Logo for Minnesota Libraries Publishing Project

Want to create or adapt books like this? Learn more about how Pressbooks supports open publishing practices.

41 Bertrand Russell–two essays

66 years old Bertrand Russell

Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell , 1872 – 1970 CE, was a British philosopher, writer, social critic and political activist. In the early 20th century, Russell led the British “revolt against idealism”.  He is considered one of the founders of analytic philosophy.  Russell was an anti-war activist and went to prison for his pacifism during World War I.    He did conclude that the war against Adolf Hitler was a necessary “lesser of two evils”  He won the Nobel Prize in Literature in 1950 “”in recognition of his varied and significant writings in which he champions humanitarian ideals and freedom of thought.”

In “Reflections on My Eightieth Birthday” (“Postscript” in his  Autobiography ), Russell wrote: “I have lived in the pursuit of a vision, both personal and social.

Personal: to care for what is noble, for what is beautiful, for what is gentle; to allow moments of insight to give wisdom at more mundane times.

Social: to see in imagination the society that is to be created, where individuals grow freely, and where hate and greed and envy die because there is nothing to nourish them. These things I believe, and the world, for all its horrors, has left me unshaken”.

You might find it interesting to see the two things that he believed he would like to say to a future generation.  It takes less than 2 minutes, but in 1959, this is what Bertrand Russell had to say:

Message to Future Generations

From  Bertrand Russell’s: The Problems of Philosophy: Chapter XV: The Value of Philosophy

This is a short interview with Woodrow Wyatt in 1960, when Russell was 87 years old.

Mankind’s Future and Philosophy

Bertrand Russell portrait.

The life of the instinctive man is shut up within the circle of his private interests : family and friends may be included, but the outer world is not regarded except as it may help or hinder what comes within the circle of instinctive wishes. In such a life there is something feverish and confined, in comparison with which the philosophic life is calm and free. The private world of instinctive interests is a small one, set in the midst of a great and powerful world which must, sooner or later, lay our private world in ruins.

Unless we can so enlarge our interests as to include the whole outer world, we remain like a garrison in a beleaguered fortress, knowing that the enemy prevents escape and that ultimate surrender is inevitable. In such a life there is no peace, but a constant strife between the insistence of desire and the powerlessness of will. In one way or another, if our life is to be great and free, we must escape this prison and this strife.

One way of escape is by philosophic contemplation. Philosophic contemplation does not, in its widest survey, divide the universe into two hostile camps—friends and foes, helpful and hostile, good and bad—it views the whole impartially. Philosophic contemplation, when it is unalloyed, does not aim at proving that the rest of the universe is akin to man. All acquisition of knowledge is an enlargement of the Self, but this enlargement is best attained when it is not directly sought. It is obtained when the desire for knowledge is alone operative, by a study which does not wish in advance that its objects should have this or that character, but adapts the Self to the characters which it finds in its objects. This enlargement of Self is not obtained when, taking the Self as it is, we try to show that the world is so similar to this Self that knowledge of it is possible without any admission of what seems alien. The desire to prove this is a form of self-assertion and, like all self-assertion, it is an obstacle to the growth of Self which it desires, and of which the Self knows that it is capable. Self-assertion, in philosophic speculation as elsewhere, views the world as a means to its own ends; thus it makes the world of less account than Self, and the Self sets bounds to the greatness of its goods. In contemplation, on the contrary, we start from the not-Self, and through its greatness the boundaries of Self are enlarged; through the infinity of the universe the mind which contemplates it achieves some share in infinity.

Bertrand Russell lecturing at the University California, Los Angeles where he had taken up a three-year appointment as Professor of Philosophy in March 1939.

The true philosophic contemplation, on the contrary, finds its satisfaction in every enlargement of the not-Self, in everything that magnifies the objects contemplated, and thereby the subject contemplating. Everything, in contemplation, that is personal or private, everything that depends upon habit, self-interest, or desire, distorts the object, and hence impairs the union which the intellect seeks. By thus making a barrier between subject and object, such personal and private things become a prison to the intellect. The free intellect will see as God might see, without a here and now, without hopes and fears, without the trammels of customary beliefs and traditional prejudices, calmly, dispassionately, in the sole and exclusive desire of knowledge—knowledge as impersonal, as purely contemplative, as it is possible for man to attain. Hence also the free intellect will value more the abstract and universal knowledge into which the accidents of private history do not enter, than the knowledge brought by the senses, and dependent, as such knowledge must be, upon an exclusive and personal point of view and a body whose sense organs distort as much as they reveal.

The mind which has become accustomed to the freedom and impartiality of philosophic contemplation will preserve something of the same freedom and impartiality in the world of action and emotion. It will view its purposes and desires as parts of the whole, with the absence of insistence that results from seeing them as infinitesimal fragments in a world of which all the rest is unaffected by any one man’s deeds. The impartiality which, in contemplation, is the unalloyed desire for truth, is the very same quality of mind which, in action, is justice, and in emotion is that universal love which can be given to all, and not only to those who are judged useful or admirable. Thus contemplation enlarges not only the objects of our thoughts, but also the objects of our actions and our affections: it makes us citizens of the universe, not only of one walled city at war with all the rest. In this citizenship of the universe consists man’s true freedom, and his liberation from the thralldom of narrow hopes and fears.

Key Takeaway

The whole problem with the world is that fools and fanatics are always so certain of themselves, but wiser people so full of doubts.

Bertrand Russell

Thus, to sum up our discussion of the value of philosophy; Philosophy is to be studied , not for the sake of any definite answers to its questions, since no definite answers can, as a rule, be known to be true, but rather for the sake of the questions themselves; because these questions enlarge our conception of what is possible, enrich our intellectual imagination and diminish the dogmatic assurance which closes the mind against speculation; but above all because, through the greatness of the universe which philosophy contemplates, the mind also is rendered great, and becomes capable of that union with the universe which constitutes its highest good.

divider between body and bibliography

Ex Libris C. K. OGDEN CONWAY MEMORIAL LECTURE

FREE THOUGHT AND OFFICIAL PROPAGANDA

Delivered at south place institute on march 24, 1922, by the hon. bertrand russell, m.a., f.r.s., (professor graham wallas in the chair), watts & co., johnson’s court, fleet street, e.c.4 1922.

Moncure Conway, in whose honor we are assembled to-day, devoted his life to two great objects: freedom of thought and freedom of the individual.

“In regard to both these objects, something has been gained since his time, but something also has been lost. New dangers, somewhat different in form from those of past ages, threaten both kinds of freedom, and unless a vigorous and vigilant public opinion can be aroused in defense of them, there will be much less of both a hundred years hence than there is now. My purpose in this address is to emphasize the new dangers and to consider how they can be met.

Let us begin by trying to be clear as to what we mean by “free thought.” This expression has two senses.

In its narrower sense it means thought which does not accept the dogmas of traditional religion. In this sense a man is a “free thinker” if he is not a Christian or a Mussulman or a Buddhist or a Shintoist or a member of any of the other bodies of men who accept some inherited orthodoxy. In Christian countries a man is called a “free thinker” if he does not decidedly believe in God, though this would not suffice to make a man a “free thinker” in a Buddhist country.

I do not wish to minimize the importance of free thought in this sense. I am myself a dissenter from all known religions, and I hope that every kind of religious belief will die out. I do not believe that, on the balance, religious belief has been a force for good. Although I am prepared to admit that in certain times and places it has had some good effects, I regard it as belonging to the infancy of human reason, and to a stage of development which we are now outgrowing.

But there is also a wider sense of “free thought,” which I regard as of still greater importance. Indeed, the harm done by traditional religions seems chiefly traceable to the fact that they have prevented free thought in this wider sense. The wider sense is not so easy to define as the narrower, and it will be well to spend some little time in trying to arrive at its essence.

To begin with the most obvious. Thought is not “free” when legal penalties are incurred by the holding or not holding of certain opinions, or by giving expression to one’s belief or lack of belief on certain matters. Very few countries in the world have as yet even this elementary kind of freedom.

In England, under the Blasphemy Laws , it is illegal to express disbelief in the Christian religion, though in practice the law is not set in motion against the well-to-do. It is also illegal to teach what Christ taught on the subject of non-resistance. Therefore, whoever wishes to avoid becoming a criminal must profess to agree with Christ’s teaching, but must avoid saying what that teaching was.

In America no one can enter the country without first solemnly declaring that he disbelieves in anarchism and polygamy; and, once inside, he must also disbelieve in communism.

In Japan it is illegal to express disbelief in the divinity of the Mikado . It will thus be seen that a voyage round the world is a perilous adventure.

A Mohammedan, a Tolstoyan, a Bolshevik, or a Christian cannot undertake it without at some point becoming a criminal, or holding his tongue about what he considers important truths. This, of course, applies only to steerage passengers; saloon passengers are allowed to believe whatever they please, provided they avoid offensive obtrusiveness.

Pen and ink sketch of Bertrand Russell

Legal penalties are, however, in the modern world, the least of the obstacles to freedom of thoughts . The two great obstacles are economic penalties and distortion of evidence. It is clear that thought is not free if the profession of certain opinions makes it impossible to earn a living. It is clear also that thought is not free if all the arguments on one side of a controversy are perpetually presented as attractively as possible, while the arguments on the other side can only be discovered by diligent search. Both these obstacles exist in every large country known to me, except China, which is the last refuge of freedom. It is these obstacles with which I shall be concerned—their present magnitude, the likelihood of their increase, and the possibility of their diminution.

We may say that thought is free when it is exposed to free competition among beliefs —i.e., when all beliefs are able to state their case, and no legal or pecuniary advantages or disadvantages attach to beliefs. This is an ideal which, for various reasons, can never be fully attained. But it is possible to approach very much nearer to it than we do at present.

head filled with branches

Three incidents in my own life will serve to show how, in modern England, the scales are weighted in favor of Christianity. My reason for mentioning them is that many people do not at all realize the disadvantages to which avowed Agnosticism still exposes people.

  • The first incident belongs to a very early stage in my life. My father was a Freethinker, but died when I was only three years old. Wishing me to be brought up without superstition, he appointed two Freethinkers as my guardians. The Courts, however, set aside his will, and had me educated in the Christian faith. I am afraid the result was disappointing, but that was not the fault of the law. If he had directed that I should be educated as a Christadelphian or a Muggletonian or a Seventh-Day Adventist, the Courts would not have dreamed of objecting. A parent has a right to ordain that any imaginable superstition shall be instilled into his children after his death, but has not the right to say that they shall be kept free from superstition if possible.
  • The second incident occurred in the year 1910 . I had at that time a desire to stand for Parliament as a Liberal, and the Whips recommended me to a certain constituency. I addressed the Liberal Association, who expressed themselves favorably, and my adoption seemed certain. But, on being questioned by a small inner caucus, I admitted that I was an Agnostic. They asked whether the fact would come out, and I said it probably would. They asked whether I should be willing to go to church occasionally, and I replied that I should not. Consequently, they selected another candidate, who was duly elected, has been in Parliament ever since, and is a member of the present Government.
  • The third incident occurred immediately afterwards. I was invited by Trinity College, Cambridge, to become a lecturer, but not a Fellow. The difference is not pecuniary; it is that a Fellow has a voice in the government of the College, and cannot be dispossessed during the term of his Fellowship except for grave immorality. The chief reason for not offering me a Fellowship was that the clerical party did not wish to add to the anti-clerical vote. The result was that they were able to dismiss me in 1916, when they disliked my views on the War. If I had been dependent on my lectureship, I should have starved.

These three incidents illustrate different kinds of disadvantages attaching to avowed freethinking even in modern England. Any other avowed Freethinker could supply similar incidents from his personal experience, often of a far more serious character. The net result is that people who are not well-to-do dare not be frank about their religious beliefs.

It is not, of course, only or even chiefly in regard to religion that there is lack of freedom. Belief in communism or free love handicaps a man much more than Agnosticism. Not only is it a disadvantage to hold those views, but it is very much more difficult to obtain publicity for the arguments in their favor. On the other hand, in Russia the advantages and disadvantages are exactly reversed: comfort and power are achieved by professing Atheism, communism, and free love, and no opportunity exists for propaganda against these opinions. The result is that in Russia one set of fanatics feels absolute certainty about one set of doubtful propositions, while in the rest of the world another set of fanatics feels equal certainty about a diametrically opposite set of equally doubtful propositions. From such a situation war, bitterness, and persecution inevitably result on both sides.

Russell was an atheist.  He has specific reasons for this.  Listen to it in his own words:

  Bertrand Russell on Religion

William James used to preach the “will to believe.” For my part, I should wish to preach the “will to doubt.” None of our beliefs are quite true; all have at least a penumbra of vagueness and error. The methods of increasing the degree of truth in our beliefs are well known; they consist in hearing all sides, trying to ascertain all the relevant facts, controlling our own bias by discussion with people who have the opposite bias, and cultivating a readiness to discard any hypothesis which has proved inadequate. These methods are practiced in science, and have built up the body of scientific knowledge.

Every man of science whose outlook is truly scientific is ready to admit that what passes for scientific knowledge at the moment is sure to require correction with the progress of discovery; nevertheless, it is near enough to the truth to serve for most practical purposes, though not for all. In science, where alone something approximating to genuine knowledge is to be found, men’s attitude is tentative and full of doubt.

In religion and politics, on the contrary, though there is as yet nothing approaching scientific knowledge , everybody considers it  de rigueur  to have a dogmatic opinion, to be backed up by inflicting starvation, prison, and war, and to be carefully guarded from argumentative competition with any different opinion. If only men could be brought into a tentatively agnostic frame of mind about these matters, nine-tenths of the evils of the modern world would be cured. War would become impossible, because each side would realize that both sides must be in the wrong. Persecution would cease. Education would aim at expanding the mind, not at narrowing it. Men would be chosen for jobs on account of fitness to do the work, not because they flattered the irrational dogmas of those in power. Thus rational doubt alone, if it could be generated, would suffice to introduce the millennium.

We have had in recent years a brilliant example of the scientific temper of mind in the theory of relativity and its reception by the world. Einstein, a German-Swiss-Jew pacifist, was appointed to a research professorship by the German Government in the early days of the War; his predictions were verified by an English expedition which observed the eclipse of 1919, very soon after the Armistice. His theory upsets the whole theoretical framework of traditional physics; it is almost as damaging to orthodox dynamics as Darwin was to  Genesis . Yet physicists everywhere have shown complete readiness to accept his theory as soon as it appeared that the evidence was in its favor. But none of them, least of all Einstein himself, would claim that he has said the last word. He has not built a monument of infallible dogma to stand for all time. There are difficulties he cannot solve; his doctrines will have to be modified in their turn as they have modified Newton’s. This critical un-dogmatic receptiveness is the true attitude of science.

Albert Einstein during a lecture in Vienna in 1921 by Ferdinand Schmutzer [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons

What is wanted is not the will to believe, but the wish to find out, which is its exact opposite.

If it is admitted that a condition of rational doubt would be desirable , it becomes important to inquire how it comes about that there is so much irrational certainty in the world. A great deal of this is due to the inherent irrationality and credulity of average human nature. But this seed of intellectual original sin is nourished and fostered by other agencies, among which three play the chief part—namely, education, propaganda, and economic pressure .

Let us consider these in turn.

The committee which framed these laws, as quoted by the  New Republic , laid it down that the teacher who “does not approve of the present social system……must surrender his office,” and that “no person who is not eager to combat the theories of social change should be entrusted with the task of fitting the young and old for the responsibilities of citizenship.”

Thus, according to the law of the State of New York, Christ and George Washington were too degraded morally to be fit for the education of the young . If Christ were to go to New York and say, “Suffer the little children to come unto me,” the President of the New York School Board would reply: “Sir, I see no evidence that you are eager to combat theories of social change. Indeed, I have heard it said that you advocate what you call the  kingdom  of heaven, whereas this country, thank God, is a republic. It is clear that the Government of your kingdom of heaven would differ materially from that of New York State, therefore no children will be allowed access to you.” If he failed to make this reply, he would not be doing his duty as a functionary entrusted with the administration of the law.

The effect of such laws is very serious. Let it be granted, for the sake of argument, that the government and the social system in the State of New York are the best that have ever existed on this planet; yet even then both would presumably be capable of improvement. Any person who admits this obvious proposition is by law incapable of teaching in a State school. Thus the law decrees that the teachers shall all be either hypocrites or fools.

Bust of Bertrand Russell by Marcelle Quinton (1980) in Red Lion Square Camden/London

Religious toleration, to a certain extent, has been won because people have ceased to consider religion so important as it was once thought to be. But in politics and economics, which have taken the place formerly occupied by religion, there is a growing tendency to persecution, which is not by any means confined to one party. The persecution of opinion in Russia is more severe than in any capitalist country. I met in Petrograd an eminent Russian poet, Alexander Block, who has since died as the result of privations. The Bolsheviks allowed him to teach æsthetics, but he complained that they insisted on his teaching the subject “from a Marxian point of view.” He had been at a loss to discover how the theory of rhythmics was connected with Marxism, although, to avoid starvation, he had done his best to find out. Of course, it has been impossible in Russia ever since the Bolsheviks came into power to print anything critical of the dogmas upon which their regime is founded.

The examples of America and Russia illustrate the conclusion to which we seem to be driven—namely, that so long as men continue to have the present fanatical belief in the importance of politics free thought on political matters will be impossible, and there is only too much danger that the lack of freedom will spread to all other matters, as it has done in Russia. Only some degree of political skepticism can save us from this misfortune.

It must not be supposed that the officials in charge of education desire the young to become educated. On the contrary, their problem is to impart information without imparting intelligence. Education should have two objects: first, to give definite knowledge—reading and writing, languages and mathematics, and so on; secondly, to create those mental habits which will enable people to acquire knowledge and form sound judgments for themselves. The first of these we may call information, the second intelligence. The utility of information is admitted practically as well as theoretically; without a literate population a modern State is impossible. But the utility of intelligence is admitted only theoretically, not practically; it is not desired that ordinary people should think for themselves, because it is felt that people who think for themselves are awkward to manage and cause administrative difficulties. Only the guardians, in Plato’s language, are to think; the rest are to obey, or to follow leaders like a herd of sheep. This doctrine, often unconsciously, has survived the introduction of political democracy, and has radically vitiated all national systems of education.

This Mikado's Empire, His Imperial Japanese Majesty, Mutsuhito, Emperor of Japan, and the 123d Mikado of the By Internet Archive Book Images [No restrictions], via Wikimedia Commons.,

Definite mis-statements of fact can be legitimately objected to, but they are by no means necessary. The mere words “Pear’s Soap,” which affirm nothing, cause people to buy that article. If, wherever these words appear, they were replaced by the words “The Labour Party,” millions of people would be led to vote for the Labour Party, although the advertisements had claimed no merit for it whatever. But if both sides in a controversy were confined by law to statements which a committee of eminent logicians considered relevant and valid, the main evil of propaganda, as at present conducted, would remain.

Suppose, under such a law, two parties with an equally good case, one of whom had a million pounds to spend on propaganda, while the other had only a hundred thousand . It is obvious that the arguments in favor of the richer party would become more widely known than those in favor of the poorer party, and therefore the richer party would win. This situation is, of course, intensified when one party is the Government. In Russia the Government has an almost complete monopoly of propaganda, but that is not necessary. The advantages which it possesses over its opponents will generally be sufficient to give it the victory, unless it has an exceptionally bad case.

There are two simple principles which, if they were adopted, would solve almost all social problems.

The first is that education should have for one of its aims to teach people only to believe propositions when there is some reason to think that they are true.

The second is that jobs should be given solely for fitness to do the work.

To take the second point first . The habit of considering a man’s religious, moral, and political opinions before appointing him to a post or giving him a job is the modern form of persecution, and it is likely to become quite as efficient as the Inquisition ever was. The old liberties can be legally retained without being of the slightest use. If, in practice, certain opinions lead a man to starve, it is poor comfort to him to know that his opinions are not punishable by law. There is a certain public feeling against starving men for not belonging to the Church of England, or for holding slightly unorthodox opinions in politics. But there is hardly any feeling against the rejection of Atheists or Mormons, extreme communists, or men who advocate free love. Such men are thought to be wicked, and it is considered only natural to refuse to employ them. People have hardly yet waked up to the fact that this refusal, in a highly industrial State, amounts to a very rigorous form of persecution.

If this danger were adequately realized, it would be possible to rouse public opinion , and to secure that a man’s beliefs should not be considered in appointing him to a post. The protection of minorities is vitally important; and even the most orthodox of us may find himself in a minority some day, so that we all have an interest in restraining the tyranny of majorities. Nothing except public opinion can solve this problem. Socialism would make it somewhat more acute, since it would eliminate the opportunities that now arise through exceptional employers. Every increase in the size of industrial undertakings makes it worse, since it diminishes the number of independent employers.

The battle must be fought exactly as the battle of religious toleration was fought. And as in that case, so in this, a decay in the intensity of belief is likely to prove the decisive factor. While men were convinced of the absolute truth of Catholicism or Protestantism, as the case might be, they were willing to persecute on account of them. While men are quite certain of their modern creeds, they will persecute on their behalf. Some element of doubt is essential to the practice, though not to the theory, of toleration.

And this brings me to my other point, which concerns the aims of education.  If there is to be toleration in the world, one of the things taught in schools must be the habit of weighing evidence, and the practice of not giving full assent to propositions which there is no reason to believe true.

By Hilo Tribune, March 21, 1905 [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons

History should be taught in the same way. Napoleon’s campaigns of 1813 and 1814, for instance, might be studied in the  Moniteur , leading up to the surprise which Parisians felt when they saw the Allies arriving under the walls of Paris after they had (according to the official bulletins) been beaten by Napoleon in every battle. In the more advanced classes, students should be encouraged to count the number of times that Lenin has been assassinated by Trotsky, in order to learn contempt for death. Finally, they should be given a school history approved by the Government, and asked to infer what a French school history would say about our wars with France. All this would be a far better training in citizenship than the trite moral maxims by which some people believe that civic duty can be inculcated.

If I am asked how the world is to be induced to adopt these two maxims—namely

(1) that jobs should be given to people on account of their fitness to perform them;

(2) that one aim of education should be to cure people of the habit of believing propositions for which there is no evidence—

I can only say that it must be done by generating an enlightened public opinion . And an enlightened public opinion can only be generated by the efforts of those who desire that it should exist. I do not believe that the economic changes advocated by Socialists will, of themselves, do anything towards curing the evils we have been considering. I think that, whatever happens in politics, the trend of economic development will make the preservation of mental freedom increasingly difficult, unless public opinion insists that the employer shall control nothing in the life of the employee except his work.

Freedom in education could easily be secured, if it were desired , by limiting the function of the State to inspection and payment, and confining inspection rigidly to the definite instruction. But that, as things stand, would leave education in the hands of the Churches, because, unfortunately, they are more anxious to teach their beliefs than Freethinkers are to teach their doubts. It would, however, give a free field, and would make it possible for a liberal education to be given if it were really desired. More than that ought not to be asked of the law.

My plea throughout this address has been for the spread of the scientific temper , which is an altogether different thing from the knowledge of scientific results. The scientific temper is capable of regenerating mankind and providing an issue for all our troubles. The results of science, in the form of mechanism, poison gas, and the yellow press, bid fair to lead to the total downfall of our civilization. It is a curious antithesis, which a Martian might contemplate with amused detachment. But for us it is a matter of life and death. Upon its issue depends the question whether our grandchildren are to live in a happier world, or are to exterminate each other by scientific methods, leaving perhaps to Negroes and Papuans the future destinies of mankind.

If you would like to hear a more thorough interview with Russell, you can find it here at:

  Face to Face Interview with the BBC

divider between body and bibliography

Project Gutenberg’s The Problems of Philosophy, by Bertrand Russell

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org

Title: The Problems of Philosophy

Author: Bertrand Russell

Release Date: May 2, 2009 [EBook #5827]

Last Updated: February 7, 2013 Language: English

Project Gutenberg’s Free Thought and Official Propaganda, by Bertrand Russell

This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org/license

Title: Free Thought and Official Propaganda

Release Date: February 16, 2014 [EBook #44932]

Language: English

Bertrand Russell--two essays Copyright © 2018 by Jody L Ondich is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License , except where otherwise noted.

Share This Book

  • Project Gutenberg
  • 73,570 free eBooks
  • 20 by Bertrand Russell

Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays by Bertrand Russell

Book Cover

Read now or download (free!)

Similar books, about this ebook.

  • Privacy policy
  • About Project Gutenberg
  • Terms of Use
  • Contact Information

iBiblio

SEP thinker apres Rodin

Bertrand Russell

Bertrand Arthur William Russell (b.1872 – d.1970) was a British philosopher, logician, essayist and social critic best known for his work in mathematical logic and analytic philosophy. His most influential contributions include his defense of logicism (the view that mathematics is in some important sense reducible to logic), his refining of the predicate calculus introduced by Gottlob Frege (which still forms the basis of most contemporary logic), his defense of neutral monism (the view that the world consists of just one type of substance that is neither exclusively mental nor exclusively physical), and his theories of definite descriptions and logical atomism . Along with G.E. Moore , Russell is generally recognized as one of the founders of modern analytic philosophy. Along with Kurt Gödel , he is regularly credited with being one of the most important logicians of the twentieth century.

Over the course of his long career, Russell made significant contributions, not just to logic and philosophy, but to a broad range of subjects including education, history, political theory and religious studies. In addition, many of his writings on a variety of topics in both the sciences and the humanities have influenced generations of general readers.

After a life marked by controversy—including dismissals from both Trinity College, Cambridge, and City College, New York—Russell was awarded the Order of Merit in 1949 and the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1950. Noted for his many spirited anti-war and anti-nuclear protests, Russell remained a prominent public figure until his death at the age of 97.

1. A Chronology of Russell's Life

2. russell's work in logic, 3. russell's work in analytic philosophy, 4. russell's theory of definite descriptions, 5. russell's neutral monism, 6. russell's social and political philosophy, primary literature: russell's writings, secondary literature, other internet resources, related entries.

Interested readers may also wish to listen to two sound clips of Russell speaking .

A short chronology of the major events in Russell's life is as follows:

  • (1872) Born May 18 at Ravenscroft, Wales.
  • (1874) Death of mother and sister.
  • (1876) Death of father; Russell's grandfather, Lord John Russell (the former Prime Minister), and grandmother succeed in overturning Russell's father's will to win custody of Russell and his brother.
  • (1878) Death of grandfather; Russell's grandmother, Lady Russell, supervises Russell's upbringing.
  • (1890) Enters Trinity College, Cambridge.
  • (1893) Awarded first-class B.A. in Mathematics.
  • (1894) Completes the Moral Sciences Tripos (Part II).
  • (1894) Marries Alys Pearsall Smith.
  • (1896) Appointed lecturer at the London School of Economics.
  • (1899) Appointed lecturer at Trinity College, Cambridge.
  • (1900) Meets Peano at International Congress in Paris.
  • (1901) Discovers Russell's paradox .
  • (1902) Corresponds with Frege .
  • (1905) Develops his theory of descriptions.
  • (1906) Elected to the London Mathematical Society.
  • (1907) Runs for parliament and is defeated.
  • (1908) Elected Fellow of the Royal Society.
  • (1911) Meets Wittgenstein and is elected President of the Aristotelian Society.
  • (1916) Fined 110 pounds and dismissed from Trinity College as a result of anti-war protests.
  • (1918) Imprisoned for five months as a result of anti-war protests.
  • (1921) Divorce from Alys and marriage to Dora Black.
  • (1922) Runs for parliament and is defeated.
  • (1923) Runs for parliament and is defeated.
  • (1927) Opens experimental school with Dora.
  • (1931) Becomes the third Earl Russell upon the death of his brother.
  • (1935) Divorce from Dora.
  • (1936) Marriage to Patricia (Peter) Helen Spence.
  • (1939) Appointed professor of philosophy at the University of California at Los Angeles.
  • (1940) Appointment at City College New York revoked prior to Russell's arrival as a result of public protests and a legal judgment in which Russell was found morally unfit to teach at the college.
  • (1943) Dismissed from Barnes Foundation in Pennsylvania, but wins a suit against the Foundation for wrongful dismissal.
  • (1949) Awarded the Order of Merit.
  • (1950) Awarded Nobel Prize for Literature.
  • (1952) Divorce from Patrica (Peter) and marriage to Edith Finch.
  • (1955) Releases Russell-Einstein Manifesto.
  • (1957) Elected President of the first Pugwash Conference.
  • (1958) Becomes founding President of the Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament.
  • (1961) Imprisoned for one week in connection with anti-nuclear protests.
  • (1963) Establishes the Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation.
  • (1970) Dies February 02 at Penrhyndeudraeth, Wales.

As A.J. Ayer writes (1972, 127), “The popular conception of a philosopher as one who combines universal learning with the direction of human conduct was more nearly satisfied by Bertrand Russell than by any other philosopher of our time,” and as W.V. Quine tells us (1966c, 657), “I think many of us were drawn to our profession by Russell's books. He wrote a spectrum of books for a graduated public, layman to specialist. We were beguiled by the wit and a sense of new-found clarity with respect to central traits of reality.” Even so, perhaps the most memorable summing up of Russell's life comes from Russell himself:

Three passions, simple but overwhelmingly strong, have governed my life: the longing for love, the search for knowledge, and unbearable pity for the suffering of mankind. These passions, like great winds, have blown me hither and thither, in a wayward course, over a deep ocean of anguish, reaching to the very verge of despair. … This has been my life. I have found it worth living, and would gladly live it again if the chance were offered me. (1967, I, 3–4)

For further information about Russell's life, readers are encouraged to consult Russell's four autobiographical volumes, My Philosophical Development (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959) and The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell (3 vols, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1967, 1968, 1969). In addition, John Slater's accessible and informative Bertrand Russell (Bristol: Thoemmes, 1994) gives a helpful and accessible short introduction to Russell's life, work and influence. Other sources of biographical information include Ronald Clark's The Life of Bertrand Russell (London: Jonathan Cape, 1975), Ray Monk's Bertrand Russell: The Spirit of Solitude (London: Jonathan Cape, 1996) and Bertrand Russell: The Ghost of Madness (London: Jonathan Cape, 2000), as well as the first volume of A.D. Irvine's Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments (London: Routledge, 1999).

Over the years, Russell has also been the subject of numerous other works, including Bruce Duffy's novel The World as I Found It (New York: Ticknor & Fields, 1987) and the graphic novel by Apostolos Doxiadis and Christos Papadimitriou, Logicomix: An Epic Search for Truth (New York: St Martin's Press, 2009).

For a chronology of Russell's major publications, readers are encouraged to consult the Primary Literature: Russell's Writings section of the Bibliography below. For a more complete list, see A Bibliography of Bertrand Russell (3 vols, London: Routledge, 1994), by Kenneth Blackwell and Harry Ruja. A less detailed, but still comprehensive, list appears in Paul Arthur Schilpp, The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell , 3rd edn (New York: Harper and Row, 1963), pp. 746–803. For a bibliography of the secondary literature surrounding Russell up to the close of the twentieth century, see A.D. Irvine, Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments , Vol. 1 (London: Routledge, 1999), pp. 247–312.

Russell's main contributions to logic and the foundations of mathematics include his discovery of Russell's paradox , his defense of logicism (the view that mathematics is, in some significant sense, reducible to formal logic), his development of the theory of types , his impressively general theory of logical relations, his formalization of the reals, and his refining of the first-order predicate calculus.

Russell discovered the paradox that bears his name in 1901, while working on his Principles of Mathematics (1903). The paradox arises in connection with the set of all sets that are not members of themselves. Such a set, if it exists, will be a member of itself if and only if it is not a member of itself. The paradox is significant since, using classical logic, all sentences are entailed by a contradiction. Russell's discovery thus prompted a large amount of work in logic, set theory, and the philosophy and foundations of mathematics .

Russell's response to the paradox came with the development of his theory of types between 1903 and 1908. It was clear to Russell that some form of restriction needed to be placed on the original comprehension (or abstraction) axiom of naive set theory, the axiom that formalizes the intuition that any coherent condition or property may be used to determine a set (or class). Russell's basic idea was that reference to sets such as the set of all sets that are not members of themselves could be avoided by arranging all sentences into a hierarchy, beginning with sentences about individuals at the lowest level, sentences about sets of individuals at the next lowest level, sentences about sets of sets of individuals at the next lowest level, and so on. Using a vicious circle principle similar to that adopted by the mathematician Henri Poincaré, together with his own so-called “no class” theory of classes, Russell was able to explain why the unrestricted comprehension axiom fails: propositional functions, such as the function “ x is a set,” may not be applied to themselves since self-application would involve a vicious circle. On Russell's view, all objects for which a given condition (or predicate) holds must be at the same level or of the same “type.” Sentences about these objects will then always be higher in the hierarchy than the objects themselves.

Although first introduced in 1903, the theory of types was further developed by Russell in his 1908 article “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types” and in the three-volume work he co-authored with Alfred North Whitehead , Principia Mathematica (1910, 1912, 1913). Thus the theory admits of two versions, the “simple theory” of 1903 and the “ramified theory” of 1908. Both versions of the theory came under attack: the simple theory for being too weak, and the ramified theory for being too strong. For some, it was important that any proposed solution be comprehensive enough to resolve all known paradoxes at once. [ 1 ] For others, it was important that any proposed solution not disallow those parts of classical mathematics that remained consistent, even though they appeared to violate the vicious circle principle.

Russell himself had recognized many of these weaknesses, noting as early as 1903 that it was unlikely that any single solution would resolve all of the known paradoxes. Together with Whitehead, he was also able to introduce a new axiom, the axiom of reducibility, which lessened the vicious circle principle's scope of application and so resolved many of the most worrisome aspects of type theory. Even so, some critics claimed that the axiom was too ad hoc to be justified philosophically.

Of equal significance during this period was Russell's defense of logicism, the theory that mathematics is in some important sense reducible to logic. First defended in his 1901 article “Recent Work on the Principles of Mathematics,” and then later in greater detail in his Principles of Mathematics and in Principia Mathematica , Russell's logicism consisted of two main theses. The first was that all mathematical truths can be translated into logical truths or, in other words, that the vocabulary of mathematics constitutes a proper subset of the vocabulary of logic. The second was that all mathematical proofs can be recast as logical proofs or, in other words, that the theorems of mathematics constitute a proper subset of the theorems of logic.

Like Gottlob Frege , Russell's basic idea for defending logicism was that numbers may be identified with classes of classes and that number-theoretic statements may be explained in terms of quantifiers and identity. Thus the number 1 would be identified with the class of all unit classes, the number 2 with the class of all two-membered classes, and so on. Statements such as “There are at least two books” would be recast as statements such as “There is a book, x , and there is a book, y , and x is not identical to y .” Statements such as “There are exactly two books” would be recast as “There is a book, x , and there is a book, y , and x is not identical to y , and if there is a book, z , then z is identical to either x or y .” It followed that number-theoretic operations could be explained in terms of set-theoretic operations such as intersection, union, and difference. In Principia Mathematica , Whitehead and Russell were able to provide many detailed derivations of major theorems in set theory, finite and transfinite arithmetic, and elementary measure theory. A fourth volume on geometry was planned but never completed.

Russell's most important writings relating to these topics include not only Principles of Mathematics (1903), “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types” (1908), and Principia Mathematica (1910, 1912, 1913), but also his earlier An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry (1897), and his Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (1919a), the last of which was largely written while Russell was serving time in Brixton Prison as a result of his anti-war activities. Coincidentally, it was at roughly this same time (1918–19) that Wittgenstein was completing his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus while being detained as a prisoner of war at Monte Cassino during World War I.

In much the same way that Russell used logic in an attempt to clarify issues in the foundations of mathematics, he also used logic in an attempt to clarify issues in philosophy. As one of the founders of analytic philosophy, Russell made significant contributions to a wide variety of areas, including metaphysics, epistemology, ethics and political theory. According to Russell, it is the philosopher's job to discover a logically ideal language — a language that will exhibit the true nature of the world in such a way that we will not be misled by the accidental surface structure of natural language. Just as atomic facts (the association of universals with an appropriate number of individuals) may be combined into molecular facts in the world itself, such a language would allow for the description of such combinations using logical connectives such as “and” and “or.” In addition to atomic and molecular facts, Russell also held that general facts (facts about “all” of something) were needed to complete the picture of the world. Famously, he vacillated on whether negative facts were also required.

The reason Russell believes that many ordinarily accepted statements may be open to doubt is that they appear to refer to entities that are known only inferentially. Thus, underlying Russell's various projects was not only Russell's use of logical analysis, but also his long-standing aim of discovering whether, and to what extent, knowledge is possible. “There is one great question,” he writes in 1911. “Can human beings know anything, and if so, what and how? This question is really the most essentially philosophical of all questions” (quoted in Slater 1994, 67).

Motivating this question was the traditional problem of the external world. If our knowledge of the external world comes through inference to the best explanation, and if such inferences are always fallible, what guarantee do we have that our beliefs are reliable? Russell's response was partly metaphysical and partly epistemological. On the metaphysical side, Russell developed his famous theory of logical atomism, in which the world is said to consist of a complex of logical atoms (such as “little patches of colour”) and their properties. Together these atoms and their properties form the atomic facts which, in turn, are combined to form logically complex objects. What we normally take to be inferred entities (for example, enduring physical objects) are then understood to be logical constructions formed from the immediately given entities of sensation, viz., “sensibilia.”

On the epistemological side, Russell argued that it was also important to show that each questionable entity may be reduced to, or defined in terms of, another entity (or class of entities) whose existence is more certain. For example, on this view, an ordinary physical object that normally might be believed to be known only through inference may be defined instead

as a certain series of appearances, connected with each other by continuity and by certain causal laws. ... More generally, a ‘thing’ will be defined as a certain series of aspects, namely those which would commonly be said to be of the thing. To say that a certain aspect is an aspect of a certain thing will merely mean that it is one of those which, taken serially, are the thing. (1914a, 106–107)

The reason we are able to do this is that

our world is not wholly a matter of inference. There are things that we know without asking the opinion of men of science. If you are too hot or too cold, you can be perfectly aware of this fact without asking the physicist what heat and cold consist of. … We may give the name ‘data’ to all the things of which we are aware without inference (1959, 23).

We can then use these data (or sensibilia or sense data) with which we are directly acquainted to construct the relevant objects of knowledge. Similarly, numbers may be reduced to collections of classes, points and instants may be reduced to ordered classes of volumes and events, and classes themselves may be reduced to propositional functions.

It is with these kinds of examples in mind that Russell suggests that we adopt what he calls “the supreme maxim in scientific philosophizing”, namely the principle that “Whenever possible, logical constructions”, or as he also sometimes puts it, logical fictions, “are to be substituted for inferred entities” (1914c, 155; cf. 1914a, 107, and 1924, 326). Anything that resists construction in this sense may be said to be an ontological atom. Such objects are atomic, both in the sense that they fail to be composed of individual, substantial parts, and in the sense that they exist independently of one another. Their corresponding propositions are also atomic, both in the sense that they contain no other propositions as parts, and in the sense that the members of any pair of true atomic propositions will be logically independent of one another. It turns out that formal logic, if carefully developed, will mirror precisely, not only the various relations between all such propositions, but their various internal structures as well.

It is in this context that Russell also introduces his famous distinction between two kinds of knowledge of truths: that which is direct, intuitive, certain and infallible, and that which is indirect, derivative, uncertain and open to error (see 1905, 41f; 1911, 1912, and 1914b). To be justified, every indirect knowledge claim must be capable of being derived from more fundamental, direct or intuitive knowledge claims. The kinds of truths that are capable of being known directly include both truths about immediate facts of sensation and truths of logic. [ 2 ]

Eventually, Russell supplemented this distinction between direct and indirect knowledge with his famous distinction between knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. As Russell explains, “I say that I am acquainted with an object when I have a direct cognitive relation to that object, i.e. when I am directly aware of the object itself. When I speak of a cognitive relation here, I do not mean the sort of relation which constitutes judgment, but the sort which constitutes presentation” (1911, 209). Later, he clarifies this point by adding that acquaintance involves, not knowledge of truths, but knowledge of things (1912a, 44). Thus, while intuitive knowledge and derivative knowledge both involve knowledge of propositions (or truths), knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description both involve knowledge of objects (or things). [ 3 ] Since it is those objects with which we have direct acquaintance that are the least questionable members of our ontology, it is these objects upon which Russell ultimately bases his epistemology.

Russell's contributions to metaphysics and epistemology were also unified by his views concerning the centrality of both scientific knowledge in general and the importance of there being an underlying scientific methodology that in large part is common to both philosophy and the scientific disciplines. In the case of philosophy, this methodology expressed itself through Russell's use of logical analysis. In fact, Russell often claimed that he had more confidence in his methodology than in any particular philosophical conclusion.

This broad conception of philosophy arose in part from Russell's idealist origins (see, e.g., Griffin 1991 and Hylton 1990a). This is so, even though Russell tells us that his one, true revolution in philosophy came about as a result of his break from idealism. Russell saw that the idealist doctrine of internal relations led to a series of contradictions regarding asymmetrical (and other) relations necessary for mathematics. Thus, in 1898, he abandoned the idealism that he had encountered as a student at Cambridge, together with his Kantian methodology, in favour of a pluralistic realism. As a result, he soon became famous as an advocate of the “new realism” and for his “new philosophy of logic,” emphasizing as he did the importance of modern logic for philosophical analysis. The underlying themes of this “revolution” included his belief in pluralism, his emphasis upon anti-psychologism, and his belief in the importance of science. Each of these themes remained central to Russell's philosophy for the remainder of his life (see, e.g., Hager 1994 and Weitz 1944).

Russell's philosophical methodology required the making and testing of hypotheses through the weighing of evidence. Hence Russell's comment that he wished to emphasize the “scientific method” in philosophy (see, e.g., Irvine 1989). It also required the rigorous analysis of problematic propositions using the machinery of first-order logic. It was Russell's belief that by using the new logic of his day, philosophers would be able to exhibit the underlying “logical form” of natural-language statements. A statement's logical form, in turn, would help philosophers resolve problems of reference associated with the ambiguity and vagueness of natural language.

Thus, just as we distinguish three separate sense of “is” (the is of predication, the is of identity, and the is of existence) and exhibit these three senses using three separate logical notations ( Px , x = y , and ∃ x respectively) we will also discover other ontologically significant distinctions by being made aware of a sentence's correct logical form. On Russell's view, the subject matter of philosophy is then distinguished from that of the sciences only by the generality and the a prioricity of philosophical statements, not by the underlying methodology of the discipline. In philosophy, just as in mathematics, Russell believed that it was by applying logical machinery and insights that advances in analysis would be made.

Russell's most famous example of his “analytic method” concerns denoting phrases such as descriptions and proper names. In his Principles of Mathematics , Russell had adopted the view that every denoting phrase (for example, “Scott,” “the author of Waverley ,” “the number two,” “the golden mountain”) denoted, or referred to, an existing entity. By the time his landmark article, “On Denoting,” appeared two years later in 1905, Russell had modified this extreme realism and had instead become convinced that denoting phrases need not possess a theoretical unity.

While logically proper names (words such as “this” or “that” which refer to sensations of which an agent is immediately aware) do have referents associated with them, descriptive phrases (such as “the smallest number less than pi”) should be viewed as a collection of quantifiers (such as “all” and “some”) and propositional functions (such as “ x is a number”). As such, they are not to be viewed as referring terms but, rather, as “incomplete symbols.” In other words, they should be viewed as symbols that take on meaning within appropriate contexts, but that are meaningless in isolation.

If Russell is correct, it follows that in the sentence

(1) The present King of France is bald,

the definite description “The present King of France” plays a role quite different from that of a proper name such as “Scott” in the sentence

(2) Scott is bald.

Letting K abbreviate the predicate “is a present King of France” and B abbreviate the predicate “is bald,” Russell assigns sentence (1) the logical form

(1′) There is an x such that Kx , for any y , if Ky then y=x , and Bx .

Alternatively, in the notation of the predicate calculus, we have

(1″) ∃ x [( Kx & ∀ y ( Ky → y=x )) & Bx ].

In contrast, by allowing s to abbreviate the name “Scott,” Russell assigns sentence (2) the very different logical form

(2′) Bs .

This distinction between logical forms allows Russell to explain three important puzzles. The first concerns the operation of the Law of Excluded Middle and how this law relates to denoting terms. According to one reading of the Law of Excluded Middle, it must be the case that either “The present King of France is bald” is true or “The present King of France is not bald” is true. But if so, both sentences appear to entail the existence of a present King of France, clearly an undesirable result. Russell's analysis shows how this conclusion can be avoided. By appealing to analysis (1′), it follows that there is a way to deny (1) without being committed to the existence of a present King of France, namely by accepting that “It is not the case that there exists a present King of France who is bald” is true.

The second puzzle concerns the Law of Identity as it operates in (so-called) opaque contexts. Even though “Scott is the author of Waverley ” is true, it does not follow that the two referring terms “Scott” and “the author of Waverley ” need be interchangeable in every situation. Thus, although “George IV wanted to know whether Scott was the the author of Waverley ” is true, “George IV wanted to know whether Scott was Scott” is, presumably, false. Russell's distinction between the logical forms associated with the use of proper names and definite descriptions shows why this is so.

To see this we once again let s abbreviate the name “Scott.” We also let w abbreviate “ Waverley ” and A abbreviate the two-place predicate “is the author of.” It then follows that the sentence

is not at all equivalent to the sentence

(4) ∃ x [ Axw & ∀ y ( Ayw → y=x ) & x=s ].

Sentence (3), for example, is clearly a necessary truth, while sentence (4) is not.

The third puzzle relates to true negative existential claims, such as the claim “The golden mountain does not exist.” Here, once again, by treating definite descriptions as having a logical form distinct from that of proper names, Russell is able to give an account of how a speaker may be committed to the truth of a negative existential without also being committed to the belief that the subject term has reference. That is, the claim that Scott does not exist is false since

(5) ~∃ x ( x=s )

is self-contradictory. (After all, there must exist at least one thing that is identical to s since it is a logical truth that s is identical to itself!) In contrast, the claim that a golden mountain does not exist may be true since, assuming that G abbreviates the predicate “is golden” and M abbreviates the predicate “is a mountain,” there is nothing contradictory about

(6) ~∃ x ( Gx & Mx ).

One final major contribution to philosophy was Russell's defence of neutral monism , the view that the world consists of just one type of substance that is neither exclusively mental nor exclusively physical. Like idealism (the view that there exists nothing but the mental) and physicalism (the view that there exists nothing but the physical), neutral monism rejects dualism (the view that there exist distinct mental and physical substances). However, unlike both idealism and physicalism, neutral monism holds that this single existing substance may be viewed in some contexts as being mental and in others as being physical. As Russell puts it,

“Neutral monism”—as opposed to idealistic monism and materialistic monism—is the theory that the things commonly regarded as mental and the things commonly regarded as physical do not differ in respect of any intrinsic property possessed by the one set and not by the other, but differ only in respect of arrangement and context. (CP, Vol. 7, 15)

To help understand this general suggestion, Russell introduces the analogy of a postal directory:

The theory may be illustrated by comparison with a postal directory, in which the same names comes twice over, once in alphabetical and once in geographical order; we may compare the alphabetical order to the mental, and the geographical order to the physical. The affinities of a given thing are quite different in the two orders, and its causes and effects obey different laws. Two objects may be connected in the mental world by the association of ideas, and in the physical world by the law of gravitation. … Just as every man in the directory has two kinds of neighbours, namely alphabetical neighbours and geographical neighbours, so every object will lie at the intersection of two causal series with different laws, namely the mental series and the physical series. ‘Thoughts’ are not different in substance from ‘things’; the stream of my thoughts is a stream of things, namely of the things which I should commonly be said to be thinking of; what leads to its being called a stream of thoughts is merely that the laws of succession are different from the physical laws. (CP, Vol. 7, 15)

In other words, when viewed as being mental, a thought or idea may have associated with it other thoughts or ideas that seem related even though, when viewed as being physical, they have very little in common. As Russell explains, “In my mind, Caesar may call up Charlemagne, whereas in the physical world the two were widely sundered” (CP, Vol. 7, 15). Even so, it is a mistake, on this view, to postulate two distinct types of thing (the idea of Caesar, and the man Caesar) that are composed to two distinct substances (the mental and the physical). Instead, “The whole duality of mind and matter, according to this theory, is a mistake; there is only one kind of stuff out of which the world is made, and this stuff is called mental in one arrangement, physical in the other” (CP, Vol. 7, 15).

Russell appears to have developed this theory around 1913, while he was working on his Theory of Knowledge manuscript, and on his 1914 Monist article, “On the Nature of Acquaintance.” Decades later, in 1964, he remarked that “I am not conscious of any serious change in my philosophy since I adopted neutral monism” (Eames 1967, 511).

Russell's most important writings relating to these topics include “On Denoting” (1905), “Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description” (1910a), “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” (1918, 1919), “Logical Atomism” (1924), The Analysis of Mind (1921), The Analysis of Matter (1927a), and Theory of Knowledge (CP, Vol. 7).

Russell's social influence stems from three main sources: his long-standing social activism, his many writings on the social and political issues of his day, and his popularizations of numerous technical writings in philosophy and the natural sciences.

Among Russell's many popularizations are his two best-selling works, The Problems of Philosophy (1912) and A History of Western Philosophy (1945). Both of these books, as well as his numerous books popularizing science, have done much to educate and inform generations of general readers. Naturally enough, Russell saw a link between education, in this broad sense, and social progress. As he put it, “Education is the key to the new world” (1926, 83). Partly this is due to our need to understand nature, but equally important is our need to understand each other:

The thing, above all, that a teacher should endeavor to produce in his pupils, if democracy is to survive, is the kind of tolerance that springs from an endeavor to understand those who are different from ourselves. It is perhaps a natural human impulse to view with horror and disgust all manners and customs different from those to which we are used. Ants and savages put strangers to death. And those who have never traveled either physically or mentally find it difficult to tolerate the queer ways and outlandish beliefs of other nations and other times, other sects and other political parties. This kind of ignorant intolerance is the antithesis of a civilized outlook, and is one of the gravest dangers to which our overcrowded world is exposed. (1950, 121)

At the same time, Russell is also famous for suggesting that a widespread reliance upon evidence, rather than upon superstition, would have enormous social consequences: “I wish to propose for the reader's favourable consideration,” says Russell, “a doctrine which may, I fear, appear wildly paradoxical and subversive. The doctrine in question is this: that it is undesirable to believe a proposition when there is no ground whatever for supposing it true” (A1928, 11).

Still, Russell is best known in many circles as a result of his campaigns against the proliferation of nuclear weapons and against western involvement in the Vietnam War during the 1960s. However, Russell's social activism stretches back at least as far as 1910, when he published his Anti-Suffragist Anxieties , and to 1916, when he was convicted and fined in connection with anti-war protests during World War I. Because of his conviction, he was dismissed from his post at Trinity College, Cambridge. Two years later, he was convicted a second time. The result was six months in prison (see, e.g., Hardy 1942). Russell also ran unsuccessfully for Parliament (in 1907, 1922, and 1923) and, together with his second wife, founded and operated an experimental school during the late 1920s and early 1930s (see, e.g., Russell 1926).

Although he became the third Earl Russell upon the death of his brother in 1931, Russell's radicalism continued to make him a controversial figure well through middle-age. While teaching in the United States in the late 1930s, he was offered a teaching appointment at City College, New York. The appointment was revoked following a large number of public protests and a 1940 judicial decision which found him morally unfit to teach at the College (see, e.g., Dewey and Kallen 1941).

In 1954 he delivered his famous “Man's Peril” broadcast on the BBC, condemning the Bikini H-bomb tests. A year later, together with Albert Einstein, he released the Russell-Einstein Manifesto calling for the curtailment of nuclear weapons. In 1957 he was a prime organizer of the first Pugwash Conference, which brought together a large number of scientists concerned about the nuclear issue. He became the founding president of the Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament in 1958 and was once again imprisoned, this time in connection with anti-nuclear protests in 1961. The media coverage surrounding his conviction only served to enhance Russell's reputation and to further inspire the many idealistic youths who were sympathetic to his anti-war and anti-nuclear protests.

During these controversial years Russell also wrote many of the books that brought him to the attention of popular audiences. These include his Principles of Social Reconstruction (1916), A Free Man's Worship (1923), On Education (1926), Why I Am Not a Christian (1927c), Marriage and Morals (1929), The Conquest of Happiness (1930), The Scientific Outlook (1931), and Power: A New Social Analysis (1938).

Upon being awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1950, Russell used his acceptance speech to emphasize, once again, themes related to his social activism.

Bibliography

A selection of russell's books and articles, major anthologies of russell's writings, the collected papers of bertrand russell.

  • (1896) German Social Democracy , London: Longmans, Green.
  • (1897) An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry , Cambridge: At the University Press.
  • (1900) A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz , Cambridge: At the University Press.
  • (1901) “Recent Work on the Principles of Mathematics,” International Monthly , 4, 83–101. Repr. as “Mathematics and the Metaphysicians” in Russell, Bertrand, Mysticism and Logic , London: Longmans Green, 1918, 74–96.
  • (1903) The Principles of Mathematics , Cambridge: At the University Press.
  • (1905) “On Denoting,” Mind , 14, 479–493. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Essays in Analysis , London: Allen and Unwin, 1973, 103–119, and in Logic and Knowledge , London: George Allen and Unwin, 1956, 41–56.
  • (1908) “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types,” American Journal of Mathematics , 30, 222–262. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge , London: Allen and Unwin, 1956, 59–102, and in van Heijenoort, Jean, From Frege to Gödel , Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 152–182.
  • (1910, 1912, 1913) (with Alfred North Whitehead) Principia Mathematica , 3 vols, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second edition, 1925 (Vol. 1), 1927 (Vols 2, 3). Abridged as Principia Mathematica to *56 , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962.
  • (1910a) “Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 11, 108–128. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Mysticism and Logic , London: Allen and Unwin, 1963, 152–167.
  • (1911) “Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,” in Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays , London: George Allen and Unwin,1918, 209–232.
  • (1912a) The Problems of Philosophy , London: Williams and Norgate; New York: Henry Holt and Company. Repr. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997.
  • (1912b) “On the Relations of Universals and Particulars,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , 12, 1–24. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge , London: Allen and Unwin, 1956, 105–124.
  • (1914a) Our Knowledge of the External World , Chicago and London: The Open Court Publishing Company.
  • (1914b) “On the Nature of Acquaintance,” in Logic and Knowledge , London: George Allen and Unwin, 1956, 127–174.
  • (1914c) “The Relation of Sense-Data to Physics,” in Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1918, 145–179.
  • (1916) Principles of Social Reconstruction , London: George Allen and Unwin. Repr. as Why Men Fight , New York: The Century Company, 1917.
  • (1917) Political Ideals , New York: The Century Company.
  • (1918, 1919) “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism,” Monist , 28, 495–527; 29, 32–63, 190–222, 345–380. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge , London: Allen and Unwin, 1956, 177–281.
  • (1919a) Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
  • (1921) The Analysis of Mind , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
  • (1923) A Free Man's Worship , Portland, Maine: Thomas Bird Mosher. Repr. as What Can A Free Man Worship? , Girard, Kansas: Haldeman-Julius Publications, 1927.
  • (1924) “Logical Atomism,” in Muirhead, J.H., Contemporary British Philosophers , London: Allen and Unwin, 1924, 356–383. Repr. in Russell, Bertrand, Logic and Knowledge , London: Allen and Unwin, 1956, 323–343.
  • (1926) On Education, Especially in Early Childhood , London: George Allen and Unwin. Repr. as Education and the Good Life , New York: Boni and Liveright, 1926. Abridged as Education of Character , New York: Philosophical Library, 1961.
  • (1927a) The Analysis of Matter , London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner; New York: Harcourt, Brace.
  • (1927b) An Outline of Philosophy , London: George Allen and Unwin. Repr. as Philosophy , New York: W.W. Norton, 1927.
  • (1927c) Why I Am Not a Christian , London: Watts, New York: The Truth Seeker Company.
  • (1929) Marriage and Morals , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Horace Liveright.
  • (1930) The Conquest of Happiness , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Horace Liveright.
  • (1931) The Scientific Outlook , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
  • (1938) Power: A New Social Analysis , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
  • (1940) An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
  • (1945) A History of Western Philosophy , New York: Simon and Schuster; London: George Allen and Unwin, 1946.
  • (1948) Human Knowledge: Its Scope and Limits , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • (1949a) Authority and the Individual , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • (1949b) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism , Minneapolis, Minnesota: Department of Philosophy, University of Minnesota. Repr. as Russell's Logical Atomism , Oxford: Fontana/Collins, 1972.
  • (1954) Human Society in Ethics and Politics , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • (1959) My Philosophical Development , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • (1967, 1968, 1969) The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell , 3 vols, London: George Allen and Unwin; Boston and Toronto: Little Brown and Company (Vols 1 and 2), New York: Simon and Schuster (Vol. 3).
  • A1910, Philosophical Essays , London: Longmans, Green.
  • A1918, Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays , London and New York: Longmans, Green. Repr. as A Free Man's Worship and Other Essays , London: Unwin Paperbacks, 1976.
  • A1928, Sceptical Essays , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
  • A1935, In Praise of Idleness , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: W.W. Norton.
  • A1950, Unpopular Essays , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • A1956a, Logic and Knowledge: Essays, 1901–1950 , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: The Macmillan Company.
  • A1956b, Portraits From Memory and Other Essays , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • A1957, Why I am Not a Christian and Other Essays on Religion and Related Subjects , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • A1961, The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell, 1903–1959 , London: George Allen and Unwin; New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • A1969, Dear Bertrand Russell , London: George Allen and Unwin; Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
  • A1973, Essays in Analysis , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • A1992, The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell, Volume 1 , London: Allen Lane, and New York: Houghton Mifflin.
  • A1999a, Russell on Ethics , London: Routledge.
  • A1999b, Russell on Religion , London: Routledge.
  • A2001, The Selected Letters of Bertrand Russell, Volume 2 , London: Routledge.
  • A2003, Russell on Metaphysics , London: Routledge.

The Bertrand Russell Editorial Project is currently in the process of publishing Russell's Collected Papers (CP). When complete, these volumes will bring together all of Russell's writings, excluding his correspondence and previously published monographs.

  • CP, Vol. 1, Cambridge Essays, 1888–99 , London, Boston, Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1983.
  • CP, Vol. 2: Philosophical Papers, 1896–99 , London and New York: Routledge, 1990.
  • CP, Vol. 3: Towarbd the Principles of Mathematics, London and New York: Routledge, 1994.
  • CP, Vol. 4: Foundations of Logic, 1903–05 , London and New York: Routledge, 1994.
  • CP, Vol. 6: Logical and Philosophical Papers, 1909–13 , London and New York: Routledge, 1992.
  • CP, Vol. 7: Theory of Knowledge: The 1913 Manuscript , London, Boston, Sydney: George Allen and Unwin, 1984.
  • CP, Vol. 8: The Philosophy of Logical Atomism and Other Essays, 1914–19 , London: George Allen and Unwin, 1986.
  • CP, Vol. 9: Essays on Language, Mind and Matter, 1919–26 , London: Unwin Hyman, 1988.
  • CP, Vol. 10: A Fresh Look at Empiricism, 1927–42 , London and New York: Routledge, 1996.
  • CP, Vol. 11: Last Philosophical Testament, 1943–68 , London and New York: Routledge, 1997.
  • CP, Vol. 12: Contemplation and Action, 1902–14 , London, Boston, Sydney: George Allen and] Unwin, 1985.
  • CP, Vol. 13: Prophecy and Dissent, 1914–16 , London: Unwin Hyman, 1988.
  • CP, Vol. 14: Pacifism and Revolution, 1916–18 , London and New York: Routledge, 1995.
  • CP, Vol. 15: Uncertain Paths to Freedom: Russia and China, 1919–1922 , London and New York: Routledge, 2000.
  • CP, Vol. 21: How to Keep the Peace: The Pacifist Dilemma, 1935–38 , London and New York: Routledge, 2008.
  • CP, Vol. 28: Man's Peril, 1954–55 , London and New York: Routledge, 2003.
  • CP, Vol. 29: Détente or Destruction, 1955–57 , London and New York: Routledge, 2005.

Planned and Forthcoming

  • Vol. 5: Toward Principia Mathematica, 1906–08.
  • Vol. 16: Labour and Internationalism, 1922–25.
  • Vol. 17: Authority versus Enlightenment, 1925–27.
  • Vol. 18: Behaviourism and Education, 1927–31.
  • Vol. 19: Science and Civilization, 1931–33.
  • Vol. 20: Fascism and Other Depression Legacies, 1933–34.
  • Vol. 22: The CCNY Case, 1938–40.
  • Vol. 23: The Problems of Democracy, 1941–44.
  • Vol. 24: Civilization and the Bomb, 1944–47.
  • Vol. 25: Defense of the West, 1948–50.
  • Vol. 26: Respectability—At Last, 1950–51.
  • Vol. 27: Culture and the Cold War, 1952–53.
  • Vol. 30: Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament, 1957–59.
  • Vol. 31: The Committee of 100, 1960–62.
  • Vol. 32: A New Plan for Peace and Other Essays, 1963–64.
  • Vol. 33: The Vietnam Campaign, 1965–66.
  • Vol. 34: International War Crimes Tribunal, 1967–70.
  • Vol. 35: Newly Discovered Papers.
  • Vol. 36: Indexes.
  • Ayer, A.J. (1972) “Bertrand Russell as a Philosopher,” Proceedings of the British Academy , 58, 127–151. Repr. in Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (1999) Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments , 4 vols, London: Routledge, vol. 1, 65–85.
  • Blackwell, Kenneth (1985) The Spinozistic Ethics of Bertrand Russell , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Blackwell, Kenneth, and Harry Ruja (1994) A Bibliography of Bertrand Russell , 3 vols, London: Routledge.
  • Broad, C.D. (1973) “Bertrand Russell, as Philosopher,” Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society , 5, 328–341. Repr. in Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (1999) Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments , 4 vols, London: Routledge, vol 1., 1–15.
  • Burke, Tom (1994) Dewey's New Logic: A Reply to Russell , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Carnap, Rudolf (1931) “The Logicist Foundations of Mathematics,” Erkenntnis , 2: 91–105. Repr. in Benacerraf, Paul, and Hilary Putnam (eds), Philosophy of Mathematics , 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983, 41–52; in Klemke, E.D. (ed.), Essays on Bertrand Russell , Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1970, 341–354; and in Pears, David F. (ed.), Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays , Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1972, 175–191.
  • Chomsky, Noam (1971) Problems of Knowledge and Freedom: The Russell Lectures , New York: Vintage.
  • Church, Alonzo (1974) “Russellian Simple Type Theory,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association , 47: 21–33.
  • Church, Alonzo (1976) “Comparison of Russell's Resolution of the Semantical Antinomies with That of Tarski,” Journal of Symbolic Logic , 41: 747–760. Repr. in Irvine, A.D., Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments , vol. 2, New York and London: Routledge, 1999, 96–112.
  • Clark, Ronald William (1975) The Life of Bertrand Russell , London: J. Cape.
  • Clark, Ronald William (1981) Bertrand Russell and His World , London: Thames and Hudson.
  • Copi, Irving (1971) The Theory of Logical Types , London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
  • Dewey, John, and Horace M. Kallen (eds) (1941) The Bertrand Russell Case , New York: Viking.
  • Doxiadis, Apostolos, and Christos Papadimitriou (2009) Logicomix: An Epic Search for Truth , New York: St Martin's Press.
  • Duffy, Bruce (1987) The World as I Found It , New York: Ticknor & Fields.
  • Eames, Elizabeth R. (1967) “The Consistency of Russell's Realism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , 27 (June), p. 511.
  • Eames, Elizabeth R. (1969) Bertrand Russell's Theory of Knowledge , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Eames, Elizabeth R. (1989) Bertrand Russell's Dialogue with his Contemporaries , Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
  • Feinberg, Barry, and Ronald Kasrils (eds) (1969) Dear Bertrand Russell , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Feinberg, Barry, and Ronald Kasrils (1973, 1983) Bertrand Russell's America , 2 vols, London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Gabbay, Dov M., and John Woods (eds) (2009) Handbook of the History of Logic: Volume 5 — Logic From Russell to Church , Amsterdam: Elsevier/North Holland.
  • Gandy, R.O. (1973) “Bertrand Russell, as Mathematician,” Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society , 5: 342–348.
  • Gödel, Kurt (1944) “Russell's Mathematical Logic,” in Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell , 3rd ed., New York: Tudor, 1951, 123–153. Repr. in Benacerraf, Paul, and Hilary Putnam (eds), Philosophy of Mathematics , 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983, 447–469; and in Pears, David F. (ed.) (1972) Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays , Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 192–226.
  • Grattan-Guinness, I. (1977) Dear Russell, Dear Jourdain: A Commentary on Russell's Logic, Based on His Correspondence with Philip Jourdain , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Griffin, Nicholas (1991) Russell's Idealist Apprenticeship , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Griffin, Nicholas (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Bertrand Russell , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hager, Paul J. (1994) Continuity and Change in the Development of Russell's Philosophy , Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
  • Hardy, Godfrey H. (1942) Bertrand Russell and Trinity , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970.
  • Hylton, Peter W. (1990a) Russell, Idealism, and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy , Oxford: Clarendon.
  • Hylton, Peter W. (1990b) “Logic in Russell's Logicism,” in Bell, David, and Neil Cooper (eds), The Analytic Tradition: Philosophical Quarterly Monographs , Vol. 1, Cambridge: Blackwell, 137–172.
  • Irvine, A.D. (1989) “Epistemic Logicism and Russell's Regressive Method,” Philosophical Studies , 55: 303–327.
  • Irvine, A.D. (1996) “Bertrand Russell and Academic Freedom,” Russell , n.s.16, 5–36.
  • Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (1999) Bertrand Russell: Critical Assessments , 4 vols, London: Routledge.
  • Irvine, A.D. (ed.) (2009) Philosophy of Mathematics , Amsterdam: Elsevier/North Holland.
  • Irvine, A.D., and G.A. Wedeking (eds) (1993) Russell and Analytic Philosophy , Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
  • Jager, Ronald (1972) The Development of Bertrand Russell's Philosophy , London: George Allen and Unwin.
  • Kaplan, David (1970) “What is Russell's Theory of Descriptions?,” in Yourgrau, Wolfgang, and Allen D. Breck, (eds), Physics, Logic, and History , New York: Plenum, 277–288. Repr. in Pears, David F. (ed.), Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays , Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1972, 227–244.
  • Klemke, E.D. (ed.) (1970) Essays on Bertrand Russell , Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
  • Landini, Gregory (1998) Russell's Hidden Substitutional Theory , New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Link, Godehard (ed.) (2004) One Hundred Years of Russell's Paradox , Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Linsky, Bernard (1999) Russell's Metaphysical Logic , Stanford: CSLI Publications.
  • Lycan, William (1981) “Logical Atomism and Ontological Atoms,” Synthese , 46: 207–229.
  • Monk, Ray (1996) Bertrand Russell: The Spirit of Solitude , London: Jonathan Cape.
  • Monk, Ray (2000) Bertrand Russell: The Ghost of Madness , London: Jonathan Cape.
  • Monk, Ray, and Anthony Palmer (eds) (1996) Bertrand Russell and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy , Bristol: Thoemmes Press.
  • Monro, D.H. (1960) “Russell's Moral Theories,” Philosophy , 35: 30–50. Repr. in Pears, David F. (ed.), Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays , Garden City, New York: Anchor Books, 1972, 325–355.
  • Moorehead, Caroline (1992) Bertrand Russell , New York: Viking.
  • Nakhnikian, George (ed.) (1974) Bertrand Russell's Philosophy , London: Duckworth.
  • Park, Joe (1963) Bertrand Russell on Education , Columbus: Ohio State University Press.
  • Patterson, Wayne (1993) Bertrand Russell's Philosophy of Logical Atomism , New York: Lang.
  • Pears, David F. (1967) Bertrand Russell and the British Tradition in Philosophy , London: Collins.
  • Pears, David F. (ed.) (1972) Bertrand Russell: A Collection of Critical Essays , New York: Doubleday.
  • Potter, Michael K. (2006) Bertrand Russell's Ethics , London: Continuum Books.
  • Proops, Ian (2006) “Russell's Reasons for Logicism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy , 44: 267-292.
  • Putnam, Hilary (1967) “The Thesis that Mathematics is Logic,” in Schoenman, Ralph (ed.), Bertrand Russell: Philosopher of the Century , London: Allen and Unwin, 273–303. Repr. in Putnam, Hilary, Mathematics, Matter and Method , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 12–42.
  • Quine, W.V. (1938) “On the Theory of Types,” Journal of Symbolic Logic , 3: 125–139.
  • Quine, W.V (1960) Word and Object , Cambridge: MIT Press.
  • Quine, W.V (1966a) Selected Logic Papers , New York: Random House.
  • Quine, W.V (1966b) Ways of Paradox , New York: Random House.
  • Quine, W.V. (1966c) “Russell's Ontological Development,” Journal of Philosophy , 63: 657–667. Repr. in Klemke, E.D., Essays on Bertrand Russell, Urbana, Chicago, London: University of Illinois Press, 3–14.
  • Ramsey, F.P. (1926) “Mathematical Logic,” Mathematical Gazette , 13: 185–194. Repr. in Ramsey, Frank Plumpton, The Foundations of Mathematics , London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1931, 62–81; in Ramsey, Frank Plumpton, Foundations , London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978, 213–232; and in Ramsey, Frank Plumpton, Philosophical Papers , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990, 225–244.
  • Roberts, George W. (ed.) (1979) Bertrand Russell Memorial Volume , London: Allen and Unwin.
  • Rodriguez-Consuegra, Francisco A. (1994) The Mathematical Philosophy of Bertrand Russell: Origins and Development , Basel: Birkhauser.
  • Ryan, Alan (1988) Bertrand Russell: A Political Life , New York: Hill and Wang.
  • Savage, C. Wade, and C. Anthony Anderson (eds) (1989) Rereading Russell: Essays on Bertrand Russell's Metaphysics and Epistemology , Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
  • Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.) (1944) The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell , Chicago: Northwestern University; 3rd ed., New York: Harper and Row, 1963.
  • Schoenman, Ralph (ed.) (1967) Bertrand Russell: Philosopher of the Century , London: Allen and Unwin.
  • Schultz, Bart (1992) “Bertrand Russell in Ethics and Politics,” Ethics , 102: 594–634.
  • Shapiro, Stewart (ed.) (2005) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Slater, John G. (1994) Bertrand Russell , Bristol: Thoemmes.
  • Strawson, Peter F. (1950) “On Referring,” Mind , 59: 320–344. Repr. in Flew, Anthony (ed.), Essays in Conceptual Analysis , London: Macmillan, 1960, 21–52, and in Klemke, E.D. (ed.), Essays on Bertrand Russell , Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1970, 147–172.
  • Tait, Katharine (1975) My Father Bertrand Russell , New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
  • Urquhart, Alasdair (1988) “Russell's Zig-Zag Path to the Ramified Theory of Types,” Russell , 8: 82–91.
  • Vellacott, Jo (1980) Bertrand Russell and the Pacifists in the First World War , Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press.
  • Weitz, Morris (1944) “Analysis and the Unity of Russell's Philosophy,” in Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.), The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell , 3rd ed., New York: Tudor, 1951, 55–121.
  • Williams, Roger (2007) What Is: Correcting the Logical Errors in Russell's Metaphysics, and the Metaphysical Errors in Predicate Logic , Glasgow: 347 Publications.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1921) Logisch-philosophische Abhandlung. Trans. as Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus , London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1922.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1956) Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Wood, Alan (1957) Bertrand Russell: The Passionate Sceptic , London: Allen and Unwin.
  • Bertrand Russell Archives
  • Bertrand Russell Gallery
  • Bertrand Russell Research Centre
  • Bertrand Russell Society
  • Bertrand Russell's Nobel Prize in Literature 1950
  • Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies
  • University of St Andrew's MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive: Bertrand Russell
  • Writings by Bertrand Russell

descriptions | Frege, Gottlob | Gödel, Kurt | knowledge: by acquaintance vs. description | logic: classical | logical atomism: Russell's | logical constructions | -->logicism and neologicism --> | mathematics, philosophy of | Moore, George Edward | neutral monism | Principia Mathematica | propositional function | Russell, Bertrand: moral philosophy | Russell's paradox | type theory | Whitehead, Alfred North | Wittgenstein, Ludwig

www.skeptic.ca

We will keep fighting for all libraries - stand with us!

Internet Archive Audio

bertrand russell essays

  • This Just In
  • Grateful Dead
  • Old Time Radio
  • 78 RPMs and Cylinder Recordings
  • Audio Books & Poetry
  • Computers, Technology and Science
  • Music, Arts & Culture
  • News & Public Affairs
  • Spirituality & Religion
  • Radio News Archive

bertrand russell essays

  • Flickr Commons
  • Occupy Wall Street Flickr
  • NASA Images
  • Solar System Collection
  • Ames Research Center

bertrand russell essays

  • All Software
  • Old School Emulation
  • MS-DOS Games
  • Historical Software
  • Classic PC Games
  • Software Library
  • Kodi Archive and Support File
  • Vintage Software
  • CD-ROM Software
  • CD-ROM Software Library
  • Software Sites
  • Tucows Software Library
  • Shareware CD-ROMs
  • Software Capsules Compilation
  • CD-ROM Images
  • ZX Spectrum
  • DOOM Level CD

bertrand russell essays

  • Smithsonian Libraries
  • FEDLINK (US)
  • Lincoln Collection
  • American Libraries
  • Canadian Libraries
  • Universal Library
  • Project Gutenberg
  • Children's Library
  • Biodiversity Heritage Library
  • Books by Language
  • Additional Collections

bertrand russell essays

  • Prelinger Archives
  • Democracy Now!
  • Occupy Wall Street
  • TV NSA Clip Library
  • Animation & Cartoons
  • Arts & Music
  • Computers & Technology
  • Cultural & Academic Films
  • Ephemeral Films
  • Sports Videos
  • Videogame Videos
  • Youth Media

Search the history of over 866 billion web pages on the Internet.

Mobile Apps

  • Wayback Machine (iOS)
  • Wayback Machine (Android)

Browser Extensions

Archive-it subscription.

  • Explore the Collections
  • Build Collections

Save Page Now

Capture a web page as it appears now for use as a trusted citation in the future.

Please enter a valid web address

  • Donate Donate icon An illustration of a heart shape

Philosophical essays

Bookreader item preview, share or embed this item, flag this item for.

  • Graphic Violence
  • Explicit Sexual Content
  • Hate Speech
  • Misinformation/Disinformation
  • Marketing/Phishing/Advertising
  • Misleading/Inaccurate/Missing Metadata

[WorldCat (this item)]

plus-circle Add Review comment Reviews

12,010 Views

40 Favorites

DOWNLOAD OPTIONS

For users with print-disabilities

IN COLLECTIONS

Uploaded by Alyson-Wieczorek on August 15, 2008

SIMILAR ITEMS (based on metadata)

bertrand russell essays

  • Politics & Social Sciences

Amazon prime logo

Enjoy fast, free delivery, exclusive deals, and award-winning movies & TV shows with Prime Try Prime and start saving today with fast, free delivery

Amazon Prime includes:

Fast, FREE Delivery is available to Prime members. To join, select "Try Amazon Prime and start saving today with Fast, FREE Delivery" below the Add to Cart button.

  • Cardmembers earn 5% Back at Amazon.com with a Prime Credit Card.
  • Unlimited Free Two-Day Delivery
  • Streaming of thousands of movies and TV shows with limited ads on Prime Video.
  • A Kindle book to borrow for free each month - with no due dates
  • Listen to over 2 million songs and hundreds of playlists
  • Unlimited photo storage with anywhere access

Important:  Your credit card will NOT be charged when you start your free trial or if you cancel during the trial period. If you're happy with Amazon Prime, do nothing. At the end of the free trial, your membership will automatically upgrade to a monthly membership.

Return this item for free

Free returns are available for the shipping address you chose. You can return the item for any reason in new and unused condition: no shipping charges

  • Go to your orders and start the return
  • Select the return method

Kindle app logo image

Download the free Kindle app and start reading Kindle books instantly on your smartphone, tablet, or computer - no Kindle device required .

Read instantly on your browser with Kindle for Web.

Using your mobile phone camera - scan the code below and download the Kindle app.

QR code to download the Kindle App

Follow the author

Bertrand Russell

Image Unavailable

Unpopular Essays (Routledge Classics)

  • To view this video download Flash Player

Unpopular Essays (Routledge Classics) 1st Edition

Purchase options and add-ons.

A classic collection of Bertrand Russell’s more controversial works, reaffirming his staunch liberal values, Unpopular Essays is one of Russell’s most characteristic and self-revealing books. Written to "combat… the growth in Dogmatism", on first publication in 1950 it met with critical acclaim and a wide readership and has since become one of his most accessible and popular books.

  • ISBN-10 0415473705
  • ISBN-13 978-0415473705
  • Edition 1st
  • Publisher Routledge
  • Publication date February 16, 2009
  • Language English
  • Dimensions 5.08 x 0.46 x 7.79 inches
  • Print length 200 pages
  • See all details

Amazon First Reads | Editors' picks at exclusive prices

Frequently bought together

Unpopular Essays (Routledge Classics)

Similar items that may deliver to you quickly

Sceptical Essays (Routledge Classics)

Editorial Reviews

‘An intellectual treat...the delight of this book lies in that combination of wit with perception, and of width of view with ease of expression for which Russell made himself known.’ - Financial Times

‘Russell is as incapable of being dull as he is of being shallow’ – The Observer

‘His writings reflect his crystalline, scintillating mind and rank him among the few masters of English style’ – Sunday Times

About the Author

Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) was one of the most formidable thinkers of the modern era. A philosopher, mathematician, educational innovator, champion of intellectual, social and sexual freedom, and a campaigner for peace and human rights, he was also a prolific writer of popular and influential books, essays and lectures on an extensive range of subjects.

Considered to be one of the most controversial figures of the twentieth century, Bertrand Russell is widely renowned for his provocative writings. These definitive works offer profound insights and forward-thinking perspectives on a changing western society progressively shaped, most significantly, by two world wars, the decline of British imperialism and an evolving moral landscape.

Product details

  • Publisher ‏ : ‎ Routledge; 1st edition (February 16, 2009)
  • Language ‏ : ‎ English
  • Paperback ‏ : ‎ 200 pages
  • ISBN-10 ‏ : ‎ 0415473705
  • ISBN-13 ‏ : ‎ 978-0415473705
  • Item Weight ‏ : ‎ 7.5 ounces
  • Dimensions ‏ : ‎ 5.08 x 0.46 x 7.79 inches
  • #408 in Epistemology Philosophy
  • #1,067 in Modern Western Philosophy
  • #2,187 in Philosophy of Ethics & Morality

About the author

Bertrand russell.

Bertrand Russell (1872 - 1970). Philosopher, mathematician, educational and sexual reformer, pacifist, prolific letter writer, author and columnist, Bertrand Russell was one of the most influential and widely known intellectual figures of the twentieth century. In 1950 he was awarded the Noble Prize for Literature in 1950 for his extensive contributions to world literature and for his "rationality and humanity, as a fearless champion of free speech and free thought in the West."

Photo by Photographer not identified (Bertrand Russell (1916). Justice in War-Time.) [Public domain], via Wikimedia Commons.

Customer reviews

Customer Reviews, including Product Star Ratings help customers to learn more about the product and decide whether it is the right product for them.

To calculate the overall star rating and percentage breakdown by star, we don’t use a simple average. Instead, our system considers things like how recent a review is and if the reviewer bought the item on Amazon. It also analyzed reviews to verify trustworthiness.

  • Sort reviews by Top reviews Most recent Top reviews

Top reviews from the United States

There was a problem filtering reviews right now. please try again later..

bertrand russell essays

Top reviews from other countries

bertrand russell essays

  • Amazon Newsletter
  • About Amazon
  • Accessibility
  • Sustainability
  • Press Center
  • Investor Relations
  • Amazon Devices
  • Amazon Science
  • Sell on Amazon
  • Sell apps on Amazon
  • Supply to Amazon
  • Protect & Build Your Brand
  • Become an Affiliate
  • Become a Delivery Driver
  • Start a Package Delivery Business
  • Advertise Your Products
  • Self-Publish with Us
  • Become an Amazon Hub Partner
  • › See More Ways to Make Money
  • Amazon Visa
  • Amazon Store Card
  • Amazon Secured Card
  • Amazon Business Card
  • Shop with Points
  • Credit Card Marketplace
  • Reload Your Balance
  • Amazon Currency Converter
  • Your Account
  • Your Orders
  • Shipping Rates & Policies
  • Amazon Prime
  • Returns & Replacements
  • Manage Your Content and Devices
  • Recalls and Product Safety Alerts
  • Conditions of Use
  • Privacy Notice
  • Consumer Health Data Privacy Disclosure
  • Your Ads Privacy Choices

bertrand russell essays

Bertrand Russell : The Conquest of Happiness, 1930 (Full Text)

bertrand russell essays

Part I: Causes of Unhappiness

Chapter 1: what makes people unhappy.

A mark in every face I meet, Marks of weakness, marks of woe,

Chapter 2: Byronic Unhappiness

There's not a joy the world can give like that it takes away, When the glow of early thought declines in feeling's dull decay.
Wherefore I praised the dead which are already dead more than the living which are yet alive. Yea, better is he than both they, which hath not yet been, who hath not seen the evil work that is done under the sun.
And I gave my heart to know wisdom, and to know madness and folly: I perceived that this also is vexation of spirit. For in much wisdom is much grief: and he that increaseth knowledge increaseth sorrow.
I said in mine heart, Go to now, I will prove thee with mirth, therefore enjoy pleasure: and, behold, this also is vanity.
Then said I in my heart, As it happeneth to the fool, so it happeneth even to me; and why was I then more wise.? Then I said in my heart, that this also is vanity.... Therefore I hated life; because the work that is wrought under the sun is grievous unto me: for all is vanity and vexation of spirit.
The rivers run into the sea; yet the sea is not full. There is no new thing under the sun. There is no remembrance of former things. I hated all my labour which I had taken under the sun: because I should leave it unto the man that shall be after me.
I warmed both hands before the fire; It sinks, and I am ready to depart.
'For the more skeptical of the Victorians, love performed some of the functions of the God whom they had lost. Faced with it, many of even the most hard-headed turned, for the moment, mystical. They found themselves in the presence of something which awoke in them that sense of reverence which nothing else claimed, and something to which they felt, even in the very depth of their being, that an unquestioning loyalty was due. For them love, like God, demanded all sacrifices; but like Him , also, it rewarded the believer by investing all the phenomena of life with a meaning not yet analysed away. We have grown used - more than they - to a Godless universe, but we are not yet accustomed to one which is loveless as well, and only when we have so become shall we realise what atheism really means.'
'Nobody can say anything against me, but I always say that it is not so bad to break the seventh commandment as the sixth, because at any rate it requires the consent of the other party.'
God be thanked, the meanest of His creatures Boasts two soul-sides, one to face the world with, One to show a woman when he loves her!
Oh Love! they wrong thee much That say thy sweet is bitter, When thy rich fruit is such As nothing can be sweeter.
True love is a durable fire, In the mind ever burning, Never sick, never dead, never cold, From itself never turning.
When beggars die, there are no comets seen; The heavens themselves blaze forth the death of princes.

Chapter 3: Competition

Chapter 4: boredom and excitement.

'My dear sir,' he would say, 'this chapter lacks pep; you can't expect your reader to be interested in a mere string of proper names of persons about whom you tell him so little. You have begun your story, I will admit, in fine style, and at first I was very favourably impressed, but you have altogether too much wish to tell it all. Pick out the highlights, take out the superfluous matter, and bring me back your manuscript when you have reduced it to a reasonable length.'

Chapter 5: Fatigue

bertrand russell essays

Chapter 6: Envy

'I must not imagine that my tail is better than that, for that would be conceit ed, but oh, how I wish it were! That odious bird is so convinced of his own magnificence! Shall I pull out some of his feathers? And then perhaps I need no longer fear comparison with him.'

Chapter 7: The sense of sin

Chapter 8: persecution mania, chapter 9: fear of public opinion.

The only man that e'er I knew Who did not make me almost spew Was Fuseli: he was both Turk and Jew. And so, dear Christian friends, how do you do?

Part II: Causes of happiness

Chapter 10: is happiness still possible, chapter 11: zest, chapter 12: affection, chapter 13: the family.

The only art her guilt to cover, To hide her shame from ev'ry eye, To give repentance to her lover And wring his bosom is - to die.
Upon Paul's steeple stands a tree As full of apples as may be, The little boys of London town They run with sticks to knock them down. And then they run from hedge to hedge Until they come to London Bridge.

IMAGES

  1. Philosophical Essays

    bertrand russell essays

  2. BERTRAND RUSSELL. Philosopher of the Century. Essays in His Honour by

    bertrand russell essays

  3. Unpopular Essays Introduction, Summary and Critical Stance

    bertrand russell essays

  4. Bertrand Russell, essays collection eBook : Russell, Bertrand : Amazon

    bertrand russell essays

  5. Philosophical Essays by Bertrand RUSSELL read by Landon D. C. Elkind

    bertrand russell essays

  6. Bertrand Russell: Unpopular Essays : Dr. S. Sen: Amazon.in: Books

    bertrand russell essays

VIDEO

  1. Bertrand Russell

  2. Prose Style of Bertrand Russell Unpopular Essays Hindi Urdu MA BS English Mk Bhutta

  3. Intellectual Rubbish by Bertrand Russell part 1/2

  4. Bertand Russell's BRILLIANT Advice To Future Generations

  5. THE FUTURE OF MANKIND by RUSSELL

  6. philosophy for Laymen by Bertrand Russell

COMMENTS

  1. Bertrand Russell

    Bertrand Russell (born May 18, 1872, Trelleck, Monmouthshire, Wales—died February 2, 1970, Penrhyndeudraeth, Merioneth) was a British philosopher, logician, and social reformer, a founding figure in the analytic movement in Anglo-American philosophy, and recipient of the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1950.

  2. Books and Articles by Bertrand Russell

    I. EARLY ESSAYS BY RUSSELL. These first essays, mostly book reviews, are Russell's earliest professional writings. ... "What I Have Lived For," Prologue to The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell (1967) V. RUSSELL'S BOOKS ON THE GREAT WAR, AND AFTER. Justice in War-Time (1916) Why Men Fight (1917) Political Ideals (1917)

  3. Bertrand Russell-two essays

    Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, 1872 - 1970 CE, was a British philosopher, writer, social critic and political activist.In the early 20th century, Russell led the British "revolt against idealism". He is considered one of the founders of analytic philosophy. Russell was an anti-war activist and went to prison for his pacifism during World War I.

  4. Bertrand Russell

    Bertrand Russell. Bertrand Arthur William Russell (1872-1970) was a British philosopher, logician, essayist and social critic best known for his work in mathematical logic and analytic philosophy. His most influential contributions include his championing of logicism (the view that mathematics is in some important sense reducible to logic ...

  5. Books by Russell, Bertrand (sorted by popularity)

    The Problem of China Bertrand Russell 1235 downloads. The Analysis of Mind Bertrand Russell 986 downloads. Modern Essays 675 downloads. Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays Bertrand Russell 603 downloads. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy Bertrand Russell 597 downloads. Proposed Roads to Freedom Bertrand Russell 539 downloads.

  6. In Praise of Idleness and Other Essays

    In Praise of Idleness and Other Essays is a 1935 collection of essays by the philosopher Bertrand Russell. Summary ... In the eponymous essay, Russell displays a series of arguments and reasoning with the aim of stating how the 'belief in the virtue of labour causes great evils in the modern world, and that the road to happiness and prosperity ...

  7. PDF The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell

    The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell - Emil O W Kirkegaard

  8. Bertrand Russell

    Bertrand Russell. First published Thu Dec 7, 1995; substantive revision Thu May 1, 2003. Bertrand Arthur William Russell (b.1872 - d.1970) was a British philosopher, logician, essayist, and social critic, best known for his work in mathematical logic and analytic philosophy. His most influential contributions include his defense of logicism ...

  9. The Project Gutenberg eBook of Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, by

    Project Gutenberg's Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, by Bertrand Russell This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org Title: Mysticism and ...

  10. Bertrand Russell

    Liberal (1907-1922) Signature. Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, OM, FRS [7] (18 May 1872 - 2 February 1970) was a British mathematician, logician, philosopher, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic philosophy.

  11. Bertrand Russell

    The Nobel Prize in Literature 1950 was awarded to Earl (Bertrand Arthur William) Russell "in recognition of his varied and significant writings in which he champions humanitarian ideals and freedom of thought" ... Philosophical Essays, 1910 (with Dr. A. N. Whitehead) Principia mathematica, 3 vols, 1910-13:

  12. In Praise of Idleness, by Bertrand Russell

    by Bertrand Russell. L IKE most of my generation, I was brought up on the saying "Satan finds some mischief still for idle hands to do.". Being a highly virtuous child, I believed all that I was told and acquired a conscience which has kept me working hard down to the present moment. But although my conscience has controlled my actions, my ...

  13. Why I Am Not a Christian

    Dutch edition book cover of Why I Am Not a Christian. Why I Am Not a Christian is an essay by the British philosopher Bertrand Russell.Originally a talk given on 6 March 1927 at Battersea Town Hall, under the auspices of the South London Branch of the National Secular Society, it was published that year as a pamphlet and has been republished several times in English and in translation.

  14. Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays by Bertrand Russell

    Russell, Bertrand, 1872-1970. Title. Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays. Credits. Produced by Jeannie Howse, Adrian Mastronardi and the. Online Distributed Proofreading Team at http: //www.pgdp.net. (This file was produced from images generously made. available by The Internet Archive/Canadian Libraries)

  15. Bertrand Russell

    Bertrand Arthur William Russell (b.1872 - d.1970) was a British philosopher, logician, essayist and social critic best known for his work in mathematical logic and analytic philosophy. ... (1876) Death of father; Russell's grandfather, Lord John Russell (the former Prime Minister), and grandmother succeed in overturning Russell's father's ...

  16. PDF A Free Man's Worship

    by Bertrand Russell. A brief introduction: "A Free Man's Worship" (first published as "The Free Man's Worship" in Dec. 1903) is perhaps Bertrand Russell's best known and most reprinted essay. Its mood and language have often been explained, even by Russell himself, as reflecting a particular time in his life; "it depend(s)," he wrote in 1929 ...

  17. The basic writings of Bertrand Russell : 1903-1959

    Selections from his autobiography, popular essays, works on philosophy, psychology, history, mathematics, and international relations ... Chronology of the life of Bertrand Russell -- Acknowledgements -- Some thoughts about Bertrand Russell -- pt. I. Autobiographical asides. 1, My religious reminiscences. 2, My mental development. 3, Adaptation ...

  18. Philosophical essays : Russell, Bertrand, 1872-1970 : Free Download

    Philosophical essays Bookreader Item Preview ... Philosophical essays by Russell, Bertrand, 1872-1970. Publication date 1910 Topics Philosophy Publisher London ; New York : Longmans, Green Collection cdl; americana Contributor University of California Libraries Language English.

  19. On Denoting

    On Denoting. " On Denoting " is an essay by Bertrand Russell. It was published in the philosophy journal Mind in 1905. In it, Russell introduces and advocates his theory of denoting phrases, according to which definite descriptions and other "denoting phrases ... never have any meaning in themselves, but every proposition in whose verbal ...

  20. Unpopular Essays (Routledge Classics): Russell, Bertrand: 9780415473705

    Unpopular Essays (Routledge Classics) 1st Edition. A classic collection of Bertrand Russell's more controversial works, reaffirming his staunch liberal values, Unpopular Essays is one of Russell's most characteristic and self-revealing books. Written to "combat… the growth in Dogmatism", on first publication in 1950 it met with critical ...

  21. Bertrand Russell

    Bertrand Russell's American Essays, v.1 The Aurobiography of Bertrand Russell Religion and Science, 1935 (full text) Power, a new social analysis, 1938 (full text) Bertrand Russell: The Triumph of Stupidity Bertrand Russell's Vocaburaries Bertrand Russell Quotes 366 with images _ _ e-texts of Bertrand Russell's writings _ _ Preface

  22. Unpopular Essays

    Unpopular Essays. Bertrand Russell. Psychology Press, 1995 - Philosophy - 190 pages. In this volume of essays Russell is concerned to combat, in one way or another, the growth of dogmatism, whether of the Left or of the Right, which has hitherto characterised our tragic century.