imagery might be quite different from touch sensations, which tend to be rare in dreams (Hobson 1988). Visual dream imagery might overall resemble waking perception but lack color saturation, background detail and focus (Rechtschaffen & Buchignani, 1992). Classifying dreams as either hallucinatory or imaginative is further complicated by the fact that there is strong overlap in cortical activity associated with both visual imagery and perception (Zeidman & Maguire, 2016). This means even a strong overlap in cortical activity between, say, visual dream imagery and visual perception does not necessarily set dreaming apart from waking imagination.

This is also true for evidence on eye movements in dreams. LaBerge and colleagues (2018) recently showed that eye tracking of objects is smooth in lucid dreaming and perceiving, but not in imagining. Drawing from this evidence, Rosen (forthcoming) suggests many dreams mimic the phenomenology of interacting with a stable world, including eye movements and visual search. Others argue we should not analogize dream imagery to mind-independent, scannable objects and that eye movements might instead be implicated in the generation of dream imagery (Windt 2018).

Another way to make sense of the claim that dreaming has the same phenomenal character as waking perception is to say some kinds of dream imagery are illusory: they involve misperception of an external object as having different properties than it actually has (cf. Smith 2002; Crane & French 2017). The illusion view disagrees with the hallucination view on whether dreams have a contemporaneous external stimulus source.

The illusion view has fallen out of favor but has a long history. The Ancients believed dreams have bodily sources. This idea underlies the practice of using dreams to diagnose illness, as practiced in the shrines at Epidaurus (Galen On Diagnosis in Dreams ; van de Castle 1994). Aristotle ( On Dreams ) thought some dreams are caused by indigestion, and Hobbes adopted this view, claiming different kinds of dreams could be traced to different bodily sensations. For instance, “lying cold breedeth Dreams of Feare, and raiseth the thought and Image of some fearfull object” (Hobbes 1651: 91).

Appeals to the bodily sources of dreaming became especially popular in the 19 th and early 20 th centuries. Many believed specific dream themes such as flying were linked to sleeping position (Macnish 1838; Scherner 1861; Vold 1910/1912; Ellis 1911) and realizing, in sleep, that one’s feet are not touching the ground (Bergson 1914).

There were also attempts to explain the phenomenology of dreaming by appealing to the absence of outward movement. The lack of appropriate feedback and of movement and touch sensations was thought to cause dreams of being unable to move (Bradley 1894) or of trying but failing to do something (Gregory 1918).

Some proponents of the “ Leibreiztheorie ” (or somatic-stimulus theory) of dreaming attempted to go beyond anecdotal observations to conduct controlled experiments. Weygandt (1893) investigated the influence of various factors including breathing, blood circulation, temperature changes, urge to urinate, sleeping position, and visual or auditory stimulation during sleep on dream content (see Schredl 2010 for details). Singer (1924) proposed experiments on stimulus incorporation in dreams can inform claims on the ontology of dreaming: If dreams are sensations, a particular auditory stimulus should increase the frequency of dreams in nearby sleepers as well as the frequency of sound in their dreams, and it should decrease the range of quality and intensity of these dreams, making them overall more similar and predictable.

Newer studies provide evidence for the incorporation of external stimuli in dreams, including light flashes, sounds, sprays of water applied to the skin (Dement & Wolpert 1958), thermal (Baldridge 1966), electrical (Koulack 1969), and verbal stimuli (Berger 1963; Breger et al. 1971; Hoelscher et al., 1981), as well as blood pressure cuff stimulation on the leg (Nielsen et al. 1995; Sauvageau et al. 1998).

Muscular activity also often leaves its mark on dreams. It occurs throughout sleep but is especially frequent in REM sleep, mostly in the form of twitching but occasionally also in the form of larger, seemingly goal-directed movements (Blumberg 2010; Blumberg & Plumeau 2016). The relation between outward and dream movements is complex: in some cases, outward movements might mirror dream movements, while in others, sensory feedback might prompt dream imagery (Windt 2018).

Generally, it seems external and bodily stimuli can be related to varying degrees to dream and sleep onset imagery (Nielsen 2017; Windt 2018; Windt et al. 2016). Some of these cases appear to fit the concept of illusion, as in when the sound of the alarm clock is experienced, in a dream, as a siren, or when blood pressure cuff inflation on the leg leads to dreams of wearing strange shoes (Windt 2018; for these and other examples, see Nielsen et al. 1995). In other cases, such as when blood pressure cuff stimulation on the leg prompts a dream of seeing someone else’s leg being run over, describing this as illusory misperception might be less straightforward.

Saying that dreams can be prompted by external stimuli and that in some cases these are best described as illusions is different from the stronger claim, sometimes advanced by historical proponents of somatic-stimulus theory, that dreams generally are caused by external or bodily stimuli. As an example of the stronger claim, consider Wundt’s proposal that the

ideas which arise in dreams come, at least to a great extent, from sensations, especially from those of the general sense, and are therefore mostly illusions of fancy, probably only seldom pure memory ideas which hence become hallucinations. (Wundt 1896: 179)

This claim is likely too strong. It is also likely that appeals to external or bodily stimuli on their own cannot fully explain dream imagery, including when and how external stimuli are incorporated in dreams. Sensory incorporation in dreams is often hard to predict and indirect; associated imagery seems related not just to stimulus intensity, but also to short- and long term memories. A full explanation of dream content additionally has to take the cognitive and memory sources of dreaming into account (Windt 2018; Nielsen 2017; cf. Silberer 1919).

The most important rival to the hallucination view is that dreams are imaginative experiences (Liao & Gendler 2019; Thomas 2014). This can mean dream imagery involves imaginings rather than percepts (including hallucinations or illusions; McGinn 2004), that dream beliefs are imaginative and not real beliefs (Sosa 2007), or both (Ichikawa 2008, 2009). An important advantage is that by assimilating dreams to commonplace mental states such as waking fantasy and daydreaming, rather than a rare and often pathological occurrence such as hallucinations, it provides a more unified account of mental life (Stone 1984). However, the reasons for adopting the imagination view are diverse, and dreams have been proposed to resemble imaginings and differ from perception along a number of dimensions (e.g. McGinn 2004, 2005a,b; Thomas 2014). This issue is complicated by the fact that there is little agreement on the definition of imagination and its relation to perception (Kind 2013).

One way is to deny dreams involve presence or the feeling of being in a world, which many believe is central to waking perception. Imagination theorists compare the sense in which we feel present in our dreams to cognitive absorption, as when we are lost in a novel, film, or vivid daydream (Sartre 1940; McGinn 2004; but see Hering 1947; Globus 1987). Some argue that reflexive consciousness or meta-awareness (as in lucid dreams) interrupts cognitive absorption and terminates the ongoing dream (Sartre 1940), essentially denying lucid dreams are possible.

Another issue is whether dreams are subject to the will (Ichikawa 2009). Imagination is often characterized as active and under our control (Wittgenstein 1967: 621, 633), involving “a special effort of the mind” (Descartes 1641: VI, 2), whereas perception is passive. Because dreams just seem to happen to us without being under voluntary control, they present an important challenge for the imagination view. Ichikawa (2009) argues lucid control dreams show dreams are generally subject to the will even where they are not under deliberate control.

Dreams are widely described as more indeterminate than waking perception (James 1890: 47; Stone 1984). In scientific dream research, vagueness is regarded as one of three main subtypes of bizarreness (Hobson 1988; Revonsuo & Salmivalli 1995). An example are dream characters who are identified not by their behavior or looks, but by just knowing (Kahn et al. 2000, 2002; Revonsuo & Tarkko 2002). Dreams are also attention-dependent and lack foreground-background structure (Thompson 2014); while it is tempting to construe the dream world as rich in detail, there is no more to dreams than meets the eye, and many think dream experience is exhausted by what is the focus of selective attention (Hunter 1983; Thompson 2014).

Indeterminacy is also related to the question of whether we dream in color or in black and white. Based on a review of historical and recent studies, Schwitzgebel (2002, 2011) argues there has been a shift in theories on dream color that coincides with the rise first of black-and-white and then color television. He argues it is unlikely that dreams themselves changed from colored to black and white and back to colored, proposing that a change in opinion is a more plausible explanation. Maybe dreams were either black and white or colored all along; or maybe they are indeterminate with respect to color, as may be the case for imagined or fictional objects; were this the case, it would strengthen the imagination view (Ichikawa 2009). Schwitzgebel’s main point is that reports of colored dreaming are unreliable and our opinions about dreams can be mistaken (but see Windt 2013, 2015a). This relates to Schwitzgebel’s (2011; Hurlburt & Schwitzgebel 2007) general skepticism about the reliability of introspection.

The issue of dream color has led to a number of follow-up studies (Schwitzgebel 2003; Schwitzgebel et al. 2006; Murzyn 2008; Schredl et al. 2008; Hoss 2010). They suggest most people dream in color and a small percentage describe grayscale or even mixed dreams (Murzyn 2008) or dreams involving moderate color saturation (Rechtschaffen and Buchignani 1992). Indeterminacy is rarely reported.

The imagination view has consequences for Cartesian dream skepticism. If dream pain does not feel like real pain, there is a fail-safe way to determine whether one is now dreaming: one need only pinch oneself (Nelson 1966; Stone 1984; but see Hodges & Carter 1969; Kantor 1970). As Locke put it,

if our dreamer pleases to try, whether the glowing heat of a glass furnace, be barely a wandering imagination in a drowsy man’s fancy, by putting his hand into it, he may perhaps be wakened into a certainty greater than he could wish, that it is something more than bare imagination. (Locke 1689: IV.XI.8)

If dreaming feels different from waking, this raises the question why we tend to describe dreams in the same terms as waking perception. Maybe this is because most people haven’t thought about these matters and they would find the imagination view plausible if they considered it (Ichikawa 2009). Or maybe

it is just because we all know that dreams are throughout un like waking experiences that we can safely use ordinary expressions in the narration of them. (Austin 1962: 42)

Some authors classify dreams as imaginings while acknowledging they feel like perceiving. For example, Hobbes describes dreams as “the imaginations of them that sleep” (Hobbes 1651: 90), and imagination as a “ decaying sense ” (Hobbes 1651: 88). Yet he also uses the concepts of imagination and fancy to describe perception and argues “their appearance to us is Fancy, the same waking, that dreaming” (Hobbes 1651: 86).

In the scientific literature, the imagination view is complemented by cognitive theories. Foulkes (1978: 5) describes dreaming as a form of thinking with its own grammar and syntax, but allows that dream imagery is sufficently perception-like to deceive us. Domhoff’s neurocognitive model of dreaming (2001, 2003) emphasizes the dependence of dreaming on visuospatial skills and on a network including the association areas of the forebrain. The theory draws from findings on the partial or global cessation of dreaming following brain lesions (cf. Solms 1997, 2000), evidence that dreaming develops gradually and in tandem with visuospatial skills in children (Foulkes 1993a, 1999; but see Resnick et al. 1994), and results from dream content analysis supporting the continuity of dreaming with waking concerns and memories (the so-called continuity hypothesis ; see Domhoff 2001, 2003; Schredl & Hofmann 2003; Schredl 2006; see also Nir & Tononi 2010).

A number of researchers have begun to consider dreaming in the context of theories of mind wandering. Mind wandering is frequent in waking and involves spontaneous thoughts that unfold dynamically and are only weakly constrained by ongoing tasks and environmental demands (Schooler et al. 2011; Smallwood & Schooler 2015; Christoff et al. 2016). Based on phenomenological and neurophysiological similarities, dreams have been proposed to be an intensified form of waking mind wandering (Pace-Schott 2007, 2013; Domhoff 2011; Wamsley 2013; Fox et al. 2013). This basic idea seems to have been anticipated by Leibniz, who noted that the spontaneous formation of visions in dreams surpasses the capacity of our waking imagination (Leibniz, Philosophical Papers and Letters , Vol. I, 177–178).

The analogy between dreams and waking mind wandering has been discussed in the context of cognitive agency. Metzinger (2013a,b, 2015) describes dreams and waking mind wandering as involving a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy, or the ability to deliberately control one’s conscious thought processes. Dreams and waking mind wandering are not mental actions but unintentional mental behaviors, comparable to subpersonal processes such as breathing or heartbeat. Because dreaming and waking mind wandering make up a the majority of our conscious mental lives, he argues that cognitive agency and mental autonomy are the exception, not the rule.

This raises the question of how to make sense of lucid control dreams, which involve both meta-awareness and agency. Windt and Voss (2018) argue that in such cases, spontaneous processes including imagery formation co-exist alongside more deliberate, top-down control; they also argue metacognitive insight and control themselves can have spontaneous elements. This suggests spontaneity and control are not opposites, but a more complex account is needed. Possibly, certain dreams and instances of waking mind wandering can be both spontaneous and agentive.

The analogy with mind wandering might help move forward the debate on the ontology of dreaming. In this debate, a common assumption is that dreams can be categorized as either hallucinatory or imaginative. Yet the application of these terms to dreams quickly runs into counterexamples and it is unclear they are mutually exclusive. One option is pluralism (Rosen 2018b), in which some aspects of dreaming are hallucinatory, others imaginative, and yet again others illusory. Another is that dreams are sui generis, combining aspects associated with wake states such as hallucinating, imagining, or perceiving in a novel manner without mimicking them completely. Windt (2015a) proposes that mind wandering, which describes a range of mental states loosely characterized by their spontaneous and dynamic character, might be particularly suitable for the characterization of dreaming precisely because that term leaves open more specific questions on the phenomenology of dreaming, allowing for variation in control, determinacy, and so on. This might be a good starting point for describing what is unique about dreaming while also acknowledging continuities across sleep-wake states and capitalizing on the strengths of the hallucination, illusion, imagination, and cognitive views.

The second strand of the imagination view argues that dream beliefs are not real beliefs, but propositional imaginings. This may or may not be combined with the claim that dream imagery is imaginative rather than perceptual (Sosa 2007; Ichikawa 2009).

Denying that dream beliefs have the status of real beliefs only makes sense before the background of a specific account of what beliefs are and how they are distinguished from other mental states such as delusions or propositional imaginings. For instance, Ichikawa (2009) argues that if we follow interpretationist or dispositionalist accounts of belief, dream beliefs fall short of real beliefs. He claims dream beliefs lack connection with perceptual experience and fail to motivate actions; consequently, they do not have the same functional role as real beliefs. Moreover, we cannot ascribe dream beliefs to a person by observing them lying asleep in bed. Dream beliefs are often inconsistent with longstanding waking beliefs and acquired and discarded without any process of belief revision (Ichikawa 2009).

This analysis of dream beliefs has consequences for skepticism. If dream beliefs are propositional imaginings, then we do not falsely believe while dreaming that we are now awake, but only imagine that we do (Sosa 2007). It is not clear though that this protects us from deception. If dream beliefs fall short of real beliefs, this might even make the specter of dream deception more worrisome: in mistaking dream beliefs for the real thing, we would now be deceived about the status of our own mental states (Ichikawa 2008).

It is also not clear whether the same type of argument extends to mental states other than beliefs. As Lewis points out, a person might

in fact believe or realize in the course of a dream that he was dreaming, and even if we said that, in such case, he only dreamt that he was dreaming, this still leaves it possible for someone who is asleep to entertain at the time the thought that he is asleep. (Lewis 1969: 133)

Mental states other than believing such as entertaining, thinking, or minimally appraisive instances of taking for granted might be sufficient for deception (Reed 1979).

The debate about dream beliefs is paralleled by a debate about whether delusions are beliefs or imaginings (see Currie 2000; Currie & Ravenscroft 2002; McGinn 2004; Bayne & Pacherie 2005; Bortolotti 2009; Gendler 2013). Both debates might plausibly inform each other, especially as dreams are sometimes proposed to be delusional (Hobson 1999).

3. Dreaming and theories of consciousness

Dreams are a global state of consciousness in which experience arises under altered behavioral and neurophysiological conditions as compared to standard wakefulness; unlike other altered states of consciousness (such as drug-induced or deep meditative states) and pathological wake states (such as psychosis or neurological syndromes), dreams occur spontaneously and regularly in healthy subjects. For both reasons, many regard dreams as a test case for theories of consciousness or even an ideal model system for consciousness research (Churchland 1988; Revonsuo 2006).

Existing proposals differ on the phenomenology of dreaming: referring to dream bizarreness, Churchland describes dream experience as robustly different from waking, whereas Revonsuo argues dreaming is similar to waking and the purest form of experience:

the dreaming brain brings out the phenomenal level of organization in a clear and distinct form. Dreaming is phenomenality pure and simple, untouched by external physical stimulation or behavioural activity. (Revonsuo 2006: 75)

Revonsuo argues dreaming reveals the basic, state-independent structure of consciousness to be immersive: “dreaming depicts consciousness first and foremost as a subjective world- for-me ” (Revonsuo 2006: 75). This leads him to introduce the “world-simulation metaphor of consciousness”, according to which consciousness itself is essentially simulational and dreamlike. This is taken to support internalism about conscious experience.

This latter claim is also contentious. Noë (2004: 213) argues that phenomenological differences between dreaming and waking (such as greater instability of visual dream imagery) result from the lack of dynamic interaction with the environment in dreams. He proposes this shows that neural states are sufficient for dreaming but denies they are also sufficient for perceptual experience.

A possible problem for both views is their reliance on background assumptions about the phenomenology of dreaming and its disconnection from environmental stimuli and bodily sensations. Windt (2015a, 2018) argues both internalism and externalism mistakenly assume dreams to be isolated from external sensory input and own-body perception; she believes both the phenomenology of dreaming and its correlation with external stimuli are complex and variable. She argues the analysis of dreaming does not clearly support either side in the debate on internalism vs externalism (but see Rosen 2018a). Generally, in the absence of a well worked out theory of dreaming and its sleep-stage and neural correlates, proposals for using dreaming as a model system or test case run the risk of relying on an oversimplified description of the target phenomenon (Windt & Noreika 2011).

Recent accounts appealing to generative models and predictive processing (Clark 2013b; Hohwy 2013) suggest a new, unified account of perception, imagination, and dreaming. In these accounts, different mental states, including perception and action, embody different strategies of hypothesis testing and prediction error minimization. Perception is the attempt to model the hidden external causes of sensory stimuli; action involves keeping the internal model stable while changing the sensory input. Clark argues that on such a model,

systems that know how to perceive an object as a cat are thus systems that, ipso facto , are able to use a top-down cascade to bring about the kinds of activity pattern that would be characteristic of the presence of a cat. […] Perceivers like us, if this is correct, are inevitably potential dreamers and imaginers too. Moreover, they are beings who, in dreaming and imagining, are deploying many of the very same strategies and resources used in ordinary perception. (Clark 2013a: 764)

Predictive processing accounts have also been used to explain specific features of dreaming. Bizarreness has been associated with the comparative lack of external stimulus processing, implying dream imagery is relatively unconstrained by prediction errors (cf. Hobson & Friston 2012; Fletcher & Frith 2008; Bucci & Grasso 2017). Windt (2018) suggests a predictive processing account of dream imagery generation that links bodily self-experience to own-body perception and subtle motor behaviors such as twitching in REM sleep (Blumberg 2010; Blumberg & Plumeau 2016). She argues that movement sensations in dreams, in relation to REM-sleep related muscle twitching, involve a form of bodily self-sampling in which coordinated muscular activity contributes to the generation and maintenance of a body model. This is important because in predictive processing accounts neither the bodily nor the external causes of sensory inputs are known; at the same time, having an accurate body model is a prerequisite for action, requiring the system to disambiguate between self- and other generated changes to sensory inputs. Especially in early development, sleep might provide the ideal conditions for exploring one’s own body via subtle but coordinated muscular activity while processing of visual and auditory stimuli is reduced.

Dreams have also been suggested as a test case for whether phenomenal consciousness can be divorced from cognitive access (e.g., Block 2007; but see Cohen & Dennett 2011). Sebastián (2014a) argues that dreams provide empirical evidence that conscious experience can occur independently of cognitive access. This is because during (non-lucid) REM-sleep dreams, the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC) as the most plausible mechanism underlying cognitive access is selectively deactivated (see also Pantani et al. 2018). This would challenge theories linking conscious experience to access, such as higher-order-thought theory (Sebastián 2014b). However, both the hypoactivation of the dlPCF in REM sleep and its association with cognitive access have been debated. Fazekas and Nemeth (2018) suggest that certain kinds of cognitive access may be independent of dlPFC activation, necessitating a more complex account.

Dreaming has been suggested as a model system not just of waking consciousness in general, but also of psychotic wake states in particular. The analogy between dreaming and madness has a long philosophical history (Plato, Phaedrus ; Kant 1766; Schopenhauer 1847) and finds particularly stark expression in Hobson’s claim that “dreaming is not a model of a psychosis. It is a psychosis. It’s just a healthy one” (Hobson 1999: 44). Gottesmann (2006) proposes dreaming as a neurophysiological model of schizophrenia. There is a rich discussion on the theoretical and methodological implications of dream research for psychiatry (see Scarone et al. 2007; d’Agostino et al. 2013; see Windt & Noreika 2011 as well as the other papers in this special issue) and a number of studies have investigated differences in dream reports from schizophrenic and healthy subjects (Limosani et al. 2011a,b).

Rather than likening dreaming to waking in general or specific wake states such as psychosis, there have also been attempts to compare specific dream phenomena to wake-state delusions. Gerrans (2012, 2013, 2014) focuses on character misidentification in dreams and delusions of hyperfamiliarity (such as the Frégoli delusion, in which strangers are mistakenly identified as family members, and déjà vu ) to argue that anomalous experience and faulty reality testing both play a role in delusion formation. Rosen (2015) analyzes instances of thought insertion and of auditory hallucinations, which are key symptoms of schizophrenia, to raise broader questions about the altered sense of agency in dreams as compared to waking.

Philosophers have focused almost exclusively on dreaming, largely leaving to the side questions about dreamless sleep including whether it is uniformly unconscious. In recent years there has been a surge of interest in the possibility of dreamless sleep experience and foundational issues about the definition of sleep and waking. This has been paralleled by growing interest in dreaming in NREM sleep.

Conceptually, interest in dreamless sleep experience has been facilitated by the precise definition of dreaming offered by simulation views (Revonsuo et al. 2015). If dreams are immersive sleep experiences characterized by their here -and- now structure, it makes sense to ask whether this is true for all or just a subset of sleep-related experiences and whether non-immersive sleep experiences exist. By contrast, if dreaming is broadly identified with any conscious mentation in sleep (Pagel et al. 2001), there is no conceptual space for dreamless sleep experience.

Following Thompson's (2014, 2015) discussion of dreamless sleep in Indian and Buddhist philosophy, Windt and colleagues (2016; see also Windt 2015b) introduce a framework for different kinds of dreamless sleep experience ranging from thinking and isolated imagery, perception, or bodily sensations, where these lack integration into a scene, to minimal kinds of experience lacking imagery or specific thought contents. A possible example of minimal phenomenal experience in sleep are white dreams, where people report having had experiences during sleep but cannot remember any details. Taken at face value, some white dream reports might describe experiences that lack reportable content (Windt 2015b); others might describe forgotten dreams or dreams with degraded content (Fazekas et al. 2018). Another example are reports of witnessing dreamless sleep, as described in certain meditation practices. This state is said to involve non-conceptual awareness of sleep, again in the absence of imagery or specific thought contents, and loss of sense of self (Thompson 2014, 2015). Some schools in Buddhist philosophy explain claims of deep and dreamless sleep by saying we never fully lose consciousness in sleep (Prasad 2000, 66; and Thompson 2014, 2015).

Empirically, interest in dreamless sleep experience is paralleled by increasing interest in experiences in NREM sleep (Fazekas et al. 2018). Most researchers now accept that dreaming is not confined to REM sleep, but also occurs at sleep onset and in NREM sleep. The deeper stages of NREM sleep are particularly interesting as they involve roughly similar proportions of dreaming, unconscious sleep, and white dreams (Noreika et al. 2009: Siclari et al. 2013, 2017). In the search for the neural correlates of dreaming vs unconscious dreamless sleep, this makes comparisons within the same sleep stage possible and avoids confounds involved in comparing presumably dreamful REM sleep with presumably dreamless NREM sleep. Findings suggest that activity in the same parietal hot zone underlies dreaming in both NREM and REM sleep (Siclari et al. 2017).

Where sleep and dream research have traditionally tried to identify the sleep stage correlates of dreaming, newer research suggests local changes occurring independently of sleep stages might in fact be more relevant. Traditionally regarded as global, whole-brain phenomena, there is now increasing evidence that sleep itself is locally driven, and local changes in sleep depth might be associated with changes in sleep-related experience (Siclari & Tononi 2017; Andrillon et al. 2019). While sleep and dream research are often considered as separate fields, changes in how sleep in general and sleep stages in particular are defined appear closely associated with changes in the theoretical conception of dreaming and its empirical investigation.

Historically, discoveries about dreaming have precipitated changing conceptions of sleep (for an excellent history of the study of sleep and dreaming, see Kroker 2007). Following Aristotle ( On Sleeping and Waking ), sleep was traditionally defined in negative terms as the absence of wakefulness and perception. This is still reflected in Malcolm’s assumption that “to a person who is sound asleep, ‘dead to the world’, things cannot even seem” (Malcolm 1956: 26). With the discovery of REM sleep, sleep came to be regarded as a heterogeneous phenomenon characterized by the cyclic alteration of different sleep stages. REM sleep was now considered as “neither sleeping nor waking. It was obviously a third state of the brain, as different from sleep as sleep is from wakefulness” (Jouvet 1999: 5). The folk-psychological dichotomy between sleep and wakefulness now seemed oversimplified and empirically implausible. At the same time dreaming, which had previously been considered as an intermediate state of half-sleeping and half-waking, came to be regarded as a genuine sleep phenomenon, but narrowed to REM sleep. Today, the framework for describing dreams and other sleep-related experiences is more precise, but dreaming has also been cast adrift from REM sleep.

A closely associated issue is how to define waking. Crowther’s (2018) capacitation thesis casts waking consciousness as a state in which the individual is fully switched on to their environment, but also to their own epistemic (cf. O’Shaugnessy 2002) and agentive potential; the waking individual is empowered to act and think in certain ways, though this potential need not be actualized. By contrast, dreaming is an “imagining-of consciousness” (O’Shaughnessy 2002: 430) and consciousness is conceptually tied to wakefulness. Because in lucid dreams, the epistemic and agentive profile of waking is at least partly realized, they might, according to Crowther, be regarded as closer to waking than nonlucid dreams.

This account of waking and sleep may also have consequences for the imagination model of dreaming and dream skepticism (Soteriou 2017). As in the imagination model, dreaming would be passive and action, including cognitive agency, would be tied to waking. If dreaming nonetheless involved passive episodes of imagining oneself to be active, one would be unable to tell that one were dreaming and imagining, as this insight would require the exercise of real agency. The sceptical consequence would be that when dreaming, one would lose agency as well as the capacity to gain insight into one’s current state. Yet our ability to know we are waking when waking would be unscathed; according to Soteriou, waking would thus have an epistemic function connected to the capacity to exercise agency over our mental lives.

Finally, definitions of consciousness themselves are bound up with conceptions of sleep and dreaming. As dreaming went from a state whose experiential status was doubted to being widely recognized as a second global state of consciousness, consciousness sometimes came to be defined contrastively as that which disappears in deep, dreamless sleep and reappears in waking and dreaming (Searle 2000; Tononi 2008). In light of dreamless sleep experience, such definitions are problematic (Thompson 2014, 2015; Windt 2015b; Windt et al. 2016). Dreamless sleep experience has been proposed to be particularly relevant for understanding minimal phenomenal experience, or the conditions under which the simplest kind of conscious experience arises (Windt 2015b). The investigation of dreamless sleep might thus shed light on the transition from unconscious sleep to sleep-related experience.

We almost always have a self in dreams, though this self can sometimes be a slightly different (e.g. older or younger) version of our waking self or even a different person entirely. Dreams therefore raise interesting questions about the identity between the dream and waking self. Locke (1689) invites us to imagine two men alternating in turns between sleep and wakefulness and sharing one continuously thinking soul (Locke 1689: II.I.12). He argues that if one man retained no memory of the soul’s thoughts and perceptions while it was linked to the other man’s body, they would be distinct persons. His position is that personal identity depends on psychological continuity, including recall: in the absence of recall, as illustrated by the toy example of two people sharing one soul, continuous conscious thinking does not suffice for identity. Locke also rejects the possibility of unrecalled dreams and the idea that we dream throughout sleep, remembering only a small proportion of our dreams (Locke 1689: II.I.19).

Valberg distinguishes between the subject of the dream (i.e., the dream self) and the sleeping person who is the dreamer of the dream and recalls it upon awakening (Valberg 2007). He argues that awakening from a dream involves crossing a chasm between discrete worlds with discrete spaces and times; it does not make sense to say that “the ‘I’ at these times [is] a single individual who crosses from one world to the other” (Valberg 2007: 69). According to Valberg, this is relevant to dream skepticism because there is no simple way to make sense of the claims that it is I who emerge from a dream or that I was the victim of dream deception.

Vicarious dreams, or dreams in which the protagonist of the dream seems to be a different person from the dreamer, are particularly puzzling with respect to identity. They may even raise the question of whether the dream self has an independent existence (Rosen & Sutton 2013: 1047). Such dreams are superficially similar to cases in which we imagine being another person, but according to Rosen and Sutton require a different explanation: in the case of dreaming, the imagined person’s thoughts are not framed as diverging from one’s own and one does not retain one’s own perspective in addition to the imagined one; in nonlucid dreams, only the perspective of the dream’s protagonist is retained.

The dream self is also at the center of simulation views of dreaming, which define dreaming via its immersive, here and now character as the experience of a self in a world. This leads to further questions about the phenomenology of self-experience in dreams and how it is different from waking self-experience. Different versions of the simulation view focus on different aspects of self- and world experience in dreams, ranging from social simulation (Revonsuo et al. 2015) to the typical features of selfhood in dreams (Revonsuo 2005, 2006, Metzinger 2003, 2009) to the minimal conditions for experiencing oneself as a self in dreams and what this tells us about minimal phenomenal selfhood in general (Windt 2015a, 2018). Yet these different versions of the simulation view are largely complementary and together have forged unity in a field that was previously hampered by lack of agreement about the definition of dreaming. They also integrate the philosophy of dreaming and scientific dream research.

As so often in debates about dreaming, there is disagreement about basic phenomenological questions. Revonsuo (2005) describes self-experience including bodily experience in dreams as identical to waking, whereas Metzinger (2003, 2009; see also Windt & Metzinger 2007) argues that important layers of waking self-experience (such as autobiographical memory, agency, a stable first-person perspective, metacognitive insight, and self-knowledge) are missing in nonlucid dreams. He argues this is due to the cognitive and mnemonic deficit that characterizes nonlucid dreams (cf. Hobson et al. 2000). Windt (2015a) analyzes the range of cognitive and bodily self-experience in dreams, both of which she describes as variable. She argues that in a majority of cases, dreams are weakly phenomenally embodied states in which bodily experience is largely related to movement sensations but a detailed and integrated body representation is lacking; instead, bodily experience in dreams is largely indeterminate (for an attempt to test this empirically, see Koppehele-Gossel et al. 2016). She proposes this is because dreams are also weakly functionally embodied states, in which the specific pattern of bodily experience reflects altered processing of bodily sensations (as in the illusion view). She also analyzes instances of bodiless dreams, in which dreamers say they experienced themselves as disembodied entities, to argue that self-experience can be reduced to pure spatiotemporal-self-location (Windt 2010); she proposes these cases can help identify the conditions for the emergence of minimal phenomenal selfhood (Blanke & Metzinger 2009; see also Metzinger 2013b).

How the phenomenology of dreaming compares to waking and what to say about how the dream self relates to the waking self bears on questions about the moral status of dreams. For Augustine ( Confessions ) dreams were a cause of moral concern because of their indistinguishability from waking life. What particularly worried him about dreams of sexual acts was their vividness, as well as the feeling of pleasure and seeming acquiescence or consent on the part of the dreamer. He concluded, however, that the transition from sleep to wakefulness involves a radical chasm, enabling the dreamer to awaken with a clear conscience and absolving them from taking responsibility for their dream actions.

What exactly Augustine thought the chasm between dreaming and waking consists in allows for different interpretations (Matthews 1981). Firstly, if the dream and waking self are not identical, then waking Augustine is not morally responsible for dream-Augustine’s actions. Secondly, actions performed in dreams might be morally irrelevant because they did not really happen. And thirdly, assuming that moral responsibility requires the ability to act otherwise, dreams provide no grounds for moral concern because we cannot refrain from having certain types of dreams.

The issue of dream immorality may also present a choice point between different accounts of moral evaluation. Where internalists assume the moral status of a person’s actions is entirely determined by internal factors such as intentions and motives, externalists look beyond these to the effects of actions. Driver (2007) argues that the absurdity of dream immorality itself should count against purely internalist accounts; yet she also acknowledges this absurdity is not a necessary feature of dreams.

Central to the question of dream immorality is the status of dreams as actions rather than mere behaviors. Mullane (1965) argues that while we don’t have full control over our dreams, they are not completely involuntary either; as is the case for blushing, considerable effort is required to attain control over our dreams and in some cases they can even be considered as actions. That lucid dream control is, to some extent, a learnable skill (Stumbrys et al. 2014) lends some support to this claim.

6. The meaning of dreams and the functions of dreaming

Philosophical discussions of dreaming tend to focus on (a) dream deception and (b) questions about the ontology of dreaming, its moral status, etc., that tend to intersect with dream skepticism. By contrast, the main source of interest in dreams outside of philosophy traditionally has been dream interpretation and whether dreams are a source of knowledge and insight. Historically, the epistemic status of dreams and the use of prophetic and diagnostic dreams was not just a theoretical, but a practical problem (Barbera 2008). Different types of dreams were distinguished by their putative epistemic value. Artemidorus, for instance, used the term enhypnion to refer to dreams that merely reflect the sleeper’s current bodily or psychological state and hence do not merit further interpretation, whereas he reserved the term oneiron for meaningful and symbolic dreams of divine origin.

The practice of dream interpretation was famously attacked by Aristotle in On Prophecy in Sleep . He denied that dreams are of divine origin, but allowed that occasionally, small affections of the sensory organs as might stem from distant events that cannot be perceived in waking are perceptible in the quiet of sleep. He also believed such dreams were mostly likely to occur in dullards whose minds resemble an empty desert – an assessment that was not apt to encourage interest in dreams (Kroker 2007: 37). A similarly negative view was held by early modern philosophers who believed dreams were often the source of superstitious beliefs (Hobbes 1651; Kant 1766; Schopenhauer 1847).

In Freudian dream theory, dream interpretation once more assumed a prominent role as the royal road to knowledge of the unconscious. This was associated with claims about the psychic sources of dreaming. Freud (1899) also rejected the influence of external or bodily sources, as championed by contemporary proponents of somatic-stimulus theory.

In the neuroscience of dreaming, Hobson famously argued that dreams are the product of the random, brain-stem driven activation of the brain during sleep (Hobson 1988) and at best enable personal insights in the same way as a Rorschach test (Hobson et al. 2000). Dennett (1991) illustrates the lack of design underlying the production of dream narratives through the “party game of psychoanalysis”, which involves an aimless game of question-and-answer. In the game, players follow simple rules to jointly produce narratives that can seem symbolic and meaningful, even though no intelligent and deliberate process of narration was involved.

Even if we grant that dreams are not messages from a hidden entity in need of decoding, this does not imply that dream interpretation cannot be a personally meaningful source of insight and creativity (Hobson & Wohl 2005). Whether and under which conditions, and following which methods, dream interpretation can lead to personally significant insights is an empirical question that is only beginning to be investigated systematically (see Edwards et al. 2013).

Finally, throughout history, views on the epistemic status of dreams and the type of knowledge to be gained from dream interpretation (e.g., knowledge about the future, diagnosis of physical illness, or insights about one’s current concerns) often changed in tandem with views on the origin and sources of dreaming, which gradually moved from divine origins and external sources, via the body, to the unconscious, and finally to the brain.

Different theories on the functions of dreaming have been proposed and the debate is ongoing. An important distinction is between the functions of sleep stages and the functions of dreaming. Well-documented functions of REM sleep include thermoregulation and the development of cortical structures in birds and mammals, as well as neurotransmitter repletion, the reconstruction and maintenance of little-used brain circuits, the structural development of the brain in early developmental phases, as well as the preparation of a repertoire of reflexive or instinctive behaviors (Hobson 2009). Yet none of these functions are obviously linked to dreaming. An exception is protoconsciousness theory, in which REM sleep plays an important role in foetal development by providing a virtual world model even before the emergence of full-blown consciousness (Hobson 2009: 808) .

Numerous studies have investigated the contribution of sleep to memory consolidation, with different sleep stages promoting different types of memories (Diekelmann et al. 2009; Walker 2009). However, only a few studies have investigated the relationship between dream content and memory consolidation in sleep (for a review, see Nielsen & Stenstrom 2005). Dreams rarely involve episodic replay of waking memories (Fosse et al. 2003). The incorporation of memory sources seems to follow a specific temporal pattern in which recent memories are integrated with older but semantically related memories (Blagrove et al. 2011). Nielsen (2017) presents a model of how external and bodily stimuli on one hand and short- and long-term memories on the other hand form seemingly novel, complex, and dreamlike images at sleep onset; he proposes these microdreams shed light on the formation and sources of more complex dreams. There is also some evidence that dream imagery might be associated with memory consolidation and task performance after sleep, though this is preliminary (Wamsley & Stickgold 2009, 2010; Wamsley et al. 2010).

Prominent theories on the function of dreaming focus on bad dreams and nightmares. It has long been thought that dreaming contributes to emotional processing and that this is particularly obvious in the dreams of nightmare sufferers or in dreams following traumatic experiences (e.g., Hartmann 1998; Nielsen & Lara-Carrasco 2007; Levin & Nielsen 2009; Cartwright 2010; Perogamvros et al. 2013). Based on the high prevalence of negative emotions and threatening dream content, threat simulation theory suggests that the evolutionary function of dreaming lies in the simulation of ancestral threats and the rehearsal of threatening events and avoidance skills in dreams has an adaptive value by enhancing the individual’s chances of survival (see Revonsuo 2000; Valli 2008). A more recent proposal is social simulation theory, in which social imagery in dreams supports social cognition, bonds, and social skills. (Revonsuo et al. 2015).

An evolutionary perspective can also be fruitfully applied to specific aspects of dream phenomenology. According to the vigilance hypothesis , natural selection disfavored the occurrence of those types of sensations during sleep that would compromise vigilance (Symons 1993). Dream sounds, but also smells or pains might distract attention from the potentially dangerous surroundings of the sleeping subject, and the vigilance hypothesis predicts that they only rarely occur in dreams without causing awakening. By contrast, because most mammals sleep with their eyes closed and in an immobile position, vivid visual and movement hallucinations during sleep would not comprise vigilance and thus can occur in dreams without endangering the sleeping subject. Focusing on the stuff dreams are not made of might then be at least as important for understanding the function of dreaming as developing a positive account.

Finally, even if dreaming in general and specific types of dream content in particular were found to be strongly associated with specific cognitive functions, it would still be possible that dreams are mere epiphenomena of brain activity during sleep (Flanagan 1995, 2000). It is also possible that the function of dreams is not knowable (Springett 2019).

A particular problem for any theory on the function of dreaming is to explain why a majority of dreams are forgotten and how dreams can fulfill their putative function independently of recall. Crick and Mitchinson (1983) famously proposed that REM sleep “erases” or deletes surplus information and unnecessary memories, which would suggest that enhanced dream recall is counterproductive. Another problem is that dreaming can be lost selectively and independently of other cognitive deficits (Solms 1997, 2000).

Some of the problems that arise for theories on the functions of dreaming can be avoided if we do not assume that dreaming has a specific function, separate from the function(s) of conscious wakeful states. This depends on the broader taxonomy of dreaming in relation to wakeful states. For example, if dreaming is continuous with waking mind wandering, imagination, and/or own-body perception, we should not expect it to have a unique function, but rather to express a similar function as these wakeful states, perhaps to varying degrees. Nor should we expect dreams to have a single function; the functions of dreaming might be as varied and complex as those of consciousness, and given the complexity of the target phenomenon, the failure to pin down a single function should not be surprising (Windt 2015a).

Questions about dreaming in different areas of philosophy such as epistemology, ontology, philosophy of mind and cognitive science, and ethics are closely intertwined. Scientific evidence from sleep and dream research can meaningfully inform the philosophical discussion and has often done so in the past. The discussion of dreaming has also often functioned as a lens on broader questions about knowledge, morality, consciousness, and self. Long a marginalized area, the philosophy of dreaming and of sleep is central to important philosophical questions and increasingly plays an important role in interdisciplinary consciousness research, for example in the search for the neural correlates of conscious states, in conscious state taxonomies, and in research on the minimal conditions for phenomenal selfhood and conscious experience.

  • Aleman, A. and F. Larøi, 2008, Hallucinations: The Science of Idiosyncratic Perception , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • Andrillon, T., J. Windt, T. Silk, S. Drummond, M. Bellgrove, and N. Tsuchiya, 2019, “Does the mind wander when the brain takes a break? Local sleep in wakefulness, attentional lapses and mind-wandering”, Frontiers in Neuroscience , 13(949), doi:10.3389/fnins.2019.00949
  • Antrobus, J.S., 1990, “The Neurocognition of Sleep Mentation: Rapid Eye Movements, Visual Imagery, and Dreaming”, in Sleep and Cognition , R. Bootzin, J. Kihlstrom, and D. Schacter (eds.), Washington: American Psychological Association, pp. 3–24.
  • Aristotle, On Dreams , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • –––, On Prophecy in Sleep , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • –––, On Sleeping and Waking , in Aristotle: On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath , (Loeb Classical Library No. 288), W.S. Hett (ed.), Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press, 1986.
  • Artemidorus, The Interpretation of Dreams , R.J. White (ed.), New Jersey: Noyes Press, 1975.
  • Aserinsky, E. and N. Kleitman, 1953, “Regularly Occurring Periods of Eye Motility and Concurrent Phenomena during Sleep”, Sleep Medicine Review , 118: 273–274.
  • –––, 1955, “Two Types of Ocular Motility Occurring in Sleep”, Journal of Applied Physiology , 8: 1–10.
  • Augustine, Against the Academics , J.J. O’Meara (ed.), Westminster, MD: Newman Press, 1950.
  • –––, Confessions , H. Chadwick (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
  • Austin, J.L., 1962, Sense and Sensibilia , G.J. Warnock (ed.), Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Ayer, A.J., 1960, “Professor Malcolm on Dreams”, Journal of Philosophy , 57: 517–535.
  • Baillet, A., 1691, La Vie de Monsieur Descartes , Paris: La Table Ronde.
  • Baird, B., S. Mota-Rolim, and M. Dresler, 2019, “The cognitive neuroscience of lucid dreaming”, Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews , 100: 305–323.
  • Baldridge, B.J., 1966, “Physical Concomittants of Dreaming and the Effect of Stimulation on Dreams”, Ohio State Medical Journal , 62: 1272–1275.
  • Barbera, J., 2008, “Sleep and Dreaming in Greek and Roman Philosophy”, Sleep Medicine , 9: 906–910.
  • Barrett, D. and P. McNamara (eds.), 2007a, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 1: Biological Aspects , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • ––– (eds.), 2007b, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 2: Content, Recall, Personality Correlates , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • ––– (eds.), 2007c, The New Science of Dreaming, Volume 3: Cultural and Theoretical Perspectives , Westport: Praeger Perspectives.
  • Bayne, T.J. and E. Pacherie, 2005, “In Defence of the Doxastic Conception of Delusions”, Mind and Language , 20(2): 163–188.
  • Berger, R.J., 1963, “Experimental Modification of Dream Content by Meaningful Verbal Stimuli”, British Journal of Psychiatry , 109: 722–740.
  • Bergson, H., 1914, Dreams , E.E. Slosson (ed. and trans.), New York: B.W. Huebsch. [ Bergson 1914 available online ]
  • Berkeley, G., 1710, “A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge”, in Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues , H. Robinson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 1–96.
  • Binz, C., 1878, Über den Traum , Bonn: Adolph Marcus.
  • Blanke, O. and T. Metzinger, 2009, “Full-Body Illusions and Minimal Phenomenal Selfhood”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 13(1): 7–13.
  • Block, N., 2007, “Consciousness, Accessibility, and the Mesh between Psychology and Neuroscience”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 30: 499–548.
  • Blumberg, M., 2010, “Beyond dreams: do sleep-related movements contribute to brain development?”, Frontiers in Neurology , 1(140), doi:10.3389/fneur.2010.00140
  • Blumberg, M., and A. Plumeau, 2016, “A new view of ‘dream enactment’ in REM sleep behavior disorder”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 30: 34–42.
  • Bortolotti, L., 2009, Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bostrom, N., 2003, “Are We Living in a Computer Simulation?”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 53(211): 243–255.
  • Bourdin, P., 1641, “Seventh Set of Objections”, reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 214–231.
  • Bradley, F.H., 1894, “The Failure of Movement in Dream”, Mind , 3(11): 373–377.
  • Breger, L., I. Hunter, and R.W. Lane, 1971, The Effect of Stress on Dreams , New York: International Universities Press.
  • Broughton, J., 2002, Descartes’s Method of Doubt , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2006, “Impressions and Ideas”, in The Blackwell Guide to Hume’s Treatise , S. Traiger (ed.), Malden, MA & Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 43–57.
  • Browne, A., 1977, “Descartes’s Dreams”, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes , 40: 256–273.
  • Bucci, A., and M. Grasso, 2017, “Sleep and dreaming in the predictive processing framework”, in T. Metzinger and W. Wiese (eds.), Philosophy and Predictive Processing (Volume 6), Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Canfield, J.V., 1961, “Judgments in Sleep”, The Philosophical Review , 70: 224–230.
  • Cartwright, R.D., 2010, The Twenty-four Hour Mind: The Role of Sleep and Dreaming in our Emotional Lives , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Chalmers, D.J., 2005, “The Matrix as Metaphysics”, in Grau 2005: 132–176.
  • Chihara, C.S., 1965, “What Dreams Are Made On”, Theoria , 31: 145–158.
  • Chihara, C.S. and J.A. Fodor, 1965, “Operationalism and Ordinary Language: A Critique of Wittgenstein”, American Philosophical Quarterly 2: 281–295; page reference is to the reprint in Dunlop 1977.
  • Christoff, K., Z. Irving, K. Fox, R. Spreng, and J. Andrews-Hanna, 2016, “Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 17(11): 718–731.
  • Churchland, P.S., 1988, “Reduction and the Neurobiological Basis of Consciousness”, in Consciousness in Contemporary Science , A. Marcel and E. Bisiach (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 273–304.
  • Clark, A., 2005, “The Twisted Matrix: Dream, Simulation, or Hybrid?”, in Grau 2005: 177–197.
  • –––, 2013a, “Dreaming the Whole Cat: Generative Models, Predictive Processing, and the Enactivist Conception of Perceptual Experience”, Mind , 121(483), 753–771.
  • –––, 2013b, “Whatever Next? Predictive Brains, Situated Agents, and the Future of Cognitive Science”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 36(03), 181–204.
  • Clarke, D.M., 2006, Descartes: A Biography , Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cohen, M.A. and D.C. Dennett, 2011, “Consciousness Cannot Be Separated from Function”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15(8), 358–364.
  • Cole, J.R., 1992, The Olympian Dreams and Youthful Rebellion of René Descartes , Urbana & Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
  • Conrad, T., 1968, Zur Wesenslehre des psychischen Lebens und Erlebens , (Phaenomenologica: Vol. 27), DenHaag: Nijhoff.
  • Crane, T. and C. French, 2017, “The Problem of Perception”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/perception-problem/ >.
  • Crick, F. and G. Mitchinson, 1983, “The Function of Dream Sleep”, Nature , 304, 111–114.
  • Crowther, T., 2018, “Experience, dreaming, and the phenomenology of wakeful consciousness”, in F. Dorsch, F. MacPherson, & M. Nida-Rumelin (eds.), Phenomenal Presence , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Currie, G., 2000, “Imagination, Delusion and Hallucination”, Mind & Language , 15(1), 168–183.
  • Currie, G. and I. Ravenscroft, 2002, Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • D’Agostino, A., A. Castelnovo, and S. Scarone, 2013, “Dreaming and the Neurobiology of Self: Recent Advances and Implications for Psychiatry”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00680 [ available online ]
  • Dang-Vu, T.T., M. Schabus, M. Desseilles, S. Schwartz, P. Maquet, 2007, “Neuroimaging of Sleep and Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007a: 95–114.
  • Dement, W.C., 1999, The Promise of Sleep. The Scientific Connection between Health, Happiness and a Good Night’s Sleep , London: Pan Books.
  • Dement, W.C. and N. Kleitman, 1957, “The Relation of Eye Movements during Sleep to Dream Activity: An Objective Method for the Study of Dreaming”, Journal of Experimental Psychology , 53: 89–97.
  • Dement, W.C. and E. Wolpert, 1958, “The Relation of Eye Movements, Body Motility, and External Stimuli to Dream Content”, Journal of Experimental Psychology , 55: 543–553.
  • Dennett, D.C., 1976, “Are dreams experiences?”, The Philosophical Review , 85(2): 151–171.
  • –––, 1979, “The Onus Re Experiences: A Reply to Emmett”, Philosophical Studies , 35(April): 315–318.
  • –––, 1991, Consciousness Explained . Boston, New York & London: Little, Brown and Company.
  • Descartes, R., 1637, Discourse on the Method of Rightly Conducting the Reason, and Seeking Truth in the Sciences ., G.B. Rawlings (ed.). [ Descartes 1637 available online ]
  • –––, 1641, Meditations on First Philosophy , reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 1–64.
  • Desseilles, M., T.T. Dang-Vu, V. Sterpenich, and S. Schwartz, 2011, “Cognitive and Emotional Processes during Dreaming: A Neuroimaging View”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 998–1008.
  • Diekelmann, S., I. Wilhelm, and J. Born, 2009, “The Whats and Whens of Sleep-Dependent Memory Consolidation”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 13(5): 309–321.
  • Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers , R.D. Hicks (ed.), Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1943.
  • Domhoff, G.W., 2001, “A New Neurocognitive Theory of Dreams”, Dreaming , 11: 13–33.
  • –––, 2003, The Scientific Study of Dreams: Neural Networks, Cognitive Development, and Content Analysis , Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
  • –––, 2011, “The Neural Substrate for Dreaming: Is It a Subsystem of the Default Network?”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 1163–1174.
  • Dreisbach, C., 2000, “Dreams in the History of Philosophy”, Dreaming , 10(1): 31–41.
  • Dresler, M., S.P. Koch, R. Wehrle, V.I. Spoormaker, F. Holsboer, A. Steiger, P. Sämann, H. Obrig, and M. Czisch, 2011, “Dreamed Movement Elicits Activation in the Sensorimotor Cortex”, Current Biology , 21(21): 1833–1837.
  • Dresler, M., R. Wehrle, V.I. Spoormaker, S.P. Koch, F. Holsboer, A. Steiger, H. Obrig, P. Sämann, and M. Czisch, 2012, “Neural Correlates of Dream Lucidity Obtained from Contrasting Lucid versus Non-lucid REM Sleep: A Combined EEG/fMRI Case Study”, Sleep , 35(7): 1017–1020.
  • Driver, J., 2007, “Dream immorality”, Philosophy , 82(1): 5–22.
  • Dunlop, C.E.M. (ed.), 1977, Philosophical Essays on Dreaming . Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press.
  • Edwards, C.L., P.M. Ruby, J.E. Malinowski, P.D. Bennett, and M.T. Blagrove, 2013, “Dreaming and Insight”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00979 [ available online ]
  • Ellis, H., 1911, The World of Dreams , London: Constable & Company LTD.
  • Emmett, K., 1978, “Oneiric Experiences”, Philosophical Studies , 34(November): 445–450.
  • Erlacher, D., M. Schredl, and S. LaBerge, S., 2003, “Motor Area Activation during Dreamed Hand Clenching: A Pilot Study on EEG Alpha Band”, Sleep and Hypnosis , 5: 182–187.
  • Erlacher, D., M. Schädlich, T. Stumbrys, and M. Schredl, 2014, “Time for Actions in Lucid Dreams: Effects of Task Modality, Length, and Complexity”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.01013 [ available online ]
  • Fazekas, P., and G. Nemeth, 2018, “Dream experiences and the neural correlates of perceptual consciousness and cognitive access”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B (Biological Sciences), 373(1755): 20170356.
  • Fazekas, P., G. Nemeth, and M. Overgaard, 2019, “White dreams are made of colours: What studying contentless dreams can teach about the neural basis of dreaming and conscious experiences”, Sleep Medicine Reviews , 43: 84–91.
  • ffytche, D.H., 2007, “Visual Hallucinatory Syndromes: Past, Present, and Future”, Dialogues in Clinical Neuroscience , 9(2): 173–189.
  • ffytche, D.H., J.D. Blom, and M. Catani, 2010, “Disorders of Visual Perception”, Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry , 81(11): 1280–1287.
  • Flanagan, O., 1995, “Deconstructing Dreams: The Spandrels of Sleep”, The Journal of Philosophy , 92: 5–27.
  • –––, 2000, Dreaming Souls: Sleep, Dreams, and the Evolution of the Conscious Mind , Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Fletcher, P.C. and C.D. Frith, 2008, “Perceiving is Believing: A Bayesian Approach to Explaining the Positive Symptoms of Schizophrenia”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 10(1): 48–58.
  • Fosse, M.J., R. Fosse, J.A. Hobson, and R.J. Stickgold, 2003, “Dreaming and Episodic Memory: A Functional Dissociation?”, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 15: 1–9.
  • Foulkes, D., 1978, A Grammar of Dreams , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1993a, “Children’s Dreaming”, in Dreaming as Cognition , C. Cavallero and D. Foulkes (eds.), New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, pp. 114–132.
  • –––, 1993b, “Dreaming and REM Sleep”, Journal of Sleep Research , 2:199–202.
  • –––, 1999, Children’s Dreaming and the Development of Consciousness , Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.
  • Fox, K.C.R., S. Nijeboer, E. Solomonova, G.W. Domhoff, and K. Christoff, 2013, “Dreaming as Mind Wandering: Evidence from Functional Neuroimaging and First-Person Content Reports”, Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7, doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00412 [ available online ]
  • Frankfurt, H.G., 1970, Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes’s Meditations , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • Freud, S., 1899, Die Traumdeutung , Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag (2003).
  • –––, 1940, Schriften über Träume und Traumdeutungen , Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag (2003).
  • Galen, On Diagnosis in Dreams , L. Pearcy (ed.), < available online >.
  • Gerrans, P., 2012, “Dream Experience and a Revisionist Account of Delusions of Misidentification”, Consciousness and Cognition , 21(1): 217–227.
  • –––, 2013, “Delusional Attitudes and Default Thinking”, Mind & Language , 28(1): 83–102.
  • –––, 2014, “Pathologies of Hyperfamiliarity in Dreams, Delusions and Déjà Vu”, Frontiers in Psychology , 5, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00097 [ available online ]
  • Globus, G.G., 1987, Dream Life, Wake Life: The Human Condition Through Dreams , New York: State University of New York Press.
  • Goblot, 1896, “Sur le souvenir des rêves”, Revue philosophique , XLII .
  • Gottesmann, C., 2006, “The Dreaming Sleep Stage: A New Neurobiological Model of Schizophrenia?”, Neuroscience , 140: 1105–1115.
  • Grau, C. (ed.), 2005, Philosophers Explore the Matrix , C. Grau (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gregory, J.C., 1916, “Dreams as Psychical Explosions”, Mind , 25(98): 193–205.
  • –––, 1918, “The Dream of ‘Frustrated Effort’: A Suggested Explanation”, Mind , 27(105): 125–128.
  • Grundmann, T., 2002, “Die Struktur des skeptischen Traumarguments”, Grazer Philosophische Studien , 64: 57–81.
  • Hacking, I., 2001, “Dreams in Place”, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , 59(3):244–260.
  • Hall, C.S., 1981, “Do We Dream during Sleep? Evidence for the Globot Hypothesis”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 53(1): 239–246.
  • Hartmann, E., 1998, Dreams and Nightmares: The New Theory on the Origin and Meaning of Dreams , Cambridge: Perseus Books.
  • Hearne, K., 1978, Lucid Dreams: An Electro-Physiological and Psychological Study , (Ph.D. thesis), University of Liverpool, England. [ Hearne 1978 available online ]
  • Hering, J., 1947, “Concerning Image, Idea, and Dream”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 8(2): 188–205.
  • Hobbes, T., 1651, Leviathan , C.B. Macpherson (ed.), London: Penguin (1985).
  • –––, 1641, “Third Set of Objections”, reprinted in Moriarty 2008: 107–124.
  • Hobson, J.A., 1988, The Dreaming Brain , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1999, Dreaming as Delirium. How the Brain Goes Out of Its Mind , Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2009, “REM Sleep and Dreaming: Towards a Theory of Protoconsciousness”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 10(November): 803–813.
  • Hobson, J. and K. Friston, 2012, “Waking and Dreaming Consciousness: Neurobiological and Functional Considerations”, Progress in Neurobiology , 98(1): 82–98.
  • Hobson, J., E.F. Pace-Schott, and R. Stickgold, 2000, “Dreaming and the Brain. Toward a Cognitive Neuroscience of Conscious States”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 793–842.
  • Hobson, J. and H. Wohl, 2005, From Angels to Neurones. Art and the New Science of Dreaming , Parma: Mattioli 1885.
  • Hodges, M. and W.R. Carter, 1969, “Nelson on Dreaming a Pain”, Philosophical Studies , 20(3): 43–46.
  • Hoelscher, T.J., E. Klinger, and S.G. Barta, 1981, “Incorporation of Concern- and Nonconcern-related Verbal Stimuli into Dream Content”, Journal of Abnormal Psychology , 90: 88–91.
  • Hohwy, J., 2013, The Predictive Mind , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Horikawa, T., M. Tamaki, Y. Miyawaki, and Y. Kamitani, 2013, “Neural Decoding of Visual Imagery during Sleep”, Science 340 (6132): 639–642.
  • Hoss, R.J., 2010, “Content Analysis on the Potential Significance of Color in Dreams: A Preliminary Investigation”, International Journal of Dream Research , 3(1): 80–90.
  • Hume, D., 1739, A Treatise of Human Nature , D.F. Norton, M.J. Norton (eds.), Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press (2000).
  • Hunter, J. F. M., 1983, “The difference between dreaming and being awake”, Mind , 92(365): 80–93.
  • Hurlburt, R.T. and E. Schwitzgebel, 2007, Describing Inner Experience?: Proponent Meets Skeptic , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Husserl, E., 1904/1905, Phantasie und Bildbewußtsein , E. Marbach (ed.), Hamburg: Felix Meiner (2006).
  • Ichikawa, J., 2008, “Scepticism and the Imagination Model of Dreaming”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 58(232): 519–527.
  • –––, 2009, “Dreaming and Imagination”, Mind & Language , 24(1): 103–121.
  • James, W., 1890, The Principles of Psychology , Volume Two, New York: Dover Publications (1950).
  • Jouvet, M., 1999, The Paradox of Sleep: The Story of Dreaming , L. Garey (ed.), Cambridge & London: MIT Press.
  • Kahn, D., E.F. Pace-Schott, and J.A. Hobson, 2002, “Emotion and Cognition: Feeling and Character Identification in Dreaming”, Consciousness and Cognition , 11: 34–50.
  • Kahn, D., R. Stickgold, E.F. Pace-Schott, and J.A. Hobson, 2000, “Dreaming and Waking Consciousness: A Character Recognition Study”, Journal of Sleep Research , 9: 317–325.
  • Kant, I., 1766 [2002], Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume der Metaphysik , Stuttgart: Reclam.
  • Kantor, J., 1970, “Pinching and Dreaming”, Philosophical Studies , 21(1–2): 28–32.
  • Keefer, M.H., 1996, “The Dreamer’s Path: Descartes and the Sixteenth Century”, Renaissance Quarterly , 49(1): 30–76.
  • Kind, A., 2013, “The heterogeneity of the imagination”, Erkenntnis , 78(1): 141–159.
  • Klein, P., 2015, “Skepticism”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/skepticism/ >.
  • Koppehele-Gossel, J., A. Klimke, K. Schermelleh-Engel, and U. Voss, 2016, “A template model of embodiment while dreaming: Proposal of a mini-me.” Consciousness and Cognition , 46: 148–162.
  • Koulack, D., 1969, “Effects of Somatosensory Stimulation on Dream Content”, Archives of General Psychiatry , (20): 718–725.
  • Kramer, M., 2007, The Dream Experience: A Systematic Exploration , New York & London: Routledge.
  • Kroker, K., 2007, The Sleep of Others and the Transformations of Sleep Research , Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
  • LaBerge, S., 2007, “Lucid Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007a: 307–328.
  • LaBerge, S., L.E. Nagel, W.C. Dement, and V.P. Zarcone, 1981, “Lucid Dreaming Verified by Volitional Communication during REM Sleep”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 52: 727–732.
  • LaBerge, S., B. Baird, and P. Zimbardo, 2018, “Smooth tracking of visual targets distinguishes lucid REM sleep dreaming and waking perception from imagination”, Nature Communications , 9(1), doi:10.1038/s41467-018-05547-0
  • Leclair-Visonneau, L., D. Oudiette, B. Gaymard, S. Leu-Semenescu, and I. Arnulf, 2010, “Do the Eyes Scan Dream Images during Rapid Eye Movement Sleep? Evidence from the Rapid Eye Movement Sleep Behaviour Disorder Model”, Brain , 133(6): 1737–1746.
  • Leibniz, G.W., 1880, Die Philosophischen Schriften , Berlin: Weidmannsche Buchhandlung.
  • –––, Philosophical Papers and Letters , L.E. Loemker (ed.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956.
  • Levin, R. and T.A. Nielsen, 2009, “Nightmares, Bad Dreams, and Emotions Dysregulation: A Review and New Neurocognitive Model of Dreaming”, Current Directions in Psychological Science , 18(2): 84–88.
  • Lewis, H.D., 1969, The Elusive Mind , London: George Allan & Unwin LTD.
  • Liao, Shen-yi and Gendler, Tamar, “Imagination”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/imagination/ >.
  • Limosani, I., A. D’Agostino, M.L. Manzone, and S. Scarone, 2011a, “The Dreaming Brain/Mind, Consciousness and Psychosis”, Consciousness & Cognition , 20(4): 987–992.
  • –––, 2011b, “Bizarreness in Dream Reports and Waking Fantasies of Psychotic, Schizophrenic and Manic Patients: Empirical Evidences and Theoretical Consequences”, Psychiatry Research , 189(2): 195–199.
  • Llinás, R. and D. Paré, 1991, “Of Dreaming and Wakefulness”, Neuroscience , 44: 521–535.
  • Llinás, R. and U. Ribary, 1994, “Perception as an Oneiric-like State Modulated by the Senses”, in Large-Scale Neuronal Theories of the Brain , C. Koch and J. Davis (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 111–124.
  • Locke, J., 1689, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding , R. Woolhouse (ed.), London: Penguin (1997).
  • Macnish, R., 1838, The Philosophy of Sleep , Glasgow: W.R. M’Phun.
  • Macpherson, F., 2013, “The Philosophy and Psychology of Hallucination: An Introduction”, in Hallucination. Philosophy and Psychology , F. Macpherson and D. Platchias (eds.), Cambridge MA: MIT Press, pp. 1–38.
  • Malcolm, N., 1956, “Dreaming and Skepticism”, The Philosophical Review , 65(1): 14–37.
  • –––, 1959, Dreaming , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Matthews, G.B., 1981, “On Being Immoral in a Dream”, Philosophy , 56(January): 47–64.
  • –––, 2005, Augustine , Malden, MA: Blackwell Pub.
  • Maury, L.-F. A., 1861, Le sommeil et les rêves: études psychologiques sur ces phénomènes et les divers états qui s’y rattachent , Paris: Didier et Cie Libraires-Éditeurs.
  • McGinn, C., 2004, Mindsight: Image, Dream, Meaning , Cambridge, MA & London: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2005a, “The Matrix of Dreams”, in Grau 2005: 62–70.
  • –––, 2005b, The Power of Movies: How Screen and Mind Interact , New York: Vintage Books.
  • Metzinger, T., 2003, Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2009, The Ego Tunnel: The Science of the Mind and the Myth of the Self , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 2013a, “The Myth of Cognitive Agency: Subpersonal Thinking as a Cyclically Recurring Loss of Mental Autonomy”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00931 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2013b, “Why Are Dreams Interesting for Philosophers? The Example of Minimal Phenomenal Selfhood, Plus an Agenda for Future Research”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00746 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015, “M-autonomy”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 22(11–12): 270–302.
  • Montaigne, M. de, “The Apology for Raymond Sebond”, in Readings in the History of Philosophy , R.M. Popkin (ed.), The Philosophy of the 16th and 17th Centuries , Toronto: Collier-Macmillan (1966): 70–81.
  • Moriarty, M. (ed.), 2008, Meditations, Objections, and Replies , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Mullane, H., 1965, “Moral Responsibility for Dreams”, Dialogue , 4(02): 224–229.
  • –––, 1966, “Dreaming as an Action”, Dialogue , 5(02): 239–242.
  • Murzyn, E., 2008, “Do We Only Dream in Colour? A Comparison of Reported Dream Colour in Younger and Older Adults with Different Experiences of Black and White Media”, Consciousness and Cognition , 17: 1228–1237.
  • Nagel, T., 1959, “Dreaming”, Analysis , 19(5): 112–116.
  • –––, 1974, “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?”, Philosophical Review , 83: 435–450.
  • Nelson, J.O., 1966, “Can One Tell that He is Awake by Pinching Himself?”, Philosophical Studies , 17(6): 81–84.
  • Nemeth, G., and P. Fazekas, 2018, “Beyond the REM--NREM Dichotomy: A Multidimensional Approach to Understanding Dreaming”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 25(11–12): 13–33.
  • Newman, L., 2019, “Descartes’ Epistemology”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = < https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/descartes-epistemology/ >.
  • Nielsen, T.A., 2000, “A Review of Mentation in REM and NREM Sleep: ‘Covert’ REM Sleep as a Possible Reconciliation of Two Opposing Models”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23(6): 851–866.
  • –––, 2010, “Dream Analysis and Classification: The Reality Simulation Perspective”, in Principles and Practice of Sleep Medicine , M. Kryger, T. Roth, and W.C. Dement (eds.), New York: Elsevier, pp. 595–603.
  • –––, 2017, “Microdream neurophenomenology”, Neuroscience of Consciousness , 1: nix001; doi:10.1093/nc/nix001
  • Nielsen, T.A. and J. Lara-Carrasco, 2007, “Nightmares, Dreaming, and Emotion Regulation: A Review”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007b: 253–284.
  • Nielsen, T.A. and P. Stenstrom, 2005, “What Are the Memory Sources of Dreaming?”, Nature , 437(7063): 1286–1289.
  • Nielsen, T.A., L. Ouellet, and A.L. Zadra, 1995, “Pressure Stimulation during REM Sleep Alters Dream Limb Activity and Body Bizarreness”, Sleep Research , 24: 134.
  • Nielsen, T.A., C. Svob, and D. Kuiken, 2009, “Dream-Enacting Behaviors in a Normal Population”, Sleep , 32(12): 1629–1636.
  • Nir, Y. and G. Tononi, 2010, “Dreaming and the Brain: From Phenomenology to Neurophysiology”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 14(2): 88–100.
  • Noë, A., 2004, Action in Perception , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Noreika, V., K. Valli, H. Lahtela, and A. Revonsuo. “Early-night serial awakenings as a new paradigm for studies on NREM dreaming”, International Journal of Psychophysiology , 74(1): 14–18.
  • O’Shaughnessy, B., 2002, “Dreaming”, Inquiry , 45: 399–432.
  • Pace-Schott, E.F., 2007, “The Frontal Lobes and Dreaming”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007b: 115–154.
  • –––, 2013, “Dreaming as a Story-Telling Instinct”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00159 [ available online ]
  • Pagel, J.F., M. Blagrove, R. Levin, B. States, B. Stickgold, and S. White, 2001, “Definitions of Dream: A Paradigm for Comparing Field Descriptive Specific Studies of Dream”, Dreaming , 11: 195–202.
  • Pantani, M., A. Tagini, and A. Raffone, 2018, “Phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness and self across waking and dreaming: bridging phenomenology and neuroscience”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17(1): 175–197.
  • Perogamvros, L., T.T. Dang-Vu, M. Desseilles, S. Schwartz, 2013, “Sleep and Dreaming Are for Important Matters”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00474 [ available online ]
  • Plato, Phaedrus , B. Jowett (ed.), in The Internet Classics Archive , available online .
  • –––, Theaetetus , B. Jowett (ed.), in The Internet Classics Archive , available online .
  • Prasad, H.S., 2000, “Dreamless Sleep and Soul: a controversy between Vedānta and Buddhism”, Asian Philosophy , 10(1): 61–73. doi:10.1080/09552360050001770
  • Putnam, H., 1981, “Brains in a Vat”, in Reason, Truth and History , H. Putnam (ed.), Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–21.
  • –––, 1962 [1986], “Dreaming and ‘Depth Grammar’”, in Analytical Philosophy First Series , R. Butler (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell & Mott; page reference is to the reprint in H. Putnam (ed.), 1986, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2.: Mind, Language and Reality , Cambridge: University Press, pp. 304–324.
  • Rechtschaffen, A. and C. Buchignani, 1992, “The Visual Appearance of Dreams”, in The Neuropsychology of Sleep and Dreaming , J.S. Antrobus and M. Bertini (eds.), Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 143–156.
  • Reed, T.M., 1979, “Dreams, Scepticism and Waking Life”, in Body, Mind, and Method. Essays in Honor of Virgil C. Aldrich , D.F. Gustafson and B.L. Tapscott (eds.), Dodrecht & Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, pp. 37–64.
  • Resnick, J., R. Stickgold, C.D. Rittenhouse, and J.A. Hobson, 1994, “Self-Representation and Bizarreness in Children’s Dream Reports Collected in the Home Setting”, Consciousness and Cognition , 3: 30–45.
  • Revonsuo, A., 2000, “The Reinterpretation of Dreams: An Evolutionary Hypothesis of the Function of Dreaming”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 877–901.
  • –––, 2005, “The Self in Dreams”, in The Lost Self. Pathologies of the Brain and Identity , T.E. Feinberg and J.P. Keenan (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 206–219.
  • –––, 2006, Inner Presence: Consciousness as a Biological Phenomenon , Cambridge, MA & London: MIT Press.
  • Revonsuo, A. and C. Salmivalli, 1995, “A Content Analysis of Bizarre Elements in Dreams”, Dreaming , 5:169–187.
  • Revonsuo, A. and K. Tarkko, 2002, “Binding in Dreams. The Bizarreness of Dream Images and the Unity of Consciousness”, Journal of Consciousness Studies , 9: 3–24.
  • Revonsuo, A., J. Tuominen, and K. Valli, 2015, “The Avatars in the Machine – Dreaming as a Simulation of Social Reality”, in T. Metzinger and J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Rosen, M.G., 2013, “What I Make up when I Wake up: Anti-Experience Views and Narrative Fabrication of Dreams”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00514 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015, “I’m thinking your thoughts while I sleep: Sense of agency and ownership over dream thought”, Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice , 2(3): 326–339.
  • –––, 2018a, “Enactive or inactive? Cranially envatted dream experience and the extended conscious mind”, Philosophical Explorations , 21(2): 295–318.
  • –––, 2018b, “How bizarre? A pluralist approach to dream content”, Consciousness and Cognition , 62: 148–162.
  • –––, forthcoming, “Dreaming of a stable world: vision and action in sleep”, first online 22 February 2019 Synthese , doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02149-1
  • Rosen, M.G. and J. Sutton, 2013, “Self-Representation and Perspectives in Dreams”, Philosophy Compass , 8(11): 1041–1053.
  • Russell, B., 1914, Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy , London & New York: Routledge (2009).
  • –––, 1948, Human Knowledge: It’s Scope and Limits , London & New York: Routledge (2009).
  • Ryle, G., 1949, The Concept of Mind , Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
  • Sartre, J.-P., 1940, L’imaginaire: Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination , Paris: Gallimard, 2005.
  • Sauvageau, A., T.A. Nielsen, and J. Montplaisir, 1998, “Effects of Somatosensory Stimulation on Dream Content in Gymnasts and Control Participants: Evidence of Vestibulomotor Adaptation in REM Sleep”, Dreaming , 8: 125–134.
  • Scarone, S., M.L. Manzone, O. Gambini, I. Kantzas, I. Limosani, A. D’Agostino, and J.A. Hobson, 2007, “The Dream as a Model for Psychosis: An Experimental Approach Using Bizarreness as a Cognitive Marker”, Schizophrenia Bulletin , 34(3): 515–522.
  • Schenck, C.H. 2005, Paradox Lost: Midnight in the Battleground of Sleep and Dreams , Minneapolis: Extreme Nights, LLC.
  • Schenck, C.H. and M.W. Mahowald, 1996, “REM Sleep Parasomnias”, Neurological Clinics , 14: 697–720.
  • Scherner, K.A., 1861, Das Leben des Traumes , Berlin: Verlag von Heinrich Schindler.
  • Schooler, J.W., J. Smallwood, K. Christoff, T.C. Handy, E.D. Reichle, and M.A. Sayette, 2011, “Meta-awareness, Perceptual Decoupling and the Wandering Mind”, Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15(7): 319–326.
  • Schopenhauer, A., 1847, Kleinere Schriften , Zürich: Haffmans Verlag (1988).
  • Schredl, M., 2006, “Factors Affecting the Continuity between Waking and Dreaming: Emotional Intensity and Emotional Tone of the Waking-Life Event”, Sleep and Hypnosis , 8: 1–5.
  • –––, 2010, “History of Dream Research: The Dissertation ‘Entstehung der Träume (Origin of Dreams)’ of Wilhelm Weygandt Published in 1893”, International Journal of Dream Research , 3(1): 95–97.
  • Schredl, M. and F. Hofmann, 2003, “Continuity between Waking Activities and Dream Activities”, Consciousness and Cognition , 12: 298–308.
  • Schredl, M., A. Fuchedzhieva, H. Hämig, and V. Schindele, 2008, “Do We Think Dreams Are in Black and White Due to Memory Problems?”, Dreaming , 18(3): 175–180.
  • Schröder, S., 1997, “The Concept of Dreaming: On Three Theses by Malcolm”, Philosophical Investigations , 20(1): 15–38.
  • Schwitzgebel, E., 2002, “Why Did We Think We Dreamed in Black and White?”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science , 33: 649–660.
  • –––, 2003, “Do People Still Report Dreaming in Black and White? An Attempt to Replicate a Questionnaire from 1942”, Perceptual and Motor Skills , 96: 25–29.
  • –––, 2011, Perplexities of Consciousness , Cambridge & London: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2017, “1% Skepticism”, Noûs , 51(2): 271–290.
  • Schwitzgebel, E., C. Huang, and Y. Zhou, 2006, “Do We Dream in Color? Cultural Variations and Skepticism”, Dreaming , 16(1): 36–42.
  • Searle, J., 2000, “Consciousness”, Annual Review of Neuroscience , 23: 557–578.
  • Sebastián, M., 2014a, “Dreams: An Empirical Way to Settle the Discussion between Cognitive and Non-Cognitive Theories of Consciousness”, Synthese , 191(2): 263–285.
  • –––, 2014b, “Not a HOT dream”, In Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience, Springer, Dordrecht, pp. 415–432.
  • Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism , R.G. Bury (ed.), Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1987).
  • Siclari, F., and G. Tononi, 2017, “Local aspects of sleep and wakefulness”, Current Opinion in Neurobiology , 44: 222–227.
  • Siclari, F., J. LaRocque, B. Postle, and G. Tononi, 2013, “Assessing sleep consciousness within subjects using a serial awakening paradigm”, Frontiers in psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00542
  • Siclari, F., B. Baird, L. Perogamvros, G. Bernardi, J. LaRocque, B. Riedner, M. Boly, B. Postle, and G. Tononi, 2017, “The neural correlates of dreaming”, Nature Neuroscience , 20(6): 872.
  • Siegler, F.A., 1967, “Remembering Dreams”, The Philosophical Quarterly , 17: 14–24.
  • Silberer, H., 1919, Der Traum: Einführung in die Traumpsychologie , Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.
  • Singer, E.A., 1924, “On Pain in Dreams”, The Journal of Philosophy , 21(22): 589–601.
  • Smallwood, J. and J.W. Schooler, 2015, “The science of mind wandering: empirically navigating the stream of consciousness”, Annual review of psychology , 66: 487–518.
  • Smith, A.D., 2002, The Problem of Perception , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Solms, M., 1997, The Neuropsychology of Dreams: A Clinico-Anatomical Study , Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
  • –––, 2000, “Dreaming and REM Sleep Are Controlled by Different Brain Mechanisms”, Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 23: 843–850.
  • Sosa, E., 2007, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge , Volume I, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Soteriou, M., forthcoming, “Dreams, agency, and judgement”, Synthese , first online 20 July 2017, doi: 10.1007/s11229-017-1496-7
  • Springett, B., 2019, “Can we know about the evolution of dreaming?”, Dreaming , 29(3): 220.
  • Stickgold, R. and M.P. Walker (eds.), 2009, The Neuroscience of Sleep , London, Burlington MA, San Diego: Elsevier: Academic Press.
  • Stone, J., 1984, “Dreaming and Certainty”, Philosophical Studies , 45(May): 353–368.
  • Stroud, B., 1984, The Significance of Philosophical Scepticism , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Stumbrys, T., D. Erlacher, and M. Schredl, 2013, “Testing the involvement of the prefrontal cortex in lucid dreaming: a tDCS study”, Consciousness and Cognition , 22(4): 1214–1222.
  • Stumbrys, T., D. Erlacher, M. Johnson, and M. Schredl, M., 2014, “The Phenomenology of Lucid Dreaming: An Online Survey”, American Journal of Psychology , 127(2): 191–204.
  • Symons, D., 1993, “The Stuff that Dreams Aren’t Made of: Why Wake-State and Dream-State Sensory Experiences Differ”, Cognition , 47(3): 181–217.
  • Thomas, N., 2014, “The multidimensional spectrum of imagination: Images, dreams, hallucinations, and active, imaginative perception”, Humanities 3(2): 132–184.
  • Thompson, E., 2014, Waking, dreaming, being: Self and consciousness in neuroscience, meditation, and philosophy , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 2015, “Dreamless Sleep, the Embodied Mind, and Consciousness – The Relevance of a Classical Indian Debate to Cognitive Science”, in T. Metzinger and J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • Tononi, G., 2008, “Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto”, Biological Bulletin , 215: 216–242.
  • Uslar, D. von, 1964, Der Traum als Welt: Untersuchungen zur Ontologie und Phänomenologie des Traums , Pfullingen: Neske.
  • Valberg, J.J., 2007, Dream, Death, and the Self , Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.
  • Valli, K., 2008, Threat Simulation: The Function of Dreaming? , doctoral thesis, Turku: Annales Universitatis Turkuensis.
  • van de Castle, R.L., 1994, Our Dreaming Mind , New York: Ballantine Books.
  • van Eeden, F., 1913, “A Study of Dreams”, Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research , 26: 431–461.
  • Vold, J.M., 1910/1912, Über den Traum , Vol. I and II, edited by O. Klemm, Leipzig: Johann Ambrosius Barth.
  • Voss, U., R. Holzmann, I. Tuin, and J.A. Hobson, 2009, “Lucid Dreaming: A State of Consciousness with Features of Both Waking and Non-Lucid Dreaming”, Sleep , 32(9): 1191–1200.
  • Voss, U., K. Schermelleh-Engel, J. Windt, C. Frenzel, and A. Hobson, 2013, “Measuring consciousness in dreams: the lucidity and consciousness in dreams scale”, Consciousness and Cognition , 22(1): 8–21.
  • Voss, U. and A. Hobson, 2015, “What is the state-of-the-art on lucid dreaming? – Recent advances and questions for future research”, in T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt a. MIND Group.
  • Voss, U., R. Holzmann, A. Hobson, W. Paulus, J. Koppehele-Gossel, A. Klimke, and M. Nitsche, 2014, “Induction of self awareness in dreams through frontal low current stimulation of gamma activity”, Nature Neuroscience , 17(6): 810.
  • Walker, M.P., 2009, “Sleep-Dependent Memory Processing”, in Stickgold and Walker 2009: 230–240.
  • Wamsley, E.J., 2013, “Dreaming, Waking Conscious Experience, and the Resting Brain: Report of Subjective Experience as a Tool in the Cognitive Neurosciences”, Frontiers in Psychology , 4, doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00637 [ available online ]
  • Wamsley, E.J. and R. Stickgold, 2009, “Incorporation of Waking Events into Dreams”, in Stickgold and Walker 2009: 330–336.
  • –––, 2010, “Dreaming and Offline Memory Processing”, Current Biology , 20(23): R1010–1013.
  • Wamsley, E.J., M. Tucker, J.D. Payne, J.A. Benavides, and R. Stickgold, 2010, “Dreaming of a Learning Task Is Associated with Enhanced Sleep-Dependent Memory Consolidation”, Current Biology , 20(9): 850–855.
  • Wamsley, E., C. Donjacour, T. Scammell, G. Lammers, and R. Stickgold, 2014, “Delusional confusion of dreaming and reality in narcolepsy”, Sleep , 37(2): 419–422.
  • Waxman, W., 1994, Hume’s Theory of Consciousness , Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Weygandt, W., 1893, Entstehung der Träume , Leipzig: Grübel & Sommerlatte.
  • Williams, B., 1978, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry , Middlesex: Pelican Books.
  • Windt, J.M., 2010, “The Immersive Spatiotemporal Hallucination Model of Dreaming”, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , 9: 295–316.
  • –––, 2011, “Altered Consciousness in Philosophy”, in Altering Consciousness. Multidisciplinary Perspectives, Volume 1: History, Culture, and the Humanities , E. Cardeña and M. Winkelman (eds.), Santa Barbera, Denver & Oxford: Praeger, pp. 229–254.
  • –––, 2013, “Reporting Dream Experience: Why (Not) to Be Skeptical about Dream Reports”, Frontiers in Human Neuroscience , 7, doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00708 [ available online ]
  • –––, 2015a, Dreaming: A Conceptual Framework for Philosophy of Mind and Empirical Research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • –––, 2015b, “Just in time – dreamless sleep experience as pure subjective temporality”, in T. Metzinger & J.M. Windt (eds.), Open MIND , Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.
  • –––, 2018, “Predictive brains, dreaming selves, sleeping bodies: how the analysis of dream movement can inform a theory of self-and world-simulation in dreams”, Synthese , 195(6): 2577–2625.
  • Windt, J.M. and T. Metzinger, 2007, “The Philosophy of Dreaming and Self-Consciousness: What Happens to the Experiential Subject during the Dream State?”, in Barrett and McNamara 2007c: 193–248.
  • Windt, J.M. and V. Noreika, 2011, “How to Integrate Dreaming into a General Theory of Consciousness—A Critical Review of Existing Positions and Suggestions for Future Research”, Consciousness and Cognition , 20(4): 1091–1107.
  • Windt, J.M., and U. Voss, 2018, “Spontaneous thought, insight, and control in lucid dreams”, in The Oxford Handbook of Spontaneous Thought: Mind-Wandering, Creativity, and Dreaming , Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 385–410.
  • Windt, J.M., T. Nielsen, and E. Thompson, 2016, “Does consciousness disappear in dreamless sleep?”, Trends in cognitive sciences , 20(12): 871–882.
  • Wittgenstein, L., 1953, Philosophical Investigations , G.E.M. Anscombe (ed.), Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 1967, Zettel , G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright (eds.), Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Wundt, W.M., 1896, Grundriss der Psychologie , Leipzig: Engelman; page reference is to the excerpt translated by C.H. Judd, reprinted in R.L. Woods and H.B. Greenhouse (eds.), The New World of Dreams , New York: Macmilllan (1974), pp. 179–180.
  • Zeidman, P., and E. Maguire, 2016, “Anterior hippocampus: the anatomy of perception, imagination and episodic memory”, Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 17(3): 173.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Philosophy of Dreaming , entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy .
  • Dreams , PhilPapers collection.
  • Dreams and Skepticism , PhilPapers collection.

belief | Berkeley, George | delusion | Descartes, René: epistemology | imagination | Locke, John | perception: the problem of | personal identity | personal identity: and ethics | Plato: on knowledge in the Theaetetus | sense data | skepticism | skepticism: and content externalism

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Regina Fabry and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and constructive criticism on an earlier version of this manuscript. And as always, I am greatly indebted to Stefan Pitz for his support.

Copyright © 2019 by Jennifer M. Windt < jennifer . windt @ monash . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Dreams vs. Reality: “Fences” and “O’ Pioneer” Essay

  • To find inspiration for your paper and overcome writer’s block
  • As a source of information (ensure proper referencing)
  • As a template for you assignment

Themes of Dream Vs Reality

The impact of the dreams vs reality, works cited.

The novels, Fences by August Wilson, and O’ Pioneer by Willa Cather describe the lifestyle of a common American citizen. August Wilson focuses on the struggles of the African Americans to fit in a society controlled by racism. The main characters like Troy do not know whether to fulfilling their dreams and ambitions or confront the real life, which faces them each day.

On the other hand, Willa Cather mainly focuses on the daily experiences of people especially in property ownership, neighborliness, life hardships, and individual relationships thus highlighting the theme of realism. Everybody in the world, at least, has an aspiration or dream but to convert it into pragmatism always proves a hard task.

Therefore, in the novel, the Fences, Troy, and Rose struggle to balance their lives as a reality because of their individual ambitions while in O’Pioneer, Alexander fights to fulfill her dreams as a reality.

In Act one, scene one, of Fences, Troy highlights the subject of hallucination, unreality, and illusions when he describes how he met with death and the devil.

Although his wife, Rose, and friend, Bono, disapprove his tale, he insists on being immortal, which is unreal. The hallucination about death leads to a conflict between Troy and his wife, but eventually the tussle draws the theme of reality. Furthermore, Troy asserts that he cheated death, but Rose refutes his claims when she says, “Troy lying” (Wilson Act I scene I).

Nevertheless, Troy’s hallucination about death arose when he suffered pneumonia during his childhood. When his wife, Rose, reminds him about the pneumonia, Troy insists on escaping death.

To brush off the tale, Rose says, “Troy, don’t nobody wanna be hearing all that stuff” (Wilson Act I scene I), which means she is not only upset, but also tired of the unrealistic tale. Therefore, Troy thinks he physically fought with death proving his self- ambition as a dreamer and a believer.

In reality can a person fight, cheat or wrestle with death? Troy’s wife calls him to wake up, stop dreaming, and face the reality of life. On the other hand, Rose’s dream is to become rich, which pushes her to invest her money in unscrupulous means like playing numbers. Eventually, she looses her money, which signals the start of her poverty.

Troy is against her game when he says, “You ain’t doing nothing but throwing your money away”(Wilson Act I scene III), which means she should invest her money in real business and not dream of making quick money. Therefore, Rose and Troy live a miserable life because they focus on their dreams forgetting about the reality of life and the changing world.

In the second instance, Troy as a black American, believes education is the only way to achieve a good life. Initially, Troy’s dream was to become a baseball player, but the aspect of racism denied him the chance to explore his skills. On the contrary, his son, Cory, will do anything to join professional football; nevertheless, Troy is against it, which degenerates to a conflict between the two.

According to Troy, historically, no black men played professional football; thus, his aim is to force his children to follow his footsteps, even though, none of his dreams succeeded. A conflict ensues between the two drifting them apart.

Cory says, “Papa was like a shadow that followed you everywhere” (Wilson Act II scene V), which means that Troy’s aspiration is to see his children live his dream. The ambition to pass his historical life to his children seems futile because of the dynamic world.

Among Troy’s philosophies are “You gotta take the crookeds with the straights” (Wilson Act II scene V), which not only builds tension between him and his children, but also leads to frequent disagreements. Similarly, Troy is against supporting his son’s desire to venture into a music career because that is not among his dreams.

According to Troy, racism, discrimination, and inequality killed his dreams and he believes the same aspects will happen to his children; regrettably, he forgets that his children are living in different times. In addition, Troy’s unfulfilled dreams pushed him to be a wicked, selfish, and tyrannizing in his family. He resorts to passing decision without consultation especially to his family members, which leaves him both angry and frustrated.

Finally, Troy’s dream not only kills his future, but also that of his children. On the other hand, in the book, O’pionee r, Willa Cather, the author, focuses on the theme of reality. Alexandra’s aim is to be a successful, rich, and famous farmer, which she not only explores, but also achieves. Alexandra achieves her dream because she owns management skills.

The author highlights the theme of reality by describing the daily lives of the characters. Relationships, land ownership, conflicts, and hard economic times are among the life experiences Cather focuses on in her work.

The aforementioned themes describe the human lives encompassing their social, economic, cultural, and personal context. Each of Troy’s family members has a dream, but the diverse ambitions lead to family conflicts. The aim of most people is to live a good life and own vast property; nevertheless, a failure in any of the aforementioned pursuits leads to frustration.

The human nature pushes people to venture into unreal world, as it is the case with Troy. Besides “wrestling with death”, his other dream is to control and mould his children in his own ways, but he fails (Wilson Act I scene I).

Sometimes the human condition is dynamic depending on the situation at hand. Socially, the personal dreams of the characters affect their social and economic lives. For instance, Alexandra rarely commits herself into any relationship; nevertheless, when loneliness (reality) sets in, she decides to marry.

Economically, property ownership is a crucial element the human nature. According to John, “The mark of man upon the land becomes indistinguishable from the marks of nature’s own processes” (Cather 14), which means land is a sensitive issue to people and it may either build or destroy an individual.

In summary, according to August and Cather, every human being has dreams but it takes an individual initiative to turn the dream into reality. Although Troy and Rose dream of living better lives, they use retrogressive means to pursue their dreams, and they fail terribly. In addition, people should strive to live in present and not base their lives on their past as it is with Troy.

Sadly, some dreams like human immortality are unrealistic and people should focus on realism, as it is the case with Alexandra. Finally, each person’s ambitions affect his or her social, economic, political, and personal decisions, as it is the case with Alexandra, Rose, and Troy as outlined in this paper.

Cather, Willa. O’pioneer. New York: Vintage Books, 1992.

Wilson, August. Fences. New York: Plume, 1986.

  • The Great Gatsby Reflection Paper
  • Themes in A Farewell to Arms
  • American Dream in Cather's "Paul's Case" and Faulkner's "Barn Burning"
  • Depression, Hallucination, and Suicide: Mental Cases
  • The Significance of Fences
  • How Decisions Affect Choices in the "Life Is a Smorgasbord"
  • Mrs. Dutta writes a letter
  • Walt Whitman: Life of an American Poet
  • “Joyas Voladoras” by Brian Doyle. Summary and Symbolism Analysis
  • Without Conscience: The Disturbing World of the Psychopaths among Us
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2018, June 4). Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer". https://ivypanda.com/essays/dreams-vs-reality/

"Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer"." IvyPanda , 4 June 2018, ivypanda.com/essays/dreams-vs-reality/.

IvyPanda . (2018) 'Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer"'. 4 June.

IvyPanda . 2018. "Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer"." June 4, 2018. https://ivypanda.com/essays/dreams-vs-reality/.

1. IvyPanda . "Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer"." June 4, 2018. https://ivypanda.com/essays/dreams-vs-reality/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer"." June 4, 2018. https://ivypanda.com/essays/dreams-vs-reality/.

IvyPanda uses cookies and similar technologies to enhance your experience, enabling functionalities such as:

  • Basic site functions
  • Ensuring secure, safe transactions
  • Secure account login
  • Remembering account, browser, and regional preferences
  • Remembering privacy and security settings
  • Analyzing site traffic and usage
  • Personalized search, content, and recommendations
  • Displaying relevant, targeted ads on and off IvyPanda

Please refer to IvyPanda's Cookies Policy and Privacy Policy for detailed information.

Certain technologies we use are essential for critical functions such as security and site integrity, account authentication, security and privacy preferences, internal site usage and maintenance data, and ensuring the site operates correctly for browsing and transactions.

Cookies and similar technologies are used to enhance your experience by:

  • Remembering general and regional preferences
  • Personalizing content, search, recommendations, and offers

Some functions, such as personalized recommendations, account preferences, or localization, may not work correctly without these technologies. For more details, please refer to IvyPanda's Cookies Policy .

To enable personalized advertising (such as interest-based ads), we may share your data with our marketing and advertising partners using cookies and other technologies. These partners may have their own information collected about you. Turning off the personalized advertising setting won't stop you from seeing IvyPanda ads, but it may make the ads you see less relevant or more repetitive.

Personalized advertising may be considered a "sale" or "sharing" of the information under California and other state privacy laws, and you may have the right to opt out. Turning off personalized advertising allows you to exercise your right to opt out. Learn more in IvyPanda's Cookies Policy and Privacy Policy .

Home — Essay Samples — Literature — The Great Gatsby — Gatsby’s Dream Vs Reality

test_template

Gatsby’s Dream Vs Reality

  • Categories: American Culture Literature Review The Great Gatsby

About this sample

close

Words: 515 |

Published: Mar 16, 2024

Words: 515 | Page: 1 | 3 min read

Table of contents

Gatsby's dream, the illusion of wealth and success, the elusiveness of love and happiness.

Image of Dr. Charlotte Jacobson

Cite this Essay

To export a reference to this article please select a referencing style below:

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Prof Ernest (PhD)

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Arts & Culture Literature

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

6 pages / 2596 words

2 pages / 766 words

3 pages / 1235 words

3 pages / 1264 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on The Great Gatsby

In F. Scott Fitzgerald's iconic novel, "The Great Gatsby," the setting of West Egg plays a crucial role in shaping the characters and their interactions. This essay will focus on the significance of West Egg in the context of [...]

F. Scott Fitzgerald's classic novel 'The Great Gatsby' is renowned for its rich symbolism, and one of its most iconic symbols is the green light. Positioned at the end of Daisy Buchanan's dock, the green light carries profound [...]

Written by F. Scott Fitzgerald and published in 1925, "The Great Gatsby" is widely regarded as a masterpiece in Fitzgerald's body of work. It has become a classic in American fiction and has been read and reread by countless [...]

Tom Wilson's death in F. Scott Fitzgerald's novel "The Great Gatsby" is a critical event that sheds light on the themes of social class, wealth, and morality in the Jazz Age. In today's world, the exploration of these themes [...]

In F. Scott Fitzgerald's novel "The Great Gatsby," symbolism plays a crucial role in conveying deeper meanings and themes throughout the story. From the iconic green light at the end of Daisy's dock to the symbolic use of colors [...]

Relationships can change your life, they can make or break you. F. Scott Fitzgerald’s The Great Gatsby represents instability of love and desire. Love, desire, rumours and the truth can be difficult for one to handle. Everyone [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

dreams vs reality essay

24/7 writing help on your phone

To install StudyMoose App tap and then “Add to Home Screen”

Dreams vs. Reality

Save to my list

Remove from my list

Sweet V

Dreams and Reality

Dreams vs. Reality. (2016, Nov 08). Retrieved from https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay

"Dreams vs. Reality." StudyMoose , 8 Nov 2016, https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay

StudyMoose. (2016). Dreams vs. Reality . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay [Accessed: 13 Sep. 2024]

"Dreams vs. Reality." StudyMoose, Nov 08, 2016. Accessed September 13, 2024. https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay

"Dreams vs. Reality," StudyMoose , 08-Nov-2016. [Online]. Available: https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay. [Accessed: 13-Sep-2024]

StudyMoose. (2016). Dreams vs. Reality . [Online]. Available at: https://studymoose.com/dreams-vs-reality-essay [Accessed: 13-Sep-2024]

  • Childhood dreams and reality Pages: 2 (405 words)
  • Dreams to Reality: A Biomedical Scientist's Journey Pages: 1 (290 words)
  • From Dream to Reality: The Journey of Turning Dreams into Achievements Pages: 3 (748 words)
  • The Secret Life of Walter Mitty Movie Review: Theme Of Contrast Between Dreams And Reality Pages: 4 (1102 words)
  • My Dreams For The Future Pages: 1 (269 words)
  • The Life-Long Journey towards Achieving Goals and Dreams Pages: 5 (1475 words)
  • Isolation's Delusions in Winter Dreams & A Wagner Matinee Pages: 7 (1838 words)
  • Empowering Dreams: A Journey from Struggle to Success Pages: 9 (2601 words)
  • Dreams in Crime & Punishment Pages: 5 (1346 words)
  • Dreams Can Be Deferred: A Raisin In The Sun By Lorraine Hansberry Pages: 9 (2614 words)

Dreams vs. Reality essay

👋 Hi! I’m your smart assistant Amy!

Don’t know where to start? Type your requirements and I’ll connect you to an academic expert within 3 minutes.

The LitCharts.com logo.

  • Ask LitCharts AI
  • Discussion Question Generator
  • Essay Prompt Generator
  • Quiz Question Generator

Guides

  • Literature Guides
  • Poetry Guides
  • Shakespeare Translations
  • Literary Terms

Life is a Dream

Pedro calderón de la barca.

dreams vs reality essay

Ask LitCharts AI: The answer to your questions

Theme Analysis

Fate vs. Free Will Theme Icon

Pedro Calderón de la Barca’s Life is a Dream tells the story of Basilio , King of Poland, who imprisons his son, Segismundo , after a prophecy claims it is the young prince’s destiny to kill his father and divide his country. Years pass, and Basilio begins to doubt his decision to imprison Segismundo and deny the people their rightful prince. He decides to free his son, but just in case Segismundo really is a monster who will only bring ruin to his country and people, Basilio tricks Segismundo into believing he is dreaming so that, if need be, he can easily be placed back in prison without knowing his true identity. After being drugged with opium, poppy, and henbane, Segismundo, in a slumber resembling death, is brought from his prison cell to the palace in Warsaw and placed in his father’s luxurious bed. When he wakes, Segismundo indeed finds himself part of an unbelievable world that surely must be some sort of dream. Through the blending of dreams and reality in Life is a Dream , Calderón effectively argues that like dreams, life itself is an illusion.

Throughout much of Calderón’s play, reality turns out to be something other than what it seems, which suggests that reality itself is merely perception. When Rosaura , one of the play’s main characters, is first introduced, she is dressed as a man, and when she next appears, Rosaura is disguised as a lady-in-waiting at court. In reality, Rosaura is really Clotaldo ’s secret daughter and Astolfo ’s jilted lover, but she appears to be something else entirely. After Rosaura, disguised as a man, is apprehended by Clotaldo for unwittingly wandering into Segismundo’s prison cell, Clotaldo is convinced that Rosaura is his long-lost son. Rosaura carries Clotaldo’s sword , which he had left, many years before, to be given to his unborn son. In reality, Clotaldo has a daughter, not a son, but his perception is that Rosaura is his son. Furthermore, Astolfo, the Duke of Muscovy and Basilio’s nephew, believes that his uncle is without children and that he is next in line for the throne. In reality, Basilio’s secret son, Segismundo, is the rightful heir, but Astolfo nevertheless believes that he will be king, which again implies that reality is only a matter of perception.

When Segismundo wakes up as the Prince of Poland after spending his whole life in prison, his new existence is completely unbelievable. Even though he doesn’t quite believe it, this new perception is still Segismundo’s reality. In short, that which is real feels like a dream, just as that which is false often seems to be real. “To say I’m dreaming is mistaken,” Segismundo cries when he wakes in a lavish bed surrounded by servants, “I know very well I’m awake.” Segismundo is used to prison and isolation, not luxury and indulgence, and he is dubious from the beginning, but he still accepts his dreamlike new reality. As the Prince of Poland, Segismundo is overwhelmed and unsure of himself. “As for me,” he says to his servants, “all of this is making me angry. / Nothing seems right to me.” However, when Basilio attempts to convince Segismundo that his experience as the prince was all just a dream, Segismundo refuses to believe him. “I’m not dreaming,” Segismundo claims, “because I feel and believe / that which I was and that which I am.” Segismundo makes it clear here that humans have little choice but to accept perception as reality—even when that reality feels like a dream.

Once Segismundo wakes up back in his prison cell, he decides that it doesn’t matter if his experience was all a dream or not. “Living is merely dreaming,” he claims. Through Segismundo’s experiences, Calderón suggests that life is only “an illusion, / a shadow, a fiction,” and one can never be fully certain that their perception is in fact reality.

Dreams vs. Reality ThemeTracker

Life is a Dream PDF

Dreams vs. Reality Quotes in Life is a Dream

By Clorilene my wife I had an unlucky son, during whose gestation the heavens exhausted their miracles even before he emerged into the lovely light from the living grave of the womb (because birth and death are similar). Infinite times his mother, amid the visions and delirium of dreams, saw her entrails being burst by a bold monster in human shape; dyed in her blood, he was killing her, born to be the human viper of the age.

Fate vs. Free Will Theme Icon

I’m not dreaming, because I feel and believe that which I was and that which I am. And, even though you regret it now, there’s not much you can do about it: I know who I am, and even if you sigh and grieve, you won’t be able to undo the fact that I was born heir to this crown; and if you saw me formerly a prisoner of my shackles, it was because I didn’t know who I was; but now I have been informed as to who I am, and I know that I’m a hybrid of man and beast.

dreams vs reality essay

Since we had been speaking about that eagle, when you slept you dreamt of empire, but even in dreams it would have been proper at that time to honor the man who raised you with such great pains, Segismundo, because even in dreams good deeds are never wasted.

Morality, Honor, and Vengeance  Theme Icon

It’s true, then: let me restrain my fierce nature, my fury, my ambition, in case I ever dream again. And I will , since we exist in such a peculiar world that living is merely dreaming; and the experience teaches me that the man who lives dreams his reality until he awakes.

What is life? A frenzy. What is life? An illusion, a shadow, a fiction, and our greatest good is but small; for, all of life is a dream, and even dreams are dreams.

I know you by now, I know you by now, and I know that you do the same thing to everyone who falls asleep. For me there is no more pretense, because, now undeceived, I know perfectly well that LIFE IS A DREAM.

Rise, rise, father, from the ground; for you must be the North Star and guide to whom I entrust my success; for 1 now know that I owe my upbringing to your great loyalty. Come and embrace me.

What are you saying?

That I’m dreaming, and that I wish to do good, because good deeds aren’t wasted, even in dreams

Fortune, let me go and reign! Don’t awaken me if I’m asleep, and, if this is reality, don’t put me to sleep. But, whether it’s reality or a dream, to do good is what matters; if it should be reality, just because it is good; if not, for the sake of winning friends for the time when we awaken.

Why are you surprised? Why are you astonished, when my teacher was a dream, and in my anxiety I’m afraid I may wake up again and find myself once more in my locked cell? And even if that doesn’t happen, merely dreaming it might is enough: for in that way I came to know that all of human happiness passes by in the end like a dream, and I wish today to enjoy mine for as long as it lasts, asking pardon for our faults, since it so befits noble hearts to pardon them!

The LitCharts.com logo.

  • Quizzes, saving guides, requests, plus so much more.

cookie

We use cookies to give you the best experience possible.

By continuing we’ll assume you are on board with our cookie policy

American Dream vs. Reality

The american dream.

The American Dream is a desire to reach personal goals and satisfy specific accomplishments that lead to a meaningful and successful life. In the search for a perfect American dream, much can be lost; this notion is reflected in Death of a Salesman, written by Arthur Miller, and The Great Gatsby, written by F. Scott Fitzgerald. The American Dream represented in each text is personal and unique to different individuals. These literary works describe the lengths that some persons can go to with the aim of achieving the stereotypical life of a wealthy, powerful and successful American that is usually considered the American Dream.

Get a Free Price Quote

First-Timer? Join!

Loman and Gatsby are heroes who are dominated by the American Dream, which destroyed them. Willy Loman wants to be respected and regarded as a successful salesman; he wants his two sons to achieve financial freedom and success. Similarly, Jay Gatsby’s American Dream involves financial success, but he only wants the money to impress Daisy and win her love. Both men struggle with attempts to fulfill their American Dreams; yet, ultimately, both stories fail to meet the real life and end with deaths. Loman is not a successful salesman, and Gatsby’s love for Daisy is idealistic as he fails to accept the reality of her life. These two men are connected by the grandness of their dreams, but they are crushed by the reality of their lives as both could neither accept this reality, nor achieve the American Dream.

In The Great Gatsby, Gatsby believes that he has lost Daisy’s love because he does not have wealth or an implemented dream of life; Daisy gets married to Tom who has both. His dream puts him on a road where he spends all of his energy on recreating his past as it was the happiest time of his life. Therefore, Gatsby desires to achieve his dream as all he has to do is to become very wealthy. He focuses his entire attention on becoming a man idealized by his American Dream. Gatsby reinvents himself through creation of a new identity and following actions of any lengths in order to earn money. The hero does these things with the aim of winning Daisy; however, Daisy represents nothing more to Gatsby than the final acquisition necessary in order to implement his dream.

Exclusive savings! Save 25% on your ORDER

15% OFF your FIRST ORDER + 10% OFF every order by receiving 300 words/page instead of 275 words/page

For this reason, Gatsby becomes a man of substance by illegal bootlegging. He does not speak about his business and when Nick Carraway asks, “I thought you inherited your money.” Gatsby responds, “That’s my affair” (Fitzgerald 90). Gatsby is very secretive about how he made his money as he does not want to admit that he gained money by breaking the law. Furthermore, he wants to be a perfect man in the eyes of Daisy. In addition, his American Dream does not include any illegal things as he plans an ideal life.

He expected Daisy to come and see that he has worked all his life in order to get a large amount of money and gain her attention. Gatsby thinks, “He half expected her to wander into one of his parties, some night, but she never did” (Fitzgerald 79). Moreover, Gatsby believes that if Daisy wanders in one night she will finally see his worth, extravagant home and huge parties. He thinks that after seeing his wealth, she will leave Tom, and come back to him again. It was his main dream, but as Daisy never attends one of his parties, Nick arranges for Gatsby and Daisy to meet privately. The main hero of the book believes that such meeting can change all his life as from Nick’s house she will see his own marvelous house. The house he has built for her. He tells Nick, “My house looks well, doesn’t it? See how the whole front of it catches the light.” (Fitzgerald 89). Gatsby is pleased and knows that Daisy will love him and see his beautiful home. Gatsby uses wealth in order to accomplish his American Dream of winning Daisy. However, his perspective is not based on reality of the world surrounding him as real life is not ideal and cannot be ideal. No matter how hard an individual strives for perfection, there is no ideally perfect life. Gatsby wants too much from his life and instead of continuing it he tries to repeat the past.

8 Reasons

Don't waste time - get the best essay in the world!

8 Reasons to choose us:

  • 01. Only original papers
  • 02. Any difficulty level
  • 03. 300 words per page
  • 04. BA, MA, and Ph.D writers
  • 05. Generous discounts
  • 06. On-time delivery
  • 07. Direct communication with an assigned writer
  • 08. VIP services

Daisy is a central figure of his Dream. The protagonist cannot believe that she once left him and ruined his life. Therefore, he wants to return her and recreate his idealized world. Gatsby claims that Daisy “only married you (Tom) because I was poor and she was tired of waiting for me. It was terrible mistake, but in her heart she never loved anyone except me” (Fitzgerald 130). These words prove Gatsby’s belief about Daisy and her devotion to him. Daisy admits her love to Gatsby; however, she is not capable of meeting his expectations.

Gatsby is unrealistic when he says, “Daisy it’s all over now. Just tell him the truth-that you never loved him – and it’s all wiped out for ever” (Fitzgerald 134). This quote shows that for Gatsby it is more important to prove that Daisy has never loved Tom than gain her entire love. In Gatsby’s mind, once Daisy admits to never having loved Tom, then he and Daisy can have the perfect, loving relationship. Daisy’s response sums up the reality of the situation, “Oh, you want too much” (Fitzgerald 134) Gatsby has this grand vision of an ideal love and he expects Daisy to fit his vision of true love.

Furthermore, Gatsby expects Daisy to tell Tom that she never loved him. However, her words, “You ask too much of me… I did love him once – but I loved you too” (Fitzgerald 130) do not bring him to reality. Gatsby cannot accept this reality and is devastated. Moreover, he cannot believe that his dream can be ruined despite his tremendous efforts. The real life does not fit his plan; therefore, he cannot and does not want to accept it. In his mind, he and Daisy have a pure love and it cannot be tainted by love to Tom. Gatsby’s American Dream ends with his death; his desire for Daisy’s love is unattainable and unrealistic because he thinks that he can obtain happiness through power and wealth. In addition, his dream is unattainable as he is in love with a memory and cannot realize that Daisy is not the same as she was in the past.

In Death of a Salesman, Loman’s American Dream is rooted in the thought that he should be financially successful and that his legacy of financial freedom will be continued by his sons, especially by Biff. However, despite great desires, this dream does not meet the reality. To the main character of the play, the American Dream is the ability to become rich by charisma as Willy believes that not hard work and innovation, but personality is the key to a successful life. For this reason, he says to his sons, “It’s not what you say; it’s how you say it-because personality always wins the day” (Miller 65). This quote shows his philosophy that success is measured by how many friends a person has.

Special offers!

VIP Services package with 20% discount -

Therefore, Loman thinks that being a salesman is the best and most honorable occupation for a man and says, “I realized that selling was the greatest career a man could want… be remembered and loved and helped by so many different people” (Miller 81). Loman wants to be a successful salesman because in such a way he will be loved and respected by others. The play describes the differences between reality of family’s lives and their dreams.

Death of a Salesman shows the loss of identity and a person’s inability to accept changes of identity and society. Loman cannot accept the fact that he is considered a mediocre salesman. For this reason, he strives to achieve his version of the American Dream even if he is to deny reality for achieving it. Therefore, instead of confirming that he is not a successful person, Loman retreats into the past and relives memories in which he is considered a successful individual. Moreover, he thinks that he can obtain a more lucrative sales position in NYC with the help of his influence. Loman assumes that whom a person knows is more important than what a person knows. Therefore, he tells his boss Howard, “Your father came to me the day you were born and asked me what I thought of the name Howard” (Miller 80). Loman honestly believes that he will get the job in NYC because of his connection with Howard’s father more than thirty years ago, but the reality is that Howard fires him leaving him without success or financial support. 

Loman thinks because his son, Biff, is a successful football player in high school, he can use those connections to begin a successful career. However, the reality is that Biff has had numerous jobs over the last fifteen years and Loman does not accept that his son cannot be financially independent. He tells Biff, “Because you got a greatness in you, Biff, remember that. You got all kinds of greatness” (Miller 67). This greatness is a part of his American Dreams. Therefore, it is important for him to encourage his sons. Moreover, Loman has faith in both of his sons and believes that they can, “Lick the world! You guys together could absolutely lick the civilized world…. I see great things for you kids, I think your troubles are over. But remember, start big and you’ll end big” (Miller 64). These words show that Loman believes there is nothing his children cannot accomplish. However, Loman’s beliefs do not match his reality, as neither Loman nor his sons are successful.

Willy Loman’s grand dream of being a successful salesman and achieving financially freedom for him and his children is not based on reality. In his head, Loman thinks he is a wonderful salesman but reality proves the opposite things. After being fired, Loman says, “No, but it’s a business, kid, and everybody’s gotta pull his own weight” (Miller 80). The reality is that Loman losing his job is strictly a business decision, because Loman is not a good salesman.

Become our VIP clients and enjoy these exclusive BENEFITS:

  • 01 Paper delivery before the deadline
  • 02 Free 1-page draft to each order
  • 03 Extended revision period
  • 04 Free plagiarism check
  • 05 TOP 10 writers assigned to each order
  • 06 Every order proofread by a TOP editor
  • 07 VIP Support Service
  • 08 SMS notification of the order status

VIP clients

The author shows that Loman is so busy of reaching success in life that he has forgotten about the reality. Despite substantial hopes for his sons, they have not achieved success. Loman realizes this when Howard asks, “Where are your sons? Why don’t your sons give you a hand” (Miller 83)? It is the first time when he realizes that he fails to implement his American Dream. However, Loman cannot accept this. Even when Biff tells Willy, “You phony little fake” (Miller 120), he continues to believe he and his sons can achieve success and the American Dream. Willy still believes that it is the Loman family that will achieve success because they are well liked by others and have great personalities.

The problem of Loman is that the society is constantly shattering his dreams. He maintains a misguided attitude towards success. The lack of understanding and suppression of life and reality surrounding him has led to this belief. Loman even refuses to accept the reality that his son was a common man with a common job. He cannot understand Biff’s words, “Pop! I’m a dime a dozen, and so are you… I am not a leader of men, Willy, and neither are you” (Miller 132). Loman’s major problem is that he cannot live with the reality that he and his sons are failures and that his grand dream is unattainable. “After all the highways, and the trains, and the appointments, and the years, you end up worth more dead than alive” (Miller 98). This quote shows that Loman finally realizes that the reality is opposite to his unattainable American Dream.

Thus, Gatsby and Loman died failing to achieve their ambitious American Dreams. While Gatsby’s goal is to use wealth in order to impress and win Daisy’s love, Loman’s ambition is to be loved, to be respected, to be a successful salesman, and to leave a lasting legacy. Death of Loman shows how a person can stop at nothing before achieving the American Dream, despite the substantial costs. Both men are blinded by their visions of what could be possible; Loman’s and Gatsby’s dreams,’ however, do not meet the real world. Gatsby and Loman only see the world around them through their unique perspectives, yet neither accepts the reality that surrounds them. Failure is too heavy of a burden for either man to deal with in life. Therefore, Gatsby’s murder and Loman’s suicide is the only escape for them both. There is one true thing about the American Dream according to which everyone desires to gain something in life, and everyone desires to get it. However, some dreams are not realistic and cannot be accomplished.

Try Your Luck! Let's Play to Win a Discount!

Not too bad but you can do better Try tomorrow again

Congratulations! GET YOUR 15% DISCOUNT USE CODE: the code is valid for 24 hours

do-you-like-this-sample-make-an-order-and-get-the-same

READY to ORDER?

Save Time And Let Professionals Work On Your Academic Papers

  • Entertainment
  • Environment
  • Information Science and Technology
  • Social Issues

Home Essay Samples Life Goals

Explaining Why Dreams and Goals Are Valuable

Table of contents, fueling aspirations and cultivating potential, guiding lights in the journey of life, building resilience and overcoming challenges, catalysts for societal progress and innovation, conclusion: the heartbeat of human ambition.

  • Dweck, C. S. (2006). Mindset: The new psychology of success. Random House Incorporated.
  • Latham, G. P., & Locke, E. A. (2007). New developments in and directions for goal-setting research. European Psychologist , 12(4), 290-300.

*minimum deadline

Cite this Essay

To export a reference to this article please select a referencing style below

writer logo

  • Watching TV
  • Healthy Lifestyle

Related Essays

Need writing help?

You can always rely on us no matter what type of paper you need

*No hidden charges

100% Unique Essays

Absolutely Confidential

Money Back Guarantee

By clicking “Send Essay”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement. We will occasionally send you account related emails

You can also get a UNIQUE essay on this or any other topic

Thank you! We’ll contact you as soon as possible.

  • JEREMY L 5* Google Verified Reviews Extremely talented and very easy to work with. Kabir is great at working through direction and is committed to getting the result we were looking for. Highly recommend!
  • Phone: (626)-246-5192
  • Studio: (424)-253-0429
  • [email protected]
  • kabirsvoice

Kabirsvoice

Reality Vs Dreams Spoken Word

Man with lights in puddle

Never stop dreaming. We hear it all the time- Never stop dreaming. But, what does that really mean? Many would argue that life is like a dream. Is life a dream? Or is life just reality? Reality vs Dreams is a spoken word poem I created when I found myself at my own crossroads with these types of questions.

When I was younger I didn’t enjoy my reality. My reality was abusive, crime ridden and full of fear and loneliness. However, in my solitude, it was my dreams that helped me through the pain. My dreams were my positive thoughts. My dreams were my true escapes. The dreams vs reality philosophy is one that I reflect on often in the darkest moments of my life. I find myself either wanting to escape my reality or pleading for a bigger dream.

Man with lights in puddle

When I reflect on my voice over career I never imagined I would be living my reality as a full time professional voice actor. I dreamt about it all the time, but to actually live it is a whole different experience. But, it was my dreams that keep me going. It was my desire and willingness to accomplish my goals that kept my dream alive. My dream is now my reality. So, is life a dream?

Never stop dreaming. I can’t help but abide by this rule now. Everyday is a new day to dream and live a life full of all possibilities. We each possess the ability to dream and accomplish our most far out goals and endeavors. It just requires a bit of courage. Dreaming reality into existence is nothing but a belief in oneself and a few good years of hard work away.

Is life a dream? I am too inexperienced to fully realize that as of now. But, I can’t help but reflect on the old nursery rhyme we all know so well….

“Row, Row, Row your boat gently down the stream

Merrily, merrily, merrily, merrily- life is but a dream .”

Make sure to subscribe to my YouTube Page Here .

Checkout my YouTube Playlist  Here !

Tap “Voice Actor” then “Video Demos” in the navigation bar above to watch more demos similar to Reality vs Dreams – Is Life a Dream? – Never Stop Dreaming  from professional actor Kabir Singh.

Listen To Kabir’s Work

Google Verified Reviews

Audition with Me

Facebook

  • Email: [email protected]
  • Phone: 1-626-246-5192
  • Skype: kabirsvoice
  • Source Connect: kabirsvoice
  • Studio: 424-253-0429
  • Location: Los Angeles, CA

Kabir Singh is a professional male voice over artist with more than 15 years of experience delivering voice over services worldwide. Kabir Singh has provided voiceover services for commercial voice overs for radio and tv as well as eLearning and corporate clients . Other specialties include male narration voice overs and College/University inspirational voiceovers. Kabir is a raw poet and spoken word artist and he uses his urban and multicultural sound to connect with people of all genders, races, cultures and religions.

“Kabirsvoice is authentic. One of the best male voice actors for hire”

Football voice over for the NFL

Logo

Paragraph on Dream And Reality

Students are often asked to write a paragraph on Dream And Reality in their schools. And if you’re also looking for the same, we have created 100-word, 200-word, and 250-word paragraphs on the topic.

Let’s take a look…

Paragraph on Dream And Reality in 100 Words

Dreams and reality are different but both are important. Dreams are like beautiful stories we see while sleeping. We can fly, meet fairies, or talk to animals in dreams. Reality is what happens when we are awake. It’s going to school, playing, eating, and spending time with family. Dreams make us happy and give us cool ideas. Reality helps us learn and grow. It’s fun to dream about magical things, but it’s also important to enjoy and learn from our real life. Both dreams and reality make our lives interesting and full of learning.

Paragraph on Dream And Reality in 200 Words

Dreams and reality are two different things that are part of our lives. Dreams are like movies that play in our heads when we sleep. We can dream about anything, like flying in the sky, talking animals, or being a superhero. These dreams can be fun and exciting, but they are not real. When we wake up, we realize that it was just a dream. On the other hand, reality is everything that is happening around us when we are awake. In reality, we can’t fly in the sky or talk to animals, but we can play, learn, and spend time with our friends and family. While dreams can be interesting, it’s important to remember that they are not real and can’t replace our reality. Reality is where we live, learn, and grow. So, it’s good to enjoy our dreams but we should also focus on our reality because that’s where we can make things happen and achieve our goals. Dreams can give us ideas, but it’s in reality where we can work hard and make those ideas come true.

Paragraph on Dream And Reality in 250 Words

Dreams and reality are two different yet connected things. Dreams are thoughts, images, or feelings that occur in our minds when we sleep, while reality is what we experience when we are awake. Dreams can be full of wonder, mystery, and sometimes fear, taking us on adventures that our waking life can’t. For instance, in dreams, you might fly like a bird or talk to a lion, which isn’t possible in real life. On the other hand, reality is based on facts and truth. It is the world around us, the things we can touch, see, and feel. It includes our daily routines, such as going to school, playing games, or eating dinner with our family.

Yet, dreams and reality are linked. Sometimes, our dreams are inspired by our reality. If you read a book about space, you might dream about being an astronaut. Additionally, dreams can influence our reality. If you dream about becoming a doctor, it might encourage you to study hard and pursue medicine when you grow up. Dreams serve as a playground for our imagination and can provide a source of motivation and direction in our real lives. So, while dreams and reality may seem different, they both play significant roles in our lives. They shape our experiences, decisions, and the way we perceive the world around us.

Explore other popular paragraph topics:

Apart from these, you can look at all the essays by  clicking here .

Happy studying!

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Pardon Our Interruption

As you were browsing something about your browser made us think you were a bot. There are a few reasons this might happen:

  • You've disabled JavaScript in your web browser.
  • You're a power user moving through this website with super-human speed.
  • You've disabled cookies in your web browser.
  • A third-party browser plugin, such as Ghostery or NoScript, is preventing JavaScript from running. Additional information is available in this support article .

To regain access, please make sure that cookies and JavaScript are enabled before reloading the page.

IMAGES

  1. Dream Vs Reality Essay Free Essay Example

    dreams vs reality essay

  2. Dreams and Reality: 1728 Words Essay Example

    dreams vs reality essay

  3. Dreams and Reality: 1728 Words Essay Example

    dreams vs reality essay

  4. Dreams and Reality: 1728 Words Essay Example

    dreams vs reality essay

  5. Dreams and Reality: 1728 Words Essay Example

    dreams vs reality essay

  6. 📗 Free Essay with a Literature Review on Dreams and Reality

    dreams vs reality essay

VIDEO

  1. My Dreams vs Reality

  2. Dreams VS Reality Part 1

COMMENTS

  1. Dreams and Reality: 1728 Words Essay Example

    Dream vs. Reality: Essay Introduction. The concept of dreams has eluded even the most renowned philosophers and psychologists, including Aristotle, Plato, and Sigmund Freud. Plato likened dreams to a presentation that we experience while sleeping (Hamilton, Cairns and Cooper 571). Modern psychology seems to have borrowed the definition of a ...

  2. Dreams and Dreaming

    This entry provides an overview of major themes in the philosophy of sleep and dreaming, with a focus on Western analytic philosophy, and discusses relevant scientific findings. 1. Dreams and epistemology. 1.1 Cartesian dream skepticism. 1.2 Earlier discussions of dream skepticism and why Descartes' version is special.

  3. Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer" Essay

    Dreams vs. Reality: "Fences" and "O' Pioneer" Essay. The novels, Fences by August Wilson, and O' Pioneer by Willa Cather describe the lifestyle of a common American citizen. August Wilson focuses on the struggles of the African Americans to fit in a society controlled by racism.

  4. Dreams Vs Reality Essay : Dreams And Reality

    Dreams Vs Reality Essay : Dreams And Reality. At some point, someone has said that high school will be the best four years of their lives and college gets even better. So with that idea in people's heads, they come up with their ideal image of the college. They start planning the perfect scenario of what college they will go to and what their ...

  5. Gatsby's Dream Vs Reality: [Essay Example], 515 words

    Gatsby's Dream Vs Reality. The protagonist, Jay Gatsby, epitomizes the pursuit of wealth, love, and happiness, but his dream is ultimately undermined by the constraints of reality. In today's society, the theme of pursuing dreams in the face of harsh realities remains as relevant as ever. This essay will examine the dichotomy between Gatsby ...

  6. Dreams and Reality: A Storyteller's Look at Life

    poem. The dreams enter with the voice. This brings the collection full circle, from starting in a reality mixed with daydreams, into fictional worlds, into the painful real struggles of life and growing to, observations of the natural world beneficial for a writer, and then ending with a mixing of observation and dreams.

  7. Dreams vs. Reality

    Dreams vs. Reality. Categories: Dream. Download. Essay, Pages 7 (1663 words) Views. 1738. The world is a deadly, unforgiving and often ironic place where people become all consumed by their surroundings. There are many occasions around the world in which people only care about themselves; for example on Black Friday people get pushed, hurt or ...

  8. Dreams vs. Reality Theme in Life is a Dream

    Dreams vs. Reality Theme Analysis. LitCharts assigns a color and icon to each theme in Life is a Dream, which you can use to track the themes throughout the work. Pedro Calderón de la Barca's Life is a Dream tells the story of Basilio, King of Poland, who imprisons his son, Segismundo, after a prophecy claims it is the young prince's ...

  9. Dreams and Reality in Of Mice and Men

    Dreams and Reality in Of Mice and Men. John Steinbeck's Of Mice and Men is a powerful and vivid depiction of life in rural America. It recounts the tragic story of George Milton and Lennie Small ...

  10. Dream Essays: Samples & Topics

    Turning My Dream to Become an Enterpreneur to Reality. 4. If I Had a Million Dollars: Dreams and Possibilities. 5. My Passion for Becoming a Registered Nurse. 6. Following Dreams: With Special Reference To Paulo Coelho's The Alchemist. 7. Illusion vs Reality it "The Great Gatsby" and Other Literature. 8. Passion And Dream Vs. Reality In ...

  11. Dreams Vs. Reality In John Steinbeck's Of Mice And Men

    The first theme incorporated is the idea if dreams versus reality. Lennie and George have a plan. They plan on getting their own ranch together. They want to have a house with a couple of acres and a few animals and a vegetable garden but most importantly, Lennie wants rabbits! He says they will live "off the fatta the lan." (Steinbeck 49 ...

  12. Dreams And Reality Essay Examples

    Stuck on your essay? Browse essays about Dreams And Reality and find inspiration. Learn by example and become a better writer with Kibin's suite of essay help services.

  13. American Dream vs. Reality

    The American Dream is a desire to reach personal goals and satisfy specific accomplishments that lead to a meaningful and successful life. In the search for a perfect American dream, much can be lost; this notion is reflected in Death of a Salesman, written by Arthur Miller, and The Great Gatsby, written by F. Scott Fitzgerald. These literary works describe the lengths that some persons can go ...

  14. Explaining Why Dreams and Goals Are Valuable

    Explaining why dreams and goals are valuable begins with their role in igniting aspirations and nurturing human potential. Dreams are the seeds of possibility, encapsulating desires, visions, and ambitions that extend beyond the present reality. They inspire individuals to envision a future that is richer, more fulfilling, and aligned with ...

  15. Dreams Essay Dreams Essay

    Dreams Vs Reality Essay : Dreams And Reality. Dreams Vs Reality At some point, someone has said that high school will be the best four years of their lives and college gets even better. So with that idea in people&#039;s heads, they come up with their ideal image of the college. They start planning the perfect scenario of what college they will ...

  16. Dreams vs Reality Philosophy & Spoken Word

    Reality vs Dreams is a spoken word poem I created when I found myself at my own crossroads with these types of questions. When I was younger I didn't enjoy my reality. My reality was abusive, crime ridden and full of fear and loneliness. However, in my solitude, it was my dreams that helped me through the pain. My dreams were my positive ...

  17. Paragraph on Dream And Reality

    Dreams can give us ideas, but it's in reality where we can work hard and make those ideas come true. Paragraph on Dream And Reality in 250 Words. Dreams and reality are two different yet connected things. Dreams are thoughts, images, or feelings that occur in our minds when we sleep, while reality is what we experience when we are awake.

  18. Dream vs. Reality in Fences and A Raisin in the Sun

    Dreams Vs. Reality Dreaming is a part of life that gives one an escape from reality into an altered state or desired fantasy. Everyone's dreams differ and not one is superior to another. Dreams are in fact, an extremely personal thing. It can be inspiring, depressing, or even preposterous....

  19. Dreams Vs. Reality In William Shakespeare's A Midsummers Night...

    Caught in a landslide, No escape from reality. Open your eyes, Look up to the skies and see…". English playwright William Shakespeare plays with this idea of dreams versus reality throughout a number of his production. The William Shakespeare play A Midsummers Night Dream plays with this idea more than any other play production created by ...

  20. Dream vs. Reality: Essay on Great Gatsby

    GATSBY ESSAY #1: DREAM VS. REALITY Dreams cannot really meet the demands of reality. High dreams can lead to great falls or regret when those high dreams are not met by reality. For example in my life, my summer, school and driving. Well this is what I dreamed my summer would be like; I tho...

  21. Dreams Essay.pdf

    Document Dreams Essay.pdf, Subject Psychology, from Seton Hall University, Length: 40 pages, Preview: Dreams Vs Reality Essay : Dreams And Reality Dreams Vs Reality At some point, someone has said Please share free course specific Documents, Notes, Summaries and more!