Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction & Top Questions

Dating, editing, translation

  • Dialogue form
  • Happiness and virtue
  • Linguistic and philosophical background
  • Forms as perfect exemplars
  • Forms as genera and species
  • Early dialogues
  • Middle dialogues
  • Late dialogues

Plato

What did Plato do?

What is plato known for, what were plato’s contributions to society, when was plato alive, what was plato’s family like.

Plato (left) and Aristotle, detail from School of Athens, fresco by Raphael, 1508-11; in the Stanza della Segnatura, the Vatican. Plato points to the heavens and the realm of Forms, Aristotle to the earth and the realm of things.

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • The Basic of Philosophy - Plato
  • World History Encyclopedia - Plato
  • Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Plato (427–347 BC)
  • The University of British Columbia - Department of Physics & Astronomy - Biography of Plato
  • Great Thinkers - Plato
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Biography of Plato
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Biograpfy of Plato
  • Plato - Children's Encyclopedia (Ages 8-11)
  • Plato - Student Encyclopedia (Ages 11 and up)
  • Table Of Contents

Plato was a philosopher during the 5th century BCE. He was a student of Socrates and later taught Aristotle . He founded the Academy , an academic program which many consider to be the first Western university. Plato wrote many philosophical texts—at least 25. He dedicated his life to learning and teaching and is hailed as one of the founders of Western philosophy .

Plato’s most famous work is the Republic , which details a wise society run by a philosopher. He is also famous for his dialogues (early, middle, and late), which showcase his metaphysical theory of forms—something else he is well known for. Plato also founded the Academy , an academic program that many consider to be the first Western university, where he stressed the importance of science and mathematics . Because of this, he became known as the “maker of mathematicians.”

Plato is one of history's most influential philosophers. His contributions range across numerous philosophical subfields, including (but not limited to) ethics , cosmology , and metaphysics . Though he was not a scientist in the modern sense, Plato also examined the natural world and the philosophical implications it held.

Plato was born in 428/427 BCE to a noble family and died in 348/347 BCE. He lived primarily in Athens , Greece . Plato’s birth occurred near the end of the Golden Age of Athens, and he grew up during the Peloponnesian War . He reached adulthood around the time of Sparta ’s final defeat of Athens. After traveling, Plato spent the remainder of his life teaching at the Academy until his death in 348/347 BCE.

Plato did not have children, and it is assumed based on textual evidence that he never married. He did have a number of siblings, however: three brothers, Glaucon, Antiphon, and Adeimantus of Collytus, and one sister, Potone. His father, Ariston of Athens, died when he was young, and his mother, Perictione, remarried with her uncle Pyrilampes.

Plato (born 428/427 bce , Athens , Greece—died 348/347, Athens) was an ancient Greek philosopher , student of Socrates (c. 470–399 bce ), teacher of Aristotle (384–322 bce ), and founder of the Academy . He is best known as the author of philosophical works of unparalleled influence and is one of the major figures of Classical antiquity .

Building on the demonstration by Socrates that those regarded as experts in ethical matters did not have the understanding necessary for a good human life, Plato introduced the idea that their mistakes were due to their not engaging properly with a class of entities he called forms , chief examples of which were Justice , Beauty, and Equality. Whereas other thinkers—and Plato himself in certain passages—used the term without any precise technical force, Plato in the course of his career came to devote specialized attention to these entities. As he conceived them, they were accessible not to the senses but to the mind alone, and they were the most important constituents of reality, underlying the existence of the sensible world and giving it what intelligibility it has. In metaphysics Plato envisioned a systematic, rational treatment of the forms and their interrelations, starting with the most fundamental among them ( the Good , or the One); in ethics and moral psychology he developed the view that the good life requires not just a certain kind of knowledge (as Socrates had suggested) but also habituation to healthy emotional responses and therefore harmony between the three parts of the soul (according to Plato, reason , spirit, and appetite). His works also contain discussions in aesthetics , political philosophy , theology , cosmology , epistemology , and the philosophy of language . His school fostered research not just in philosophy narrowly conceived but in a wide range of endeavours that today would be called mathematical or scientific.

The son of Ariston (his father) and Perictione (his mother), Plato was born in the year after the death of the great Athenian statesman Pericles . His brothers Glaucon and Adeimantus are portrayed as interlocutors in Plato’s masterpiece the Republic , and his half brother Antiphon figures in the Parmenides . Plato’s family was aristocratic and distinguished: his father’s side claimed descent from the god Poseidon , and his mother’s side was related to the lawgiver Solon (c. 630–560 bce ). Less creditably, his mother’s close relatives Critias and Charmides were among the Thirty Tyrants who seized power in Athens and ruled briefly until the restoration of democracy in 403.

Plato as a young man was a member of the circle around Socrates . Since the latter wrote nothing, what is known of his characteristic activity of engaging his fellow citizens (and the occasional itinerant celebrity) in conversation derives wholly from the writings of others, most notably Plato himself. The works of Plato commonly referred to as “Socratic” represent the sort of thing the historical Socrates was doing. He would challenge men who supposedly had expertise about some facet of human excellence to give accounts of these matters—variously of courage, piety, and so on, or at times of the whole of “virtue”—and they typically failed to maintain their position. Resentment against Socrates grew, leading ultimately to his trial and execution on charges of impiety and corrupting the youth in 399. Plato was profoundly affected by both the life and the death of Socrates. The activity of the older man provided the starting point of Plato’s philosophizing. Moreover, if Plato’s Seventh Letter is to be believed (its authorship is disputed), the treatment of Socrates by both the oligarchy and the democracy made Plato wary of entering public life, as someone of his background would normally have done.

Agathon (centre) greeting guests in Plato's Symposium, oil on canvas by Anselm Feuerbach, 1869; in the Staatliche Kunsthalle, Karlsruhe, Germany.

After the death of Socrates, Plato may have traveled extensively in Greece , Italy , and Egypt , though on such particulars the evidence is uncertain. The followers of Pythagoras (c. 580–c. 500 bce ) seem to have influenced his philosophical program (they are criticized in the Phaedo and the Republic but receive respectful mention in the Philebus ). It is thought that his three trips to Syracuse in Sicily (many of the Letters concern these, though their authenticity is controversial) led to a deep personal attachment to Dion (408–354 bce ), brother-in-law of Dionysius the Elder (430–367 bce ), the tyrant of Syracuse. Plato, at Dion’s urging , apparently undertook to put into practice the ideal of the “philosopher-king” (described in the Republic ) by educating Dionysius the Younger ; the project was not a success, and in the ensuing instability Dion was murdered.

Plato’s Academy , founded in the 380s, was the ultimate ancestor of the modern university (hence the English term academic ); an influential centre of research and learning, it attracted many men of outstanding ability. The great mathematicians Theaetetus (417–369 bce ) and Eudoxus of Cnidus (c. 395–c. 342 bce ) were associated with it. Although Plato was not a research mathematician, he was aware of the results of those who were, and he made use of them in his own work. For 20 years Aristotle was also a member of the Academy. He started his own school, the Lyceum , only after Plato’s death, when he was passed over as Plato’s successor at the Academy, probably because of his connections to the court of Macedonia.

plato mathematician biography

Because Aristotle often discusses issues by contrasting his views with those of his teacher, it is easy to be impressed by the ways in which they diverge. Thus, whereas for Plato the crown of ethics is the good in general, or Goodness itself (the Good), for Aristotle it is the good for human beings; and whereas for Plato the genus to which a thing belongs possesses a greater reality than the thing itself, for Aristotle the opposite is true. Plato’s emphasis on the ideal, and Aristotle’s on the worldly, informs Raphael ’s depiction of the two philosophers in the School of Athens (1508–11). But if one considers the two philosophers not just in relation to each other but in the context of the whole of Western philosophy , it is clear how much Aristotle’s program is continuous with that of his teacher. (Indeed, the painting may be said to represent this continuity by showing the two men conversing amicably.) In any case, the Academy did not impose a dogmatic orthodoxy and in fact seems to have fostered a spirit of independent inquiry; at a later time it took on a skeptical orientation.

Plato once delivered a public lecture, “On the Good,” in which he mystified his audience by announcing, “ the Good is one.” He better gauged his readers in his dialogues , many of which are accessible, entertaining, and inviting. Although Plato is well known for his negative remarks about much great literature , in the Symposium he depicts literature and philosophy as the offspring of lovers, who gain a more lasting posterity than do parents of mortal children. His own literary and philosophical gifts ensure that something of Plato will live on for as long as readers engage with his works.

Plato’s works are traditionally arranged in a manner deriving from Thrasyllus of Alexandria (flourished 1st century ce ): 36 works (counting the Letters as one) are divided into nine groups of four. But the ordering of Thrasyllus makes no sense for a reader today. Unfortunately, the order of composition of Plato’s works cannot be known. Conjecture regarding chronology has been based on two kinds of consideration: perceived development in content and “stylometry,” or the study of special features of prose style, now executed with the aid of computers. By combining the two kinds of consideration, scholars have arrived at a widely used rough grouping of works, labeled with the traditional designations of early, middle, and late dialogues . These groups can also be thought of as the Socratic works (based on the activities of the historical Socrates), the literary masterpieces, and the technical studies ( see below Works individually described ).

Each of Plato’s dialogues has been transmitted substantially as he left it. However, it is important to be aware of the causal chain that connects modern readers to Greek authors of Plato’s time. To survive until the era of printing, an ancient author’s words had to be copied by hand, and the copies had to be copied, and so on over the course of centuries—by which time the original would have long perished. The copying process inevitably resulted in some corruption, which is often shown by disagreement between rival manuscript traditions.

Even if some Platonic “urtext” had survived, however, it would not be anything like what is published in a modern edition of Plato’s works. Writing in Plato’s time did not employ word divisions and punctuation or the present-day distinction between capital and lowercase letters. These features represent the contributions of scholars of many generations and countries, as does the ongoing attempt to correct for corruption. (Important variant readings and suggestions are commonly printed at the bottom of each page of text, forming the apparatus criticus .) In the great majority of cases only one decision is possible, but there are instances—some of crucial importance—where several courses can be adopted and where the resulting readings have widely differing import. Thus, the preparation of an edition of Plato’s works involves an enormous interpretive component. The work of the translator imports another layer of similar judgments. Some Greek sentences admit of several fundamentally different grammatical construals with widely differing senses, and many ancient Greek words have no neat English equivalents.

A notable artifact of the work of translators and scholars is a device of selective capitalization sometimes employed in English. To mark the objects of Plato’s special interest, the forms, some follow a convention in which one capitalizes the term Form (or Idea ) as well as the names of particular forms, such as Justice, the Good , and so on. Others have employed a variant of this convention in which capitalization is used to indicate a special way in which Plato is supposed to have thought of the forms during a certain period (i.e., as “separate” from sensible particulars, the nature of this separation then being the subject of interpretative controversy). Still others do not use capital letters for any such purpose. Readers will do best to keep in mind that such devices are in any case only suggestions.

In recent centuries there have been some changes in the purpose and style of English translations of ancient philosophy. The great Plato translation by Benjamin Jowett (1817–93), for example, was not intended as a tool of scholarship; anyone who would undertake such a study already knew ancient Greek. Instead, it made Plato’s corpus generally accessible in English prose of considerable merit. At the other extreme was a type of translation that aimed to be useful to serious students and professional philosophers who did not know Greek; its goal was to indicate as clearly as possible the philosophical potentialities of the text, however much readability suffered in consequence. Exemplars of this style, which was much in vogue in the second half of the 20th century, are the series published by the Clarendon Press and also, in a different tradition, the translations undertaken by followers of Leo Strauss (1899–1973). Except in a few cases, however, the gains envisioned by this notion of fidelity proved to be elusive .

Despite, but also because of, the many factors that mediate the contemporary reader’s access to Plato’s works, many dialogues are conveyed quite well in translation. This is particularly true of the short, Socratic dialogues. In the case of works that are large-scale literary masterpieces, such as the Phaedrus , a translation of course cannot match the artistry of the original. Finally, because translators of difficult technical studies such as the Parmenides and the Sophist must make basic interpretive decisions in order to render any English at all, reading their work is very far from reading Plato. In the case of these dialogues, familiarity with commentaries and other secondary literature and a knowledge of ancient Greek are highly desirable.

logo white

  • Mathematicians
  • Math Lessons
  • Square Roots
  • Math Calculators
  • PLATO – THE ATHENIAN PHILOSOPHER

PLATO – THE ATHENIAN PHILOSOPHER

Biography: what was plato known for.

Plato (c.428-348 BCE)

Although usually remembered today as a philosopher, Plato was also one of ancient Greece’s most important patrons of mathematics . Inspired by Pythagoras , he founded his Academy in Athens in 387 BCE, where he stressed mathematics as a way of understanding more about reality. In particular, he was convinced that geometry was the key to unlocking the secrets of the universe. The sign above the Academy entrance read: “Let no-one ignorant of geometry enter here”.

Plato played an important role in encouraging and inspiring Greek intellectuals to study mathematics as well as philosophy. His Academy taught mathematics as a branch of philosophy, as Pythagoras had done, and the first 10 years of the 15 year course at the Academy involved the study of science and mathematics, including plane and solid geometry, astronomy and harmonics. Plato became known as the “maker of mathematicians”, and his Academy boasted some of the most prominent mathematicians of the ancient world, including Eudoxus, Theaetetus and Archytas.

He demanded of his students accurate definitions, clearly stated assumptions, and logical deductive proof, and he insisted that geometric proofs be demonstrated with no aids other than a straight edge and a compass. Among the many mathematical problems Plato posed for his students’ investigation were the so-called Three Classical Problems (“squaring the circle”, “doubling the cube” and “trisecting the angle”) and to some extent these problems have become identified with Plato, although he was not the first to pose them.

Platonic Solids

Platonic Solids

Plato the mathematician is perhaps best known for his identification of 5 regular symmetrical 3-dimensional shapes, which he maintained were the basis for the whole universe, and which have become known as the Platonic Solids : the tetrahedron (constructed of 4 regular triangles, and which for Plato represented fire), the octahedron (composed of 8 triangles, representing air), the icosahedron (composed of 20 triangles, and representing water), the cube (composed of 6 squares, and representing earth), and the dodecahedron (made up of 12 pentagons, which Plato obscurely described as “ the god used for arranging the constellations on the whole heaven ”).

The tetrahedron, cube and dodecahedron were probably familiar to Pythagoras , and the octahedron and icosahedron were probably discovered by Theaetetus, a contemporary of Plato. Furthermore, it fell to Euclid , half a century later, to prove that these were the only possible convex regular polyhedra. But they nevertheless became popularly known as the Platonic Solids, and inspired mathematicians and geometers for many centuries to come. For example, around 1600, the German astronomer Johannes Kepler devised an ingenious system of nested Platonic solids and spheres to approximate quite well the distances of the known planets from the Sun (although he was enough of a scientist to abandon his elegant model when it proved to be not accurate enough).





Ancient Greek philosopher Plato founded the Academy and is the author of philosophical works of unparalleled influence in Western thought.

plato

Who Was Plato?

Ancient Greek philosopher Plato was a student of Socrates and a teacher of Aristotle. His writings explored justice, beauty and equality, and also contained discussions in aesthetics, political philosophy, theology, cosmology, epistemology and the philosophy of language. Plato founded the Academy in Athens, one of the first institutions of higher learning in the Western world.

Due to a lack of primary sources from the time period, much of Plato's life has been constructed by scholars through his writings and the writings of contemporaries and classical historians. Traditional history estimates Plato's birth was around 428 B.C.E., but more modern scholars, tracing later events in his life, believe he was born between 424 and 423 B.C.E. Both of his parents came from the Greek aristocracy. Plato's father, Ariston, descended from the kings of Athens and Messenia. His mother, Perictione, is said to be related to the 6th century B.C.E. Greek statesman Solon.

Some scholars believe that Plato was named for his grandfather, Aristocles, following the tradition of the naming the eldest son after the grandfather. But there is no conclusive evidence of this, or that Plato was the eldest son in his family. Other historians claim that "Plato" was a nickname, referring to his broad physical build. This too is possible, although there is record that the name Plato was given to boys before Aristocles was born.

As with many young boys of his social class, Plato was probably taught by some of Athens' finest educators. The curriculum would have featured the doctrines of Cratylus and Pythagoras as well as Parmenides. These probably helped develop the foundation for Plato's study of metaphysics (the study of nature) and epistemology (the study of knowledge).

Plato's father died when he was young, and his mother remarried her uncle, Pyrilampes, a Greek politician and ambassador to Persia. Plato is believed to have had two full brothers, one sister and a half brother, though it is not certain where he falls in the birth order. Often, members of Plato's family appeared in his dialogues. Historians believe this is an indication of Plato's pride in his family lineage.

As a young man, Plato experienced two major events that set his course in life. One was meeting the great Greek philosopher Socrates. Socrates's methods of dialogue and debate impressed Plato so much that he soon he became a close associate and dedicated his life to the question of virtue and the formation of a noble character. The other significant event was the Peloponnesian War between Athens and Sparta, in which Plato served for a brief time between 409 and 404 B.C.E. The defeat of Athens ended its democracy, which the Spartans replaced with an oligarchy. Two of Plato's relatives, Charmides and Critias, were prominent figures in the new government, part of the notorious Thirty Tyrants whose brief rule severely reduced the rights of Athenian citizens. After the oligarchy was overthrown and democracy was restored, Plato briefly considered a career in politics, but the execution of Socrates in 399 B.C.E. soured him on this idea and he turned to a life of study and philosophy.

After Socrates's death, Plato traveled for 12 years throughout the Mediterranean region, studying mathematics with the Pythagoreans in Italy, and geometry, geology, astronomy and religion in Egypt. During this time, or soon after, he began his extensive writing. There is some debate among scholars on the order of these writings, but most believe they fall into three distinct periods.

Early, Middle and Late Periods: An Overview

The first, or early, period occurs during Plato's travels (399-387 B.C.E.). The Apology of Socrates seems to have been written shortly after Socrates's death. Other texts in this time period include Protagoras , Euthyphro , Hippias Major and Minor and Ion . In these dialogues, Plato attempts to convey Socrates's philosophy and teachings.

In the second, or middle, period, Plato writes in his own voice on the central ideals of justice, courage, wisdom and moderation of the individual and society. The Republic was written during this time with its exploration of just government ruled by philosopher kings.

In the third, or late, period, Socrates is relegated to a minor role and Plato takes a closer look at his own early metaphysical ideas. He explores the role of art, including dance, music, drama and architecture, as well as ethics and morality. In his writings on the Theory of Forms, Plato suggests that the world of ideas is the only constant and that the perceived world through our senses is deceptive and changeable.

Founding the Academy

Sometime around 385 B.C.E., Plato founded a school of learning, known as the Academy, which he presided over until his death. It is believed the school was located at an enclosed park named for a legendary Athenian hero. The Academy operated until 529 C.E.., when it was closed by Roman Emperor Justinian I, who feared it was a source of paganism and a threat to Christianity. Over its years of operation, the Academy's curriculum included astronomy, biology, mathematics, political theory and philosophy. Plato hoped the Academy would provide a place for future leaders to discover how to build a better government in the Greek city-states.

In 367 B.C.E., Plato was invited by Dion, a friend and disciple, to be the personal tutor of his nephew, Dionysius II, the new ruler of Syracuse (Sicily). Dion believed that Dionysius showed promise as an ideal leader. Plato accepted, hoping the experience would produce a philosopher king. But Dionysius fell far short of expectations and suspected Dion, and later Plato, of conspiring against him. He had Dion exiled and Plato placed under "house arrest." Eventually, Plato returned to Athens and his Academy. One of his more promising students there was Aristotle, who would take his mentor's teachings in new directions.

Final Years and Death

Plato's final years were spent at the Academy and with his writing. The circumstances surrounding his death are clouded, though it is fairly certain that he died in Athens around 348 B.C.E., when he was in his early 80s. Some scholars suggest that he died while attending a wedding, while others believe he died peacefully in his sleep.

Plato's impact on philosophy and the nature of humans has had a lasting impact far beyond his homeland of Greece. His work covered a broad spectrum of interests and ideas: mathematics, science and nature, morals and political theory. His beliefs on the importance of mathematics in education have proven to be essential for understanding the entire universe. His work on the use of reason to develop a more fair and just society that is focused on the equality of individuals established the foundation for modern democracy.

QUICK FACTS

  • Birth Year: 428
  • Birth City: Athens
  • Birth Country: Greece
  • Gender: Male
  • Best Known For: Ancient Greek philosopher Plato founded the Academy and is the author of philosophical works of unparalleled influence in Western thought.
  • Education and Academia
  • Nationalities
  • Death Year: 348
  • Death City: Athens
  • Death Country: Greece

We strive for accuracy and fairness. If you see something that doesn't look right, contact us !

  • All the gold which is under or upon the earth is not enough to give in exchange for virtue.
  • Attention to health is life's greatest hindrance.
  • Courage is knowing what not to fear.
  • Dictatorship naturally arises out of democracy, and the most aggravated form of tyranny and slavery out of the most extreme liberty.
  • Good actions give strength to ourselves and inspire good actions in others.

preview for Biography Scholars & Educators Playlist

Philosophers

noam chomsky smiles and looks past the camera, he wears glasses, a black suit jacket, a blue collared shirt and a blue and white sweater

Noam Chomsky

marcus garvey

Marcus Garvey

john locke

Francis Bacon

auguste comte

Auguste Comte

charles louis de secondat

Charles-Louis de Secondat

saint thomas aquinas

Saint Thomas Aquinas

john dewey

William James

john stuart mill

John Stuart Mill

jean paul sartre

Jean-Paul Sartre

Plato Biography

Birthday: May 21 , 428 BC ( Gemini )

Born In: Classical Athens, Greece

Plato

Recommended For You

Aristotle Biography

Died At Age: 79

father: Ariston, Ariston of Athens

mother: Perictione

siblings: Adeimantus of Collytus, Antiphon, Glaucon, Potone

Born Country: Greece

Philosophers Greek Men

Died on: 348 BC

place of death: Athens, Greece

You wanted to know

What is plato known for.

Plato was a renowned Greek philosopher and the founder of the Academy in Athens. He is best known for his philosophical dialogues and his contributions to the fields of ethics, metaphysics, epistemology, and political theory.

What are Plato's most famous works?

Some of Plato's most famous works include "The Republic," "Symposium," "Phaedo," "Phaedrus," and "Apology." These dialogues cover a wide range of philosophical topics and continue to be studied and analyzed to this day.

What is Plato's theory of Forms?

Plato's theory of Forms posits that there exists a higher realm of abstract entities, or Forms, which are the true reality behind the physical world we perceive. These Forms are perfect and unchanging ideals that serve as the ultimate source of all existence and knowledge.

What is Plato's allegory of the cave?

Plato's allegory of the cave is a metaphorical story found in his work "The Republic." It describes a group of prisoners who are chained inside a cave, facing a wall and only able to see shadows of objects cast by a fire behind them. The allegory serves as an illustration of the journey from ignorance to enlightenment and the importance of philosophical education.

What was Plato's view on democracy?

Plato was critical of democracy in his work "The Republic." He believed that democracy could easily devolve into tyranny if left unchecked, as it often prioritizes the desires of the masses over the pursuit of wisdom and justice. Plato favored a form of government led by philosopher-kings who would rule with wisdom and virtue.

Recommended Lists:

Plato was believed to have been a skilled wrestler in his youth, showcasing his physical prowess alongside his intellectual capabilities.

Plato had a pet peacock, which was considered a rare and exotic pet in ancient Greece, reflecting his appreciation for unique and beautiful things.

Plato was a talented poet and wrote several poems in his lifetime, revealing his creative side beyond his philosophical works.

See the events in life of Plato in Chronological Order

Sharma, V.

How To Cite

People Also Viewed

Aristotle Biography

Also Listed In

© Famous People All Rights Reserved

Famous Philosophers

Biography, Facts and Works

Plato Picture

Plato was a classical Greek philosopher and mathematician, influencing the realm of Western philosophy. He remained a diligent disciple of Socrates , and along with Socrates and his renowned student Aristotle , he found the first higher learning academy in Athens. Plato’s philosophy is heavily influenced by Socrates, Parmenides , Heraclitus and Pythagoras. It deals with the ideas of morality, observation, reality, love and sexuality.

Plato was so inspired by his teacher Socrates, that his early writings are accurate reports of his master’s words, conveyed to the reader in the form of dialogues. These early dialogues are presented as questions and answers, and each tackle a sole vital issue. His writing Euthyphro questions whether morally correct actions are approved divinely. In Apology , Plato puts forward Socrates’ version of how to lead a philosophical life, as presented by him to the jury of Athens. The Crito debates whether a citizen of a state is ever correct about disobeying the rules of the state.

By the time Plato presented his middle works, he developed a distinct thought process of his own, which is evident by the main character’s representation of Plato himself, as opposed to Socrates being the main character earlier. He interconnects politics, metaphysics, epistemology, morality, psychology and a myriad of issues to present an intricate philosophy of his own. The middle dialogues also include his famous work Republic in which he denounces various forms of arts, and says that arts and poetry merely replicates reality and creates overwhelming feelings. In Meno Plato discusses whether goodness can be taught, and that no one intends to act wrongly. The  Phaedo lays down the principles of Plato’s famous Doctrine of the Forms, which claims that human soul is imperishable.

The later writings of Plato gave up the shape of dialogues. They examined in detail the Theory of Forms, knowledge and cosmology, and political discussion about a state’s rules and regulations in his works titled Parmenides, Theaetetus, Timaeus and Laws .

In many of Plato’s dialogues, Socrates suggested that the world perceived by us is not real, it is a mere deception created by our senses. The form of the real world can only be reached through reason. This real world of forms is unseen and unchangeable, while what we observe is constantly under change. This is Plato’s Theory of Forms.

He often discusses the father-son relationship in his philosophical works. He looked down upon those fathers who spent lavishly on tutoring their sons, as he believed that knowledge and goodness is a divine gift, which cannot be taught. It can only be polished.

Similarly, he presents Socrates’ idea of knowledge being a recollection of memories, not observation or studying. He stresses on the notion that knowledge cannot be gained through inspection alone, when one lacks deep insight. Plato also discusses at length his views on immortality and afterlife. He also compares phenomena such as knowledge and opinion, reality and observation.

The famous notion of ‘Platonic love’ is his idea that when lovers resort to physical pleasures, their love will not achieve higher form of divine beauty, which Plato calls the ‘Beauty Itself’. He often presents lovers as each other’s halves, and says that love alone is heavenly madness, a state where the lover can achieve the highest aspirations humanly possible. Keeping this view, Plato thought that people give up the true power of love by limiting themselves to mere physical beauty and its few pleasures.

The profound notions and questions put forward by him have dazzled readers of all ages, religions and places. Without a doubt, Plato has remained one of the most influential and widely-read thinkers throughout the history of philosophy.

Buy books by Plato

plato mathematician biography

  • John Searle
  • John Stuart Mill
  • Jonathan Edwards
  • Judith Butler
  • Julia Kristeva
  • Jürgen Habermas
  • Karl Jaspers
  • Lucien Goldmann
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein
  • Marcus Aurelius
  • Mario Bunge
  • Martha Nussbaum
  • Martin Buber
  • Martin Heidegger
  • Mary Wollstonecraft
  • Max Scheler
  • Max Stirner
  • Meister Eckhart
  • Michel Foucault
  • Miguel De Unamuno
  • Niccolò Machiavelli
  • Nick Bostrom
  • Noam Chomsky
  • Peter Singer
  • René Descartes
  • Robert Nozick
  • Roland Barthes
  • Rosa Luxemburg
  • Rudolf Steiner
  • Sigmund Freud
  • Simone De Beauvoir
  • Simone Weil
  • Søren Kierkegaard
  • Theodor Adorno
  • Thomas Aquinas
  • Thomas Hobbes
  • Thomas Jefferson
  • Thomas Kühn
  • U.G. Krishnamurti
  • Walter Benjamin
  • Wilhelm Reich
  • William James
  • William Lane Craig
  • Alain de Benoist
  • Alan Turing
  • Albert Camus
  • Albertus Magnus
  • Arthur Schopenhauer
  • Auguste Comte
  • Baruch Spinoza
  • Bertrand Russell
  • Cesare Beccaria
  • Charles Sanders Peirce
  • Daniel Dennett
  • Edmund Burke
  • Edmund Husserl
  • Emile Durkheim
  • Emma Goldman
  • Francis Bacon
  • Friedrich Engels
  • Friedrich Hayek
  • Friedrich Nietzsche
  • George Berkeley
  • George Herbert Mead
  • George Santayana
  • Georges Bataille
  • Gilles Deleuze
  • Giordano Bruno
  • Gottfried Leibniz
  • Hannah Arendt
  • Henry David Thoreau
  • Hildegard Of Bingen
  • Immanuel Kant
  • Iris Murdoch
  • Jacques Derrida
  • Jacques Lacan
  • Jean Baudrillard
  • Jean Jacques Rousseau
  • Jean-Paul Sartre
  • Jeremy Bentham
  • Jiddu Krishnamurti

Biography Online

Biography

Plato Biography

plato

“The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.”

Alfred North Whitehead

Early life of Plato

The early life of Plato is only partially recorded, but he was born in 428/427 BCE to an aristocratic family in Athens. His father’s side claimed descent from the god Poseidon and the last kings of Athens. Some sources suggest that his real name was Aristocles, and that ‘Plato’ was a nickname given to him later in life. Plato roughly translates as the ‘broad’ It may have been a reflection of the breadth of interests that Plato considered.

He was given a good education, and he soon impressed those around him with his speed of learning and clarity of thought. He was also drawn to the philosopher Socrates . Socrates was a great and independent thinker who gathered a group of young men to talk and discuss philosophy. Plato was deeply impressed by the personality, spirit and philosophic detachment of his mentor Socrates. As Plato writes:

“Oh dear Pan and all the other Gods of this place, grant that I may be beautiful inside.  Let all my external possessions be in friendly harmony with what is within.  May I consider the wise man rich.  As for gold, let me have as much as a moderate man could bear and carry with him.”

– Plato, “Phaedrus” – a prayer of Socrates, as portrayed in the dialogue.

Plato was deeply hurt after Socrates’ trial in 399 BC where he was condemned for ‘corrupting the youth of Athens’ and sentenced to death – being forced to drink hemlock. After the death of Socrates, Plato left Athens, disgusted with the mob-mentality of Athenian democracy. He travelled widely around the Meditteranean region, visiting Greece, Italy and Egypt. He came into contact with followers of Pythagoras and he was influenced by some of their philosophic ideas.

Relationship with Socrates

Socrates appears in most of Plato’s writings, and it is clear that Socrates and his Socratic dialogues had a big influence on Plato’s own writing and style of teaching.

It is only through Plato, that we get a clear idea of Socrates’ philosophy and way of life. In ‘ Apology of Socrates ‘ , Plato writes an account of Socrates defending himself in a trial which ultimately led to his own death. It presents Socrates as a model philosopher, calmly putting the ideals of justice above any personal desire.

“It would be better for me … that multitudes of men should disagree with me rather than that I, being one, should be out of harmony with myself.”

Plato (Words spoken by Socrates,) “The Gorgias”

However, Plato was not merely transcribing the words of Socrates; he was also using his own interpretations and ideas to those which he learned from him.

Plato Academy

The_School_of_Athens__by_Raffaello_Sanzio_da_Urbino

The School of Athens by Raffael. Plato and Aristotle are depicted together

In the 380s, Plato returned to Athens where he founded “The Academy” a school of learning, philosophy and research. It was a pioneer of future universities and became a magnet for the leading minds of the time. The polymath Aristotle spent 20 years at Plato’s Academy and further heightened its reputation. It was at the Academy that Plato wrote his great works and taught a range of students.

Plato’s Central Doctrines

Plato-raphael

Plato in the Academy picture

Plato wrote on a whole range of topics, but it is his ethics and general philosophy which seemed to be his biggest interest. Plato was fundamentally a rationalist who felt the role of philosophy was to help people to live a good life. He sought to make sense of the world through reason and empiricism and he used this basic approach to a range of different topics. On metaphysics, he saw a distinction between the body (corporeal world) and the soul. To Plato, the soul could become captive to the material desires of the body, and to gain lasting happiness, the higher-wisdom of the soul and mind should be in control of a man’s lower passions.

“The inexperienced in wisdom and virtue, ever occupied with feasting and such, are carried downward, and there, as is fitting, they wander their whole life long, neither ever looking upward to the truth above them nor rising toward it, nor tasting pure and lasting pleasures.” – Plato, “The Republic”

Plato also saw a distinction between the imperfection of the material world and the highest ideals which transcend material imperfections. Plato felt that someone of a ‘philosophic mind’ could differentiate between outward limitations and the highest ideals of beauty, truth, unity and justice. It is a philosophy which hints at the limitations of the material and the mental world and encourages an aspiration to higher ideals.

“I only wish that wisdom were the kind of thing that flowed … from the vessel that was full to the one that was empty.” – Plato, “The Symposium”

He also mentions that the life we live is based on previous choices in either this incarnation or previous incarnations. Plato’s philosophy was also heavily influenced by Pythagoras , especially his religious views on transmigration.

In Politics , Plato developed the idea of a ‘Philosopher King’ someone who would be a wisdom lover and develop the necessary qualities to rule over his people with wisdom and justice. This may have partly been a reaction to the demographic democracy he saw in Athens and a hesitation to rely on the ‘wisdom of the crowds,’ that prevailed in Athens at the time. He made the analogy that the philosopher-king was like a ship’s captain or doctor. Someone who knows best what his patient needs.

“Until philosophers rule as kings or those who are now called kings and leading men genuinely and adequately philosophise, that is, until political power and philosophy entirely coincide, while the many natures who at present pursue either one exclusively are forcibly prevented from doing so, cities will have no rest from evils,… nor, I think, will the human race.” ( Republic 473c-d)

To guard against philosopher-kings becoming tyrants, Plato also stated that they should be subject to the rule of law that limits the ruler’s actions

Style of Teaching

Plato didn’t write treatises and lectures, but wrote in an indirect way, encouraging the reader to ask questions and think for himself. Inspired by Socrates, he makes use of informal conversation and humorous anecdote. Like his teacher Socrates, Plato was happy to play the role of observer rather than a preacher. There is also signs of development and changes in thought, though some of this is due to uncertainty over whether letters ascribed to Plato, were actually written by him.

Plato and Aristotle

Aristotle didn’t agree with many conclusions of his teacher. For example, Aristotle felt the soul was an intrinsic part of the body. However, although Aristotle disagreed with Plato in some regards, he revered him as a supreme authority and person. His esteem for Plato was so great that he felt it would be “Blasphemy in the extreme even to praise him.” After Plato’s death, Aristotle started his own school – The Lyceum.

Death of Plato

There are conflicting reports on the death of Plato. But, he died between the ages of 81 and 84, and so was long-lived by ancient standards.

Citation: Pettinger, Tejvan . “Biography of Plato”, Oxford, UK. www.biographyonline.net , Originally published 26 February 2012. Last updated 8 March 2020.

Plato Quotes

“Be kind, for everyone you meet is fighting a harder battle.”
“Every heart sings a song, incomplete, until another heart whispers back. Those who wish to sing always find a song. At the touch of a lover, everyone becomes a poet.”
“We can easily forgive a child who is afraid of the dark; the real tragedy of life is when men are afraid of the light.”
“One of the penalties of refusing to participate in politics is that you end up being governed by your inferiors.”
“I am the wisest man alive, for I know one thing, and that is that I know nothing.”

― Plato, The Republic

“There are three classes of men; lovers of wisdom, lovers of honor, and lovers of gain.”

Plato: Complete Works

Book Cover

Plato: Complete Works at Amazon

Related pages

einstein

Related people

web analytics

plato mathematician biography

History >> Ancient Greece >> Biography

  • Occupation: Philosopher and Mathematician
  • Born: 427 BC in Athens, Greece
  • Died: 347 BC in Athens, Greece
  • Best known for: Greek philosopher who helped form the foundation of Western philosophy and founded the Academy in Athens.
  • Plato's real name may have been Aristocles after his father. Plato might have been a nickname that meant "broad" or "wide."
  • He was related to the famous lawmaker and poet Solon through his mother.
  • After Athens lost the Peloponnesian War to Sparta, Plato was offered to be one of the "Thirty Tyrants" that ruled over Athens, but he declined.
  • Plato was also heavily influenced by the mathematician and philosopher Pythagoras.
  • Listen to a recorded reading of this page:



























































plato mathematician biography

  • History Classics
  • Your Profile
  • Find History on Facebook (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on Twitter (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on YouTube (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on Instagram (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on TikTok (Opens in a new window)
  • This Day In History
  • History Podcasts
  • History Vault

By: History.com Editors

Updated: June 16, 2023 | Original: November 9, 2009

Detail, Raphael's Vatican fresco 'School of Athens' featuring Plato and Aristotle

The Athenian philosopher Plato (c. 428-347 B.C.) is one of the most important figures of the Ancient Greek world and the entire history of Western thought. In his written dialogues he conveyed and expanded on the ideas and techniques of his teacher Socrates. 

The Academy he founded was by some accounts the world’s first university and in it he trained his greatest student, the equally influential philosopher Aristotle. Plato’s recurring fascination was the distinction between ideal forms and everyday experience, and how it played out both for individuals and for societies. In the “Republic,” his most famous work, he envisioned a civilization governed not by lowly appetites but by the pure wisdom of a philosopher-king.

Plato: Early Life and Education

Plato was born around 428 B.C., during the final years of the Golden Age of Pericles’ Athens. He was of noble Athenian lineage on both sides. His father Ariston died when Plato was a child. His mother Perictione remarried the politician Pyrilampes. Plato grew up during the Peloponnesian War (431-404) and came of age around the time of Athens’ final defeat by Sparta and the political chaos that followed. He was educated in philosophy, poetry and gymnastics by distinguished Athenian teachers including the philosopher Cratylus.

Plato's Influences

The young Plato became a devoted follower of Socrates—indeed, he was one of the youths Socrates was condemned for allegedly corrupting. Plato’s recollections of Socrates’ lived-out philosophy and style of relentless questioning, the Socratic method, became the basis for his early dialogues. Plato’s dialogues, along with “Apologia,” his written account of the trial of Socrates, are viewed by historians as the most accurate available picture of the elder philosopher, who left no written works of his own.

Following Socrates’ forced suicide, Plato spent 12 years traveling in southern Italy, Sicily and Egypt, studying with other philosophers including followers of the mystic mathematician Pythagoras including Theodorus of Cyrene (creator of the spiral of Theodorus or Pythagorean spiral), Archytas of Tarentum and Echecrates of Phlius. Plato’s time among the Pythagoreans piqued his interest in mathematics.

Plato’s Theory of Forms, stating that the physical world we know is but a shadow of the real one, was strongly influenced by Parmenides and Zeno of Elea. The two appear as characters in Plato’s dialogue “The Parmenides.”

Plato had a lifelong relationship with the ruling family of Syracuse, who would later seek his advice on reforming their city’s politics.

Platonic Academy

Around 387, the 40-year-old Plato returned to Athens and founded his philosophical school in the grove of the Greek hero Academus, just outside the city walls. In his open-air Academy he delivered lectures to students gathered from throughout the Greek world (nine-tenths of them from outside Athens). 

Did you know? The section on music in Plato's "Republic" suggests that in an ideal society flutes would be banned in favor of the more dignified lyre, but on his deathbed Plato reportedly summoned a young girl to play her flute for him, tapping out the rhythm with his finger while he breathed his last.

Many of Plato’s writings, especially the so-called later dialogues, seem to have originated in his teaching there. In establishing the Academy Plato moved beyond the precepts of Socrates, who never founded a school and questioned the very idea of a teacher’s ability to impart knowledge.

Aristotle arrived from northern Greece to join the Academy at age 17, studying and teaching there for the last 20 years of Plato’s life. Plato died in Athens, and was probably buried on the Academy grounds.

Plato's Dialogues

With the exception of a set of letters of dubious provenance, all of Plato’s surviving writings are in dialogue form, with the character of Socrates appearing in all but one of them. His 36 dialogues are generally ordered into early, middle and late, though their chronology is determined by style and content rather than specific dates. 

The earliest of Plato’s dialogues offer a deep exploration of Socrates’ dialectic method of breaking down and analyzing ideas and presumptions. In the “Euthpyro,” Socrates’ endless questioning pushes a religious expert to realize that he has no understanding of what “piety” means. Such analyses pushed his students towards grappling with so-called Platonic forms—the ineffable perfect models (truth, beauty, what a chair should look like) by which people judge objects and experiences. 

In the middle dialogues, Plato’s individual ideas and beliefs, though never advocated outright, emerge from the Socratic form. The “Symposium” is a series of drinking-party speeches on the nature of love, in which Socrates says the best thing to do with romantic desire is to convert it into amicable truth-seeking (an idea termed “Platonic love” by later writers). In the “Meno,” Socrates demonstrates that wisdom is less a matter of learning things than “recollecting” what the soul already knows, in the way that an untaught boy can be led to discover for himself a geometric proof. 

The monumental “Republic” is a parallel exploration of the soul of a nation and of an individual. In both, Plato finds a three-part hierarchy between rulers, auxiliaries and citizens and between reason, emotion and desire. Just as reason should reign supreme in the individual, so should a wise ruler control a society. 

Only those with wisdom (ideally a sort of “philosopher-king”) are able to discern the true nature of things. The experiences of the lower tiers of the state and of the soul are—as Plato’s famous analogy has it—related to true knowledge the way the shadows on the wall of a cave are related to, yet wholly different from, the forms that cast them. 

Plato’s late dialogues are barely dialogues at all but rather explorations of specific topics. The “Timeaus” explains a cosmology intertwined with geometry, in which perfected three-dimensional shapes—cubes, pyramids, icosahedrons—are the “Platonic solids” out of which the whole universe is made. In the “Laws,” his final dialogue, Plato retreats from the pure theory of the “Republic,” suggesting that experience and history as well as wisdom can inform the running of an ideal state. 

Plato Quotes 

Plato is credited with coining several phrases that are still popular today. Here are some of Plato’s most famous quotes: 

· “Love is a serious mental disease.” 

· “When the mind is thinking it is talking to itself.”

 · “Wise men talk because they have something to say; fools, because they have to say something.” 

· “Music is a moral law. It gives soul to the universe, wings to the mind, flight to the imagination, and charm and gaiety to life and to everything.” 

· “One of the penalties for refusing to participate in politics is that you end up being governed by your inferiors.” 

· “Man-a being in search of meaning.” 

· “Every heart sings a song, incomplete, until another heart whispers back. Those who wish to sing always find a song. At the touch of lover, everyone becomes a poet.” 

· “There are two things a person should never be angry at: What they can help, and what they cannot.” 

· “People are like dirt. They can either nourish you and help you grow as a person or they can stunt your growth and make you wilt and die.” 

Plato: Legacy and Influence 

The Academy flourished for nearly three centuries following Plato’s death, but was destroyed in the sacking of Athens by the Roman general Sulla in 86 B.C. Though continually read in the  Byzantine Empire  and in the Islamic world, Plato was overshadowed by Aristotle in the Christian west. 

It was only in the Renaissance that scholars like Petrarch led a revival of Plato’s thought, in particular his explorations of logic and geometry. William Wordsworth, Percy Shelly and others in the 19th-century Romantic movement found philosophical solace in Plato’s dialogues.

plato mathematician biography

HISTORY Vault: Ancient History

From the Sphinx of Egypt to the Kama Sutra, explore ancient history videos.

plato mathematician biography

Sign up for Inside History

Get HISTORY’s most fascinating stories delivered to your inbox three times a week.

By submitting your information, you agree to receive emails from HISTORY and A+E Networks. You can opt out at any time. You must be 16 years or older and a resident of the United States.

More details : Privacy Notice | Terms of Use | Contact Us

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Plato (429?–347 B.C.E.) is, by any reckoning, one of the most dazzling writers in the Western literary tradition and one of the most penetrating, wide-ranging, and influential authors in the history of philosophy. An Athenian citizen of high status, he displays in his works his absorption in the political events and intellectual movements of his time, but the questions he raises are so profound and the strategies he uses for tackling them so richly suggestive and provocative that educated readers of nearly every period have in some way been influenced by him, and in practically every age there have been philosophers who count themselves Platonists in some important respects. He was not the first thinker or writer to whom the word “philosopher” should be applied. But he was so self-conscious about how philosophy should be conceived, and what its scope and ambitions properly are, and he so transformed the intellectual currents with which he grappled, that the subject of philosophy, as it is often conceived—a rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political, metaphysical, and epistemological issues, armed with a distinctive method—can be called his invention. Few other authors in the history of Western philosophy approximate him in depth and range: perhaps only Aristotle (who studied with him), Aquinas, and Kant would be generally agreed to be of the same rank.

1. Plato’s central doctrines

2. plato’s puzzles, 3. dialogue, setting, character, 4. socrates, 5. plato’s indirectness, 6. can we know plato’s mind, 7. socrates as the dominant speaker, 8. links between the dialogues, 9. does plato change his mind about forms, 10. does plato change his mind about politics, 11. the historical socrates: early, middle, and late dialogues, 12. why dialogues, primary literature, secondary literature, other internet resources, related entries.

Many people associate Plato with a few central doctrines that are advocated in his writings: The world that appears to our senses is in some way defective and filled with error, but there is a more real and perfect realm, populated by entities (called “forms” or “ideas”) that are eternal, changeless, and in some sense paradigmatic for the structure and character of the world presented to our senses. Among the most important of these abstract objects (as they are now called, because they are not located in space or time) are goodness, beauty, equality, bigness, likeness, unity, being, sameness, difference, change, and changelessness. (These terms—“goodness”, “beauty”, and so on—are often capitalized by those who write about Plato, in order to call attention to their exalted status; similarly for “Forms” and “Ideas.”) The most fundamental distinction in Plato’s philosophy is between the many observable objects that appear beautiful (good, just, unified, equal, big) and the one object that is what beauty (goodness, justice, unity) really is, from which those many beautiful (good, just, unified, equal, big) things receive their names and their corresponding characteristics. Nearly every major work of Plato is, in some way, devoted to or dependent on this distinction. Many of them explore the ethical and practical consequences of conceiving of reality in this bifurcated way. We are urged to transform our values by taking to heart the greater reality of the forms and the defectiveness of the corporeal world. We must recognize that the soul is a different sort of object from the body—so much so that it does not depend on the existence of the body for its functioning, and can in fact grasp the nature of the forms far more easily when it is not encumbered by its attachment to anything corporeal. In a few of Plato’s works, we are told that the soul always retains the ability to recollect what it once grasped of the forms, when it was disembodied prior to its possessor’s birth (see especially Meno ), and that the lives we lead are to some extent a punishment or reward for choices we made in a previous existence (see especially the final pages of Republic ). But in many of Plato’s writings, it is asserted or assumed that true philosophers—those who recognize how important it is to distinguish the one (the one thing that goodness is, or virtue is, or courage is) from the many (the many things that are called good or virtuous or courageous )—are in a position to become ethically superior to unenlightened human beings, because of the greater degree of insight they can acquire. To understand which things are good and why they are good (and if we are not interested in such questions, how can we become good?), we must investigate the form of good.

Although these propositions are often identified by Plato’s readers as forming a large part of the core of his philosophy, many of his greatest admirers and most careful students point out that few, if any, of his writings can accurately be described as mere advocacy of a cut-and-dried group of propositions. Often Plato’s works exhibit a certain degree of dissatisfaction and puzzlement with even those doctrines that are being recommended for our consideration. For example, the forms are sometimes described as hypotheses (see for example Phaedo ). The form of good in particular is described as something of a mystery whose real nature is elusive and as yet unknown to anyone at all ( Republic ). Puzzles are raised—and not overtly answered—about how any of the forms can be known and how we are to talk about them without falling into contradiction ( Parmenides ), or about what it is to know anything ( Theaetetus ) or to name anything ( Cratylus ). When one compares Plato with some of the other philosophers who are often ranked with him—Aristotle, Aquinas, and Kant, for example—he can be recognized to be far more exploratory, incompletely systematic, elusive, and playful than they. That, along with his gifts as a writer and as a creator of vivid character and dramatic setting, is one of the reasons why he is often thought to be the ideal author from whom one should receive one’s introduction to philosophy. His readers are not presented with an elaborate system of doctrines held to be so fully worked out that they are in no need of further exploration or development; instead, what we often receive from Plato is a few key ideas together with a series of suggestions and problems about how those ideas are to be interrogated and deployed. Readers of a Platonic dialogue are drawn into thinking for themselves about the issues raised, if they are to learn what the dialogue itself might be thought to say about them. Many of his works therefore give their readers a strong sense of philosophy as a living and unfinished subject (perhaps one that can never be completed) to which they themselves will have to contribute. All of Plato’s works are in some way meant to leave further work for their readers, but among the ones that most conspicuously fall into this category are: Euthyphro , Laches , Charmides , Euthydemus , Theaetetus , and Parmenides .

There is another feature of Plato’s writings that makes him distinctive among the great philosophers and colors our experience of him as an author. Nearly everything he wrote takes the form of a dialogue. (There is one striking exception: his Apology , which purports to be the speech that Socrates gave in his defense—the Greek word apologia means “defense”—when, in 399, he was legally charged and convicted of the crime of impiety. However, even there, Socrates is presented at one point addressing questions of a philosophical character to his accuser, Meletus, and responding to them. In addition, since antiquity, a collection of 13 letters has been included among his collected works, but their authenticity as compositions of Plato is not universally accepted among scholars, and many or most of them are almost certainly not his (see Burnyeat and Frede 2015). Most of them purport to be the outcome of his involvement in the politics of Syracuse, a heavily populated Greek city located in Sicily and ruled by tyrants.)

We are of course familiar with the dialogue form through our acquaintance with the literary genre of drama. But Plato’s dialogues do not try to create a fictional world for the purposes of telling a story, as many literary dramas do; nor do they invoke an earlier mythical realm, like the creations of the great Greek tragedians Aeschylus, Sophocles, and Euripides. Nor are they all presented in the form of a drama: in many of them, a single speaker narrates events in which he participated. They are philosophical discussions—“debates” would, in some cases, also be an appropriate word—among a small number of interlocutors, many of whom can be identified as real historical figures (see Nails 2002); and often they begin with a depiction of the setting of the discussion—a visit to a prison, a wealthy man’s house, a celebration over drinks, a religious festival, a visit to the gymnasium, a stroll outside the city’s wall, a long walk on a hot day. As a group, they form vivid portraits of a social world, and are not purely intellectual exchanges between characterless and socially unmarked speakers. (At any rate, that is true of a large number of Plato’s interlocutors. However, it must be added that in some of his works the speakers display little or no character. See, for example, Sophist and Statesman —dialogues in which a visitor from the town of Elea in Southern Italy leads the discussion; and Laws , a discussion between an unnamed Athenian and two named fictional characters, one from Crete and the other from Sparta.) In many of his dialogues (though not all), Plato is not only attempting to draw his readers into a discussion, but is also commenting on the social milieu that he is depicting, and criticizing the character and ways of life of his interlocutors (see Blondell 2002). Some of the dialogues that most evidently fall into this category are Protagoras , Gorgias , Hippias Major , Euthydemus , and Symposium .

There is one interlocutor who speaks in nearly all of Plato’s dialogues, being completely absent only in Laws , which ancient testimony tells us was one of his latest works: that figure is Socrates. Like nearly everyone else who appears in Plato’s works, he is not an invention of Plato: there really was a Socrates just as there really was a Crito, a Gorgias, a Thrasymachus, and a Laches. Plato was not the only author whose personal experience of Socrates led to the depiction of him as a character in one or more dramatic works. Socrates is one of the principal characters of Aristophanes’ comedy, Clouds ; and Xenophon, a historian and military leader, wrote, like Plato, both an Apology of Socrates (an account of Socrates’ trial) and other works in which Socrates appears as a principal speaker. Furthermore, we have some fragmentary remains of dialogues written by other contemporaries of Socrates besides Plato and Xenophon (Aeschines, Antisthenes, Eucleides, Phaedo), and these purport to describe conversations he conducted with others (see Boys-Stone and Rowe 2013). So, when Plato wrote dialogues that feature Socrates as a principal speaker, he was both contributing to a genre that was inspired by the life of Socrates and participating in a lively literary debate about the kind of person Socrates was and the value of the intellectual conversations in which he was involved. Aristophanes’ comic portrayal of Socrates is at the same time a bitter critique of him and other leading intellectual figures of the day (the 420s B.C.), but from Plato, Xenophon, and the other composers (in the 390’s and later) of “Socratic discourses” (as Aristotle calls this body of writings) we receive a far more favorable impression.

Evidently, the historical Socrates was the sort of person who provoked in those who knew him, or knew of him, a profound response, and he inspired many of those who came under his influence to write about him. But the portraits composed by Aristophanes, Xenophon, and Plato are the ones that have survived intact, and they are therefore the ones that must play the greatest role in shaping our conception of what Socrates was like. Of these, Clouds has the least value as an indication of what was distinctive of Socrates’ mode of philosophizing: after all, it is not intended as a philosophical work, and although it may contain a few lines that are characterizations of features unique to Socrates, for the most part it is an attack on a philosophical type—the long-haired, unwashed, amoral investigator into abstruse phenomena—rather than a depiction of Socrates himself. Xenophon’s depiction of Socrates, whatever its value as historical testimony (which may be considerable), is generally thought to lack the philosophical subtlety and depth of Plato’s. At any rate, no one (certainly not Xenophon himself) takes Xenophon to be a major philosopher in his own right; when we read his Socratic works, we are not encountering a great philosophical mind. But that is what we experience when we read Plato. We may read Plato’s Socratic dialogues because we are (as Plato evidently wanted us to be) interested in who Socrates was and what he stood for, but even if we have little or no desire to learn about the historical Socrates, we will want to read Plato because in doing so we are encountering an author of the greatest philosophical significance. No doubt he in some way borrowed in important ways from Socrates, though it is not easy to say where to draw the line between him and his teacher (more about this below in section 12). But it is widely agreed among scholars that Plato is not a mere transcriber of the words of Socrates (any more than Xenophon or the other authors of Socratic discourses). His use of a figure called “Socrates” in so many of his dialogues should not be taken to mean that Plato is merely preserving for a reading public the lessons he learned from his teacher.

Socrates, it should be kept in mind, does not appear in all of Plato’s works. He makes no appearance in Laws , and there are several dialogues ( Sophist , Statesman , Timaeus ) in which his role is small and peripheral, while some other figure dominates the conversation or even, as in the Timaeus and Critias , presents a long and elaborate, continuous discourse of their own. Plato’s dialogues are not a static literary form; not only do his topics vary, not only do his speakers vary, but the role played by questions and answers is never the same from one dialogue to another. ( Symposium , for example, is a series of speeches, and there are also lengthy speeches in Apology , Menexenus , Protagoras , Crito , Phaedrus , Timaeus , and Critias ; in fact, one might reasonably question whether these works are properly called dialogues). But even though Plato constantly adapted “the dialogue form” (a commonly used term, and convenient enough, so long as we do not think of it as an unvarying unity) to suit his purposes, it is striking that throughout his career as a writer he never engaged in a form of composition that was widely used in his time and was soon to become the standard mode of philosophical address: Plato never became a writer of philosophical treatises, even though the writing of treatises (for example, on rhetoric, medicine, and geometry) was a common practice among his predecessors and contemporaries. (The closest we come to an exception to this generalization is the seventh letter, which contains a brief section in which the author, Plato or someone pretending to be him, commits himself to several philosophical points—while insisting, at the same time, that no philosopher will write about the deepest matters, but will communicate his thoughts only in private discussion with selected individuals. As noted above, the authenticity of Plato’s letters is a matter of great controversy; and in any case, the author of the seventh letter declares his opposition to the writing of philosophical books. Whether Plato wrote it or not, it cannot be regarded as a philosophical treatise, and its author did not wish it to be so regarded.) In all of his writings—except in the letters, if any of them are genuine—Plato never speaks to his audience directly (see Frede 1992) and in his own voice. Strictly speaking, he does not himself affirm anything in his dialogues; rather, it is the interlocutors in his dialogues who are made by Plato to do all of the affirming, doubting, questioning, arguing, and so on. Whatever he wishes to communicate to us is conveyed indirectly.

This feature of Plato’s works raises important questions about how they are to be read, and has led to considerable controversy among those who study his writings. Since he does not himself affirm anything in any of his dialogues, can we ever be on secure ground in attributing a philosophical doctrine to him (as opposed to one of his characters)? Did he himself have philosophical convictions, and can we discover what they were? Are we justified in speaking of “the philosophy of Plato”? Or, if we attribute some view to Plato himself, are we being unfaithful to the spirit in which he intended the dialogues to be read? Is his whole point, in refraining from writing treatises, to discourage the readers of his works from asking what their author believes and to encourage them instead simply to consider the plausibility or implausibility of what his characters are saying? Is that why Plato wrote dialogues? If not for this reason, then what was his purpose in refraining from addressing his audience in a more direct way (see Griswold 1988, Klagge and Smith 1992, Press 2002)? There are other important questions about the particular shape his dialogues take: for example, why does Socrates play such a prominent role in so many of them, and why, in some of these works, does Socrates play a smaller role, or none at all?

Once these questions are raised and their difficulty acknowledged, it is tempting, in reading Plato’s works and reflecting upon them, to adopt a strategy of extreme caution. Rather than commit oneself to any hypothesis about what he is trying to communicate to his readers, one might adopt a stance of neutrality about his intentions, and confine oneself to talking only about what is said by his dramatis personae . One cannot be faulted, for example, if one notes that, in Plato’s Republic , Socrates argues that justice in the soul consists in each part of the soul doing its own. It is equally correct to point out that other principal speakers in that work, Glaucon and Adeimantus, accept the arguments that Socrates gives for that definition of justice. Perhaps there is no need for us to say more—to say, for example, that Plato himself agrees that this is how justice should be defined, or that Plato himself accepts the arguments that Socrates gives in support of this definition. And we might adopt this same “minimalist” approach to all of Plato’s works. After all, is it of any importance to discover what went on inside his head as he wrote—to find out whether he himself endorsed the ideas he put in the mouths of his characters, whether they constitute “the philosophy of Plato”? Should we not read his works for their intrinsic philosophical value, and not as tools to be used for entering into the mind of their author? We know what Plato’s characters say—and isn’t that all that we need, for the purpose of engaging with his works philosophically?

But the fact that we know what Plato’s characters say does not show that by refusing to entertain any hypotheses about what the author of these works is trying to communicate to his readers we can understand what those characters mean by what they say. We should not lose sight of this obvious fact: it is Plato, not any of his dramatis personae , who is reaching out to a readership and trying to influence their beliefs and actions by means of his literary actions. When we ask whether an argument put forward by a character in Plato’s works should be read as an effort to persuade us of its conclusion, or is better read as a revelation of how foolish that speaker is, we are asking about what Plato as author (not that character) is trying to lead us to believe, through the writing that he is presenting to our attention. We need to interpret the work itself to find out what it, or Plato the author, is saying. Similarly, when we ask how a word that has several different senses is best understood, we are asking what Plato means to communicate to us through the speaker who uses that word. We should not suppose that we can derive much philosophical value from Plato’s writings if we refuse to entertain any thoughts about what use he intends us to make of the things his speakers say. Penetrating the mind of Plato and comprehending what his interlocutors mean by what they say are not two separate tasks but one, and if we do not ask what his interlocutors mean by what they say, and what the dialogue itself indicates we should think about what they mean, we will not profit from reading his dialogues.

Furthermore, the dialogues have certain characteristics that are most easily explained by supposing that Plato is using them as vehicles for inducing his readers to become convinced (or more convinced than they already are) of certain propositions—for example, that there are forms, that the soul is not corporeal, that knowledge can be acquired only by means of a study of the forms, and so on. Why, after all, did Plato write so many works (for example: Phaedo , Symposium , Republic , Phaedrus , Theaetetus , Sophist , Statesman , Timaeus , Philebus , Laws ) in which one character dominates the conversation (often, but not always, Socrates) and convinces the other speakers (at times, after encountering initial resistance) that they should accept or reject certain conclusions, on the basis of the arguments presented? The only plausible way of answering that question is to say that these dialogues were intended by Plato to be devices by which he might induce the audience for which they are intended to reflect on and accept the arguments and conclusions offered by his principal interlocutor. (It is noteworthy that in Laws , the principal speaker—an unnamed visitor from Athens—proposes that laws should be accompanied by “preludes” in which their philosophical basis is given as full an explanation as possible. The educative value of written texts is thus explicitly acknowledged by Plato’s dominant speaker. If preludes can educate a whole citizenry that is prepared to learn from them, then surely Plato thinks that other sorts of written texts—for example, his own dialogues—can also serve an educative function.)

This does not mean that Plato thinks that his readers can become wise simply by reading and studying his works. On the contrary, it is highly likely that he wanted all of his writings to be supplementary aids to philosophical conversation: in one of his works, he has Socrates warn his readers against relying solely on books, or taking them to be authoritative. They are, Socrates says, best used as devices that stimulate the readers’ memory of discussions they have had ( Phaedrus 274e-276d). In those face-to-face conversations with a knowledgeable leader, positions are taken, arguments are given, and conclusions are drawn. Plato’s writings, he implies in this passage from Phaedrus , will work best when conversational seeds have already been sown for the arguments they contain.

If we take Plato to be trying to persuade us, in many of his works, to accept the conclusions arrived at by his principal interlocutors (or to persuade us of the refutations of their opponents), we can easily explain why he so often chooses Socrates as the dominant speaker in his dialogues. Presumably the contemporary audience for whom Plato was writing included many of Socrates’ admirers. They would be predisposed to think that a character called “Socrates” would have all of the intellectual brilliance and moral passion of the historical person after whom he is named (especially since Plato often makes special efforts to give his “Socrates” a life-like reality, and has him refer to his trial or to the characteristics by which he was best known); and the aura surrounding the character called “Socrates” would give the words he speaks in the dialogue considerable persuasive power. Furthermore, if Plato felt strongly indebted to Socrates for many of his philosophical techniques and ideas, that would give him further reason for assigning a dominant role to him in many of his works. (More about this in section 12.)

Of course, there are other more speculative possible ways of explaining why Plato so often makes Socrates his principal speaker. For example, we could say that Plato was trying to undermine the reputation of the historical Socrates by writing a series of works in which a figure called “Socrates” manages to persuade a group of naïve and sycophantic interlocutors to accept absurd conclusions on the basis of sophistries. But anyone who has read some of Plato’s works will quickly recognize the utter implausibility of that alternative way of reading them. Plato could have written into his works clear signals to the reader that the arguments of Socrates do not work, and that his interlocutors are foolish to accept them. But there are many signs in such works as Meno , Phaedo , Republic , and Phaedrus that point in the opposite direction. (And the great admiration Plato feels for Socrates is also evident from his Apology .) The reader is given every encouragement to believe that the reason why Socrates is successful in persuading his interlocutors (on those occasions when he does succeed) is that his arguments are powerful ones. The reader, in other words, is being encouraged by the author to accept those arguments, if not as definitive then at least as highly arresting and deserving of careful and full positive consideration. When we interpret the dialogues in this way, we cannot escape the fact that we are entering into the mind of Plato, and attributing to him, their author, a positive evaluation of the arguments that his speakers present to each other.

There is a further reason for entertaining hypotheses about what Plato intended and believed, and not merely confining ourselves to observations about what sorts of people his characters are and what they say to each other. When we undertake a serious study of Plato, and go beyond reading just one of his works, we are inevitably confronted with the question of how we are to link the work we are currently reading with the many others that Plato composed. Admittedly, many of his dialogues make a fresh start in their setting and their interlocutors: typically, Socrates encounters a group of people many of whom do not appear in any other work of Plato, and so, as an author, he needs to give his readers some indication of their character and social circumstances. But often Plato’s characters make statements that would be difficult for readers to understand unless they had already read one or more of his other works. For example, in Phaedo (73a-b), Socrates says that one argument for the immortality of the soul derives from the fact that when people are asked certain kinds of questions, and are aided with diagrams, they answer in a way that shows that they are not learning afresh from the diagrams or from information provided in the questions, but are drawing their knowledge of the answers from within themselves. That remark would be of little worth for an audience that had not already read Meno . Several pages later, Socrates tells his interlocutors that his argument about our prior knowledge of equality itself (the form of equality) applies no less to other forms—to the beautiful, good, just, pious and to all the other things that are involved in their asking and answering of questions (75d). This reference to asking and answering questions would not be well understood by a reader who had not yet encountered a series of dialogues in which Socrates asks his interlocutors questions of the form, “What is X?” ( Euthyphro : what is piety? Laches : what is courage? Charmides : What is moderation? Hippias Major : what is beauty? see Dancy 2004). Evidently, Plato is assuming that readers of Phaedo have already read several of his other works, and will bring to bear on the current argument all of the lessons that they have learned from them. In some of his writings, Plato’s characters refer ahead to the continuation of their conversations on another day, or refer back to conversations they had recently: thus Plato signals to us that we should read Theaetetus , Sophist , and Statesman sequentially; and similarly, since the opening of Timaeus refers us back to Republic , Plato is indicating to his readers that they must seek some connection between these two works.

These features of the dialogues show Plato’s awareness that he cannot entirely start from scratch in every work that he writes. He will introduce new ideas and raise fresh difficulties, but he will also expect his readers to have already familiarized themselves with the conversations held by the interlocutors of other dialogues—even when there is some alteration among those interlocutors. (Meno does not re-appear in Phaedo ; Timaeus was not among the interlocutors of Republic .) Why does Plato have his dominant characters (Socrates, the Eleatic visitor) reaffirm some of the same points from one dialogue to another, and build on ideas that were made in earlier works? If the dialogues were merely meant as provocations to thought—mere exercises for the mind—there would be no need for Plato to identify his leading characters with a consistent and ever-developing doctrine. For example, Socrates continues to maintain, over a large number of dialogues, that there are such things as forms—and there is no better explanation for this continuity than to suppose that Plato is recommending that doctrine to his readers. Furthermore, when Socrates is replaced as the principal investigator by the visitor from Elea (in Sophist and Statesman ), the existence of forms continues to be taken for granted, and the visitor criticizes any conception of reality that excludes such incorporeal objects as souls and forms. The Eleatic visitor, in other words, upholds a metaphysics that is, in many respects, like the one that Socrates is made to defend. Again, the best explanation for this continuity is that Plato is using both characters—Socrates and the Eleatic visitor—as devices for the presentation and defense of a doctrine that he embraces and wants his readers to embrace as well.

This way of reading Plato’s dialogues does not presuppose that he never changes his mind about anything—that whatever any of his main interlocutors uphold in one dialogue will continue to be presupposed or affirmed elsewhere without alteration. It is, in fact, a difficult and delicate matter to determine, on the basis of our reading of the dialogues, whether Plato means to modify or reject in one dialogue what he has his main interlocutor affirm in some other. One of the most intriguing and controversial questions about his treatment of the forms, for example, is whether he concedes that his conception of those abstract entities is vulnerable to criticism; and, if so, whether he revises some of the assumptions he had been making about them, or develops a more elaborate picture of them that allows him to respond to that criticism (see Meinwald 2016). In Parmenides , the principal interlocutor (not Socrates—he is here portrayed as a promising, young philosopher in need of further training—but rather the pre-Socratic from Elea who gives the dialogue its name: Parmenides) subjects the forms to withering criticism, and then consents to conduct an inquiry into the nature of oneness that has no overt connection to his critique of the forms. Does the discussion of oneness (a baffling series of contradictions—or at any rate, propositions that seem, on the surface, to be contradictions) in some way help address the problems raised about forms? That is one way of reading the dialogue. And if we do read it in this way, does that show that Plato has changed his mind about some of the ideas about forms he inserted into earlier dialogues? Can we find dialogues in which we encounter a “new theory of forms”—that is, a way of thinking of forms that carefully steers clear of the assumptions about forms that led to Parmenides’ critique? It is not easy to say. But we cannot even raise this as an issue worth pondering unless we presuppose that behind the dialogues there stands a single mind that is using these writings as a way of hitting upon the truth, and of bringing that truth to the attention of others. If we find Timaeus (the principal interlocutor of the dialogue named after him) and the Eleatic visitor of the Sophist and Statesman talking about forms in a way that is entirely consistent with the way Socrates talks about forms in Phaedo and Republic , then there is only one reasonable explanation for that consistency: Plato believes that their way of talking about forms is correct, or is at least strongly supported by powerful considerations. If, on the other hand, we find that Timaeus or the Eleatic visitor talks about forms in a way that does not harmonize with the way Socrates conceives of those abstract objects, in the dialogues that assign him a central role as director of the conversation, then the most plausible explanation for these discrepancies is that Plato has changed his mind about the nature of these entities. It would be implausible to suppose that Plato himself had no convictions about forms, and merely wants to give his readers mental exercise by composing dialogues in which different leading characters talk about these objects in discordant ways.

The same point—that we must view the dialogues as the product of a single mind, a single philosopher, though perhaps one who changes his mind—can be made in connection with the politics of Plato’s works (see Bobonich 2002).

It is noteworthy, to begin with, that Plato is, among other things, a political philosopher. For he gives expression, in several of his writings (particular Phaedo ), to a yearning to escape from the tawdriness of ordinary human relations. (Similarly, he evinces a sense of the ugliness of the sensible world, whose beauty pales in comparison with that of the forms.) Because of this, it would have been all too easy for Plato to turn his back entirely on practical reality, and to confine his speculations to theoretical questions. Some of his works— Parmenides is a stellar example—do confine themselves to exploring questions that seem to have no bearing whatsoever on practical life. But it is remarkable how few of his works fall into this category. Even the highly abstract questions raised in Sophist about the nature of being and not-being are, after all, embedded in a search for the definition of sophistry; and thus they call to mind the question whether Socrates should be classified as a sophist—whether, in other words, sophists are to be despised and avoided. In any case, despite the great sympathy Plato expresses for the desire to shed one’s body and live in an incorporeal world, he devotes an enormous amount of energy to the task of understanding the world we live in, appreciating its limited beauty, and improving it.

His tribute to the mixed beauty of the sensible world, in Timaeus , consists in his depiction of it as the outcome of divine efforts to mold reality in the image of the forms, using simple geometrical patterns and harmonious arithmetic relations as building blocks. The desire to transform human relations is given expression in a far larger number of works. Socrates presents himself, in Plato’s Apology , as a man who does not have his head in the clouds (that is part of Aristophanes’ charge against him in Clouds ). He does not want to escape from the everyday world but to make it better (see Allen 2010). He presents himself, in Gorgias , as the only Athenian who has tried his hand at the true art of politics.

Similarly, the Socrates of Republic devotes a considerable part of his discussion to the critique of ordinary social institutions—the family, private property, and rule by the many. The motivation that lies behind the writing of this dialogue is the desire to transform (or, at any rate, to improve) political life, not to escape from it (although it is acknowledged that the desire to escape is an honorable one: the best sort of rulers greatly prefer the contemplation of divine reality to the governance of the city). And if we have any further doubts that Plato does take an interest in the practical realm, we need only turn to Laws . A work of such great detail and length about voting procedures, punishments, education, legislation, and the oversight of public officials can only have been produced by someone who wants to contribute something to the improvement of the lives we lead in this sensible and imperfect realm. Further evidence of Plato’s interest in practical matters can be drawn from his letters, if they are genuine. In most of them, he presents himself as having a deep interest in educating (with the help of his friend, Dion) the ruler of Syracuse, Dionysius II, and thus reforming that city’s politics.

Just as any attempt to understand Plato’s views about forms must confront the question whether his thoughts about them developed or altered over time, so too our reading of him as a political philosopher must be shaped by a willingness to consider the possibility that he changed his mind. For example, on any plausible reading of Republic , Plato evinces a deep antipathy to rule by the many. Socrates tells his interlocutors that the only politics that should engage them are those of the anti-democratic regime he depicts as the paradigm of a good constitution. And yet in Laws , the Athenian visitor proposes a detailed legislative framework for a city in which non-philosophers (people who have never heard of the forms, and have not been trained to understand them) are given considerable powers as rulers. Plato would not have invested so much time in the creation of this comprehensive and lengthy work, had he not believed that the creation of a political community ruled by those who are philosophically unenlightened is a project that deserves the support of his readers. Has Plato changed his mind, then? Has he re-evaluated the highly negative opinion he once held of those who are innocent of philosophy? Did he at first think that the reform of existing Greek cities, with all of their imperfections, is a waste of time—but then decide that it is an endeavor of great value? (And if so, what led him to change his mind?) Answers to these questions can be justified only by careful attention to what he has his interlocutors say. But it would be utterly implausible to suppose that these developmental questions need not be raised, on the grounds that Republic and Laws each has its own cast of characters, and that the two works therefore cannot come into contradiction with each other. According to this hypothesis (one that must be rejected), because it is Socrates (not Plato) who is critical of democracy in Republic , and because it is the Athenian visitor (not Plato) who recognizes the merits of rule by the many in Laws , there is no possibility that the two dialogues are in tension with each other. Against this hypothesis, we should say: Since both Republic and Laws are works in which Plato is trying to move his readers towards certain conclusions, by having them reflect on certain arguments—these dialogues are not barred from having this feature by their use of interlocutors—it would be an evasion of our responsibility as readers and students of Plato not to ask whether what one of them advocates is compatible with what the other advocates. If we answer that question negatively, we have some explaining to do: what led to this change? Alternatively, if we conclude that the two works are compatible, we must say why the appearance of conflict is illusory.

Many contemporary scholars find it plausible that when Plato embarked on his career as a philosophical writer, he composed, in addition to his Apology of Socrates, a number of short ethical dialogues that contain little or nothing in the way of positive philosophical doctrine, but are mainly devoted to portraying the way in which Socrates punctured the pretensions of his interlocutors and forced them to realize that they are unable to offer satisfactory definitions of the ethical terms they used, or satisfactory arguments for their moral beliefs. According to this way of placing the dialogues into a rough chronological order—associated especially with Gregory Vlastos’s name (see especially his Socrates Ironist and Moral Philosopher , chapters 2 and 3)—Plato, at this point of his career, was content to use his writings primarily for the purpose of preserving the memory of Socrates and making plain the superiority of his hero, in intellectual skill and moral seriousness, to all of his contemporaries—particularly those among them who claimed to be experts on religious, political, or moral matters. Into this category of early dialogues (they are also sometimes called “Socratic” dialogues, possibly without any intended chronological connotation) are placed: Charmides , Crito , Euthydemus , Euthyphro , Gorgias , Hippias Major , Hippias Minor , Ion , Laches , Lysis , and Protagoras , (Some scholars hold that we can tell which of these come later during Plato’s early period. For example, it is sometimes said that Protagoras and Gorgias are later, because of their greater length and philosophical complexity. Other dialogues—for example, Charmides and Lysis —are thought not to be among Plato’s earliest within this early group, because in them Socrates appears to be playing a more active role in shaping the progress of the dialogue: that is, he has more ideas of his own.) In comparison with many of Plato’s other dialogues, these “Socratic” works contain little in the way of metaphysical, epistemological, or methodological speculation, and they therefore fit well with the way Socrates characterizes himself in Plato’s Apology : as a man who leaves investigations of high falutin’ matters (which are “in the sky and below the earth”) to wiser heads, and confines all of his investigations to the question how one should live one’s life. Aristotle describes Socrates as someone whose interests were restricted to only one branch of philosophy—the realm of the ethical; and he also says that he was in the habit of asking definitional questions to which he himself lacked answers ( Metaphysics 987b1, Sophistical Refutations 183b7). That testimony gives added weight to the widely accepted hypothesis that there is a group of dialogues—the ones mentioned above as his early works, whether or not they were all written early in Plato’s writing career—in which Plato used the dialogue form as a way of portraying the philosophical activities of the historical Socrates (although, of course, he might also have used them in other ways as well—for example to suggest and begin to explore philosophical difficulties raised by them, see Santas 1979, Brickhouse and Smith 1994).

But at a certain point—so says this hypothesis about the chronology of the dialogues—Plato began to use his works to advance ideas that were his own creations rather than those of Socrates, although he continued to use the name “Socrates” for the interlocutor who presented and argued for these new ideas. The speaker called “Socrates” now begins to move beyond and depart from the historical Socrates: he has views about the methodology that should be used by philosophers (a methodology borrowed from mathematics), and he argues for the immortality of the soul and the existence and importance of the forms of beauty, justice, goodness, and the like. (By contrast, in Apology Socrates says that no one knows what becomes of us after we die.) Phaedo is often said to be the dialogue in which Plato first comes into his own as a philosopher who is moving far beyond the ideas of his teacher (though it is also commonly said that we see a new methodological sophistication and a greater interest in mathematical knowledge in Meno ). Having completed all of the dialogues that, according to this hypothesis, we characterize as early, Plato widened the range of topics to be explored in his writings (no longer confining himself to ethics), and placed the theory of forms (and related ideas about language, knowledge, and love) at the center of his thinking. In these works of his “middle” period—for example, in Phaedo , Cratylus , Symposium , Republic , and Phaedrus —there is both a change of emphasis and of doctrine. The focus is no longer on ridding ourselves of false ideas and self-deceit; rather, we are asked to accept (however tentatively) a radical new conception of ourselves (now divided into three parts), our world—or rather, our two worlds—and our need to negotiate between them. Definitions of the most important virtue terms are finally proposed in Republic (the search for them in some of the early dialogues having been unsuccessful): Book I of this dialogue is a portrait of how the historical Socrates might have handled the search for a definition of justice, and the rest of the dialogue shows how the new ideas and tools discovered by Plato can complete the project that his teacher was unable to finish. Plato continues to use a figure called “Socrates” as his principal interlocutor, and in this way he creates a sense of continuity between the methods, insights, and ideals of the historical Socrates and the new Socrates who has now become a vehicle for the articulation of his own new philosophical outlook. In doing so, he acknowledges his intellectual debt to his teacher and appropriates for his own purposes the extraordinary prestige of the man who was the wisest of his time.

This hypothesis about the chronology of Plato’s writings has a third component: it does not place his works into either of only two categories—the early or “Socratic” dialogues, and all the rest—but works instead with a threefold division of early, middle, and late. That is because, following ancient testimony, it has become a widely accepted assumption that Laws is one of Plato’s last works, and further that this dialogue shares a great many stylistic affinities with a small group of others: Sophist , Statesman , Timaeus , Critias , and Philebus . These five dialogues together with Laws are generally agreed to be his late works, because they have much more in common with each other, when one counts certain stylistic features apparent only to readers of Plato’s Greek, than with any of Plato’s other works. (Computer counts have aided these stylometric studies, but the isolation of a group of six dialogues by means of their stylistic commonalities was recognized in the nineteenth century. See Brandwood 1990, Young 1994.)

It is not at all clear whether there are one or more philosophical affinities among this group of six dialogues—that is, whether the philosophy they contain is sharply different from that of all of the other dialogues. Plato does nothing to encourage the reader to view these works as a distinctive and separate component of his thinking. On the contrary, he links Sophist with Theaetetus (the conversations they present have a largely overlapping cast of characters, and take place on successive days) no less than Sophist and Statesman . Sophist contains, in its opening pages, a reference to the conversation of Parmenides —and perhaps Plato is thus signaling to his readers that they should bring to bear on Sophist the lessons that are to be drawn from Parmenides . Similarly, Timaeus opens with a reminder of some of the principal ethical and political doctrines of Republic . It could be argued, of course, that when one looks beyond these stage-setting devices, one finds significant philosophical changes in the six late dialogues, setting this group off from all that preceded them. But there is no consensus that they should be read in this way. Resolving this issue requires intensive study of the content of Plato’s works. So, although it is widely accepted that the six dialogues mentioned above belong to Plato’s latest period, there is, as yet, no agreement among students of Plato that these six form a distinctive stage in his philosophical development.

In fact, it remains a matter of dispute whether the division of Plato’s works into three periods—early, middle, late—does correctly indicate the order of composition, and whether it is a useful tool for the understanding of his thought (See Cooper 1997, vii–xxvii). Of course, it would be wildly implausible to suppose that Plato’s writing career began with such complex works as Laws , Parmenides , Phaedrus , or Republic . In light of widely accepted assumptions about how most philosophical minds develop, it is likely that when Plato started writing philosophical works some of the shorter and simpler dialogues were the ones he composed: Laches , or Crito , or Ion (for example). (Similarly, Apology does not advance a complex philosophical agenda or presuppose an earlier body of work; so that too is likely to have been composed near the beginning of Plato’s writing career.) Even so, there is no good reason to eliminate the hypothesis that throughout much of his life Plato devoted himself to writing two sorts of dialogues at the same time, moving back and forth between them as he aged: on the one hand, introductory works whose primary purpose is to show readers the difficulty of apparently simple philosophical problems, and thereby to rid them of their pretensions and false beliefs; and on the other hand, works filled with more substantive philosophical theories supported by elaborate argumentation. Moreover, one could point to features of many of the “Socratic” dialogues that would justify putting them in the latter category, even though the argumentation does not concern metaphysics or methodology or invoke mathematics— Gorgias , Protagoras , Lysis , Euthydemus , Hippias Major among them.

Plato makes it clear that both of these processes, one preceding the other, must be part of one’s philosophical education. One of his deepest methodological convictions (affirmed in Meno , Theaetetus , and Sophist ) is that in order to make intellectual progress we must recognize that knowledge cannot be acquired by passively receiving it from others: rather, we must work our way through problems and assess the merits of competing theories with an independent mind. Accordingly, some of his dialogues are primarily devices for breaking down the reader’s complacency, and that is why it is essential that they come to no positive conclusions; others are contributions to theory-construction, and are therefore best absorbed by those who have already passed through the first stage of philosophical development. We should not assume that Plato could have written the preparatory dialogues only at the earliest stage of his career. Although he may well have begun his writing career by taking up that sort of project, he may have continued writing these “negative” works at later stages, at the same time that he was composing his theory-constructing dialogues. For example although both Euthydemus and Charmides are widely assumed to be early dialogues, they might have been written around the same time as Symposium and Republic , which are generally assumed to be compositions of his middle period—or even later.

No doubt, some of the works widely considered to be early really are such. But it is an open question which and how many of them are. At any rate, it is clear that Plato continued to write in a “Socratic” and “negative” vein even after he was well beyond the earliest stages of his career: Theaetetus features a Socrates who is even more insistent upon his ignorance than are the dramatic representations of Socrates in briefer and philosophically less complex works that are reasonably assumed to be early; and like many of those early works, Theaetetus seeks but does not find the answer to the “what is it?” question that it relentlessly pursues—“What is knowledge?” Similarly, Parmenides , though certainly not an early dialogue, is a work whose principal aim is to puzzle the reader by the presentation of arguments for apparently contradictory conclusions; since it does not tell us how it is possible to accept all of those conclusions, its principal effect on the reader is similar to that of dialogues (many of them no doubt early) that reach only negative conclusions. Plato uses this educational device—provoking the reader through the presentation of opposed arguments, and leaving the contradiction unresolved—in Protagoras (often considered an early dialogue) as well. So it is clear that even after he was well beyond the earliest stages of his thinking, he continued to assign himself the project of writing works whose principal aim is the presentation of unresolved difficulties. (And, just as we should recognize that puzzling the reader continues to be his aim even in later works, so too we should not overlook the fact that there is some substantive theory-construction in the ethical works that are simple enough to have been early compositions: Ion , for example, affirms a theory of poetic inspiration; and Crito sets out the conditions under which a citizen acquires an obligation to obey civic commands. Neither ends in failure.)

If we are justified in taking Socrates’ speech in Plato’s Apology to constitute reliable evidence about what the historical Socrates was like, then whatever we find in Plato’s other works that is of a piece with that speech can also be safely attributed to Socrates. So understood, Socrates was a moralist but (unlike Plato) not a metaphysician or epistemologist or cosmologist. That fits with Aristotle’s testimony, and Plato’s way of choosing the dominant speaker of his dialogues gives further support to this way of distinguishing between him and Socrates. The number of dialogues that are dominated by a Socrates who is spinning out elaborate philosophical doctrines is remarkably small: Phaedo , Republic , Phaedrus , and Philebus . All of them are dominated by ethical issues: whether to fear death, whether to be just, whom to love, the place of pleasure. Evidently, Plato thinks that it is appropriate to make Socrates the major speaker in a dialogue that is filled with positive content only when the topics explored in that work primarily have to do with the ethical life of the individual. (The political aspects of Republic are explicitly said to serve the larger question whether any individual, no matter what his circumstances, should be just.) When the doctrines he wishes to present systematically become primarily metaphysical, he turns to a visitor from Elea ( Sophist , Statesman ); when they become cosmological, he turns to Timaeus; when they become constitutional, he turns, in Laws , to a visitor from Athens (and he then eliminates Socrates entirely). In effect, Plato is showing us: although he owes a great deal to the ethical insights of Socrates, as well as to his method of puncturing the intellectual pretensions of his interlocutors by leading them into contradiction, he thinks he should not put into the mouth of his teacher too elaborate an exploration of ontological, or cosmological, or political themes, because Socrates refrained from entering these domains. This may be part of the explanation why he has Socrates put into the mouth of the personified Laws of Athens the theory advanced in Crito , which reaches the conclusion that it would be unjust for him to escape from prison. Perhaps Plato is indicating, at the point where these speakers enter the dialogue, that none of what is said here is in any way derived from or inspired by the conversation of Socrates.

Just as we should reject the idea that Plato must have made a decision, at a fairly early point in his career, no longer to write one kind of dialogue (negative, destructive, preparatory) and to write only works of elaborate theory-construction; so we should also question whether he went through an early stage during which he refrained from introducing into his works any of his own ideas (if he had any), but was content to play the role of a faithful portraitist, representing to his readers the life and thought of Socrates. It is unrealistic to suppose that someone as original and creative as Plato, who probably began to write dialogues somewhere in his thirties (he was around 28 when Socrates was killed), would have started his compositions with no ideas of his own, or, having such ideas, would have decided to suppress them, for some period of time, allowing himself to think for himself only later. (What would have led to such a decision?) We should instead treat the moves made in the dialogues, even those that are likely to be early, as Platonic inventions—derived, no doubt, by Plato’s reflections on and transformations of the key themes of Socrates that he attributes to Socrates in Apology . That speech indicates, for example, that the kind of religiosity exhibited by Socrates was unorthodox and likely to give offense or lead to misunderstanding. It would be implausible to suppose that Plato simply concocted the idea that Socrates followed a divine sign, especially because Xenophon too attributes this to his Socrates. But what of the various philosophical moves rehearsed in Euthyphro —the dialogue in which Socrates searches, unsuccessfully, for an understanding of what piety is? We have no good reason to think that in writing this work Plato adopted the role of a mere recording device, or something close to it (changing a word here and there, but for the most part simply recalling what he heard Socrates say, as he made his way to court). It is more likely that Plato, having been inspired by the unorthodoxy of Socrates’ conception of piety, developed, on his own, a series of questions and answers designed to show his readers how difficult it is to reach an understanding of the central concept that Socrates’ fellow citizens relied upon when they condemned him to death. The idea that it is important to search for definitions may have been Socratic in origin. (After all, Aristotle attributes this much to Socrates.) But the twists and turns of the arguments in Euthyphro and other dialogues that search for definitions are more likely to be the products of Plato’s mind than the content of any conversations that really took place.

It is equally unrealistic to suppose that when Plato embarked on his career as a writer, he made a conscious decision to put all of the compositions that he would henceforth compose for a general reading public (with the exception of Apology ) in the form of a dialogue. If the question, “why did Plato write dialogues?”, which many of his readers are tempted to ask, pre-supposes that there must have been some such once-and-for-all decision, then it is poorly posed. It makes better sense to break that question apart into many little ones: better to ask, “Why did Plato write this particular work (for example: Protagoras , or Republic , or Symposium , or Laws ) in the form of a dialogue—and that one ( Timaeus , say) mostly in the form of a long and rhetorically elaborate single speech?” than to ask why he decided to adopt the dialogue form.

The best way to form a reasonable conjecture about why Plato wrote any given work in the form of a dialogue is to ask: what would be lost, were one to attempt to re-write this work in a way that eliminated the give-and-take of interchange, stripped the characters of their personality and social markers, and transformed the result into something that comes straight from the mouth of its author? This is often a question that will be easy to answer, but the answer might vary greatly from one dialogue to another. In pursuing this strategy, we must not rule out the possibility that some of Plato’s reasons for writing this or that work in the form of a dialogue will also be his reason for doing so in other cases—perhaps some of his reasons, so far as we can guess at them, will be present in all other cases. For example, the use of character and conversation allows an author to enliven his work, to awaken the interest of his readership, and therefore to reach a wider audience. The enormous appeal of Plato’s writings is in part a result of their dramatic composition. Even treatise-like compositions— Timaeus and Laws , for example—improve in readability because of their conversational frame. Furthermore, the dialogue form allows Plato’s evident interest in pedagogical questions (how is it possible to learn? what is the best way to learn? from what sort of person can we learn? what sort of person is in a position to learn?) to be pursued not only in the content of his compositions but also in their form. Even in Laws such questions are not far from Plato’s mind, as he demonstrates, through the dialogue form, how it is possible for the citizens of Athens, Sparta, and Crete to learn from each other by adapting and improving upon each other’s social and political institutions.

In some of his works, it is evident that one of Plato’s goals is to create a sense of puzzlement among his readers, and that the dialogue form is being used for this purpose. The Parmenides is perhaps the clearest example of such a work, because here Plato relentlessly rubs his readers’ faces in a baffling series of unresolved puzzles and apparent contradictions. But several of his other works also have this character, though to a smaller degree: for example, Protagoras (can virtue be taught?), Hippias Minor (is voluntary wrongdoing better than involuntary wrongdoing?), and portions of Meno (are some people virtuous because of divine inspiration?). Just as someone who encounters Socrates in conversation should sometimes be puzzled about whether he means what he says (or whether he is instead speaking ironically), so Plato sometimes uses the dialogue form to create in his readers a similar sense of discomfort about what he means and what we ought to infer from the arguments that have been presented to us. But Socrates does not always speak ironically, and similarly Plato’s dialogues do not always aim at creating a sense of bafflement about what we are to think about the subject under discussion. There is no mechanical rule for discovering how best to read a dialogue, no interpretive strategy that applies equally well to all of his works. We will best understand Plato’s works and profit most from our reading of them if we recognize their great diversity of styles and adapt our way of reading accordingly. Rather than impose on our reading of Plato a uniform expectation of what he must be doing (because he has done such a thing elsewhere), we should bring to each dialogue a receptivity to what is unique to it. That would be the most fitting reaction to the artistry in his philosophy.

The bibliography below is meant as a highly selective and limited guide for readers who want to learn more about the issues covered above. Further discussion of these and other issues regarding Plato’s philosophy, and far more bibliographical information, is available in the other entries on Plato.

  • Cooper, John M. (ed.), 1997, Plato: Complete Works , Indianapolis: Hackett. (Contains translations of all the works handed down from antiquity with attribution to Plato, some of which are universally agreed to be spurious, with explanatory footnotes and both a general Introduction to the study of the dialogues and individual Introductory Notes to each work translated.)
  • Burnyeat, Myles and Michael Frede, 2015, The Pseudo-Platonic Seventh Letter , Dominic Scott (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ahbel-Rappe, Sara, and Rachana Kamtekar (eds.), 2006, A Companion to Socrates , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Allen, Danielle, S., 2010, Why Plato Wrote , Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Annas, Julia, 2003, Plato: A Very Short Introduction , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Benson, Hugh (ed.), 2006, A Companion to Plato , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Blondell, Ruby, 2002, The Play of Character in Plato’s Dialogues , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bobonich, Christopher, 2002, Plato’s Utopia Recast: His Later Ethics and Politics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Boys-Stone George, and Christopher Rowe (eds.), 2013, The Circle of Socrates: Readings in the First-Generation Socratics , Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Brandwood, Leonard, 1990, The Chronology of Plato’s Dialogues , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Brickhouse, Thomas C. & Nicholas D. Smith, 1994, Plato’s Socrates , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Dancy, Russell, 2004, Plato’s Introduction of Forms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Ebrey, David and Richard Kraut (eds.), 2022, The Cambridge Companion to Plato , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Fine, Gail (ed.), 1999, Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 1999, Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the Soul , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2008, The Oxford Handbook of Plato , Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Essays by many scholars on a wide range of topics, including several studies of individual dialogues.)
  • ––– (ed.), 2019, The Oxford Handbook of Plato , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Frede, Michael, 1992, “Plato’s Arguments and the Dialogue Form,” in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , Supplementary Volume 1992, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 201–220.
  • Griswold, Charles L. (ed.), 1988, Platonic Writings, Platonic Readings , London: Routledge.
  • Guthrie, W.K.C., 1971, Socrates , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1975, A History of Greek Philosophy , Volume 4, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1978, A History of Greek Philosophy , Volume 5, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Irwin, Terence, 1995, Plato’s Ethics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Kahn, Charles H., 1996, Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2003, “On Platonic Chronology,” in Julia Annas and Christopher Rowe (eds.), New Perspectives on Plato: Modern and Ancient , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, chapter 4.
  • Klagge, James C. and Nicholas D. Smith (eds.), 1992, Methods of Interpreting Plato and His Dialogue , Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 1992, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Kraut, Richard (ed.), 1992, The Cambridge Companion to Plato , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2008, How to Read Plato , London: Granta.
  • Ledger, Gerald R., 1989, Re-Counting Plato: A Computer Analysis of Plato’s Style , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McCabe, Mary Margaret, 1994, Plato’s Individuals , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 2000, Plato and His Predecessors: The Dramatisation of Reason , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Meinwald, Constance, 2016, Plato , London: Routledge.
  • Morrison, Donald R., 2012, The Cambridge Companion to Socrates , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nails, Debra, 1995, Agora, Academy, and the Conduct of Philosophy , Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
  • –––, 2002, The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics , Indianapolis: Hackett. (An encyclopedia of information about the characters in all of the dialogues.)
  • Nightingale, Andrea, 1993, Genres in Dialogue: Plato and the Construction of Philosophy , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Peterson, Sandra, 2011, Socrates and Philosophy in the Dialogues of Plato , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Press, Gerald A. (ed.), 2000, Who Speaks for Plato? Studies in Platonic Anonymity , Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
  • Prior, William J., 2019, Socrates , Cambridge: Polity Press.
  • Rowe, C.J., 2007, Plato and the Art of Philosophical Writing , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Rowe, Christopher, & Malcolm Schofield (eds.), 2000, Greek and Roman Political Thought , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (Contains 7 introductory essays by 7 hands on Socratic and Platonic political thought.)
  • Rudebusch, George, 2009, Socrates , Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Russell, Daniel C., 2005, Plato on Pleasure and the Good Life , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Rutherford, R.B., 1995, The Art of Plato: Ten Essays in Platonic Interpretation , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Santas, Gerasimos, 1979, Socrates: Philosophy in Plato’s Early Dialogues , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Sayre, Kenneth, 1995, Plato’s Literary Garden , Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Schofield, Malcolm, 2006, Plato: Political Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Silverman, Allan, 2002, The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato’s Metaphysics , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Smith, Nicholas D. and Thomas C. Brickhouse, 1994, Plato’s Socrates , Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • –––and John Bussanich (eds.), 2015, The Bloomsbury Companion to Socrates , London: Bloomsbury.
  • Taylor, C.C.W., 1998, Socrates , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Thesleff, Holger, 1982, Studies in Platonic Chronology , Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum 70, Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica.
  • Vander Waerdt, Paul. A. (ed.), 1994, The Socratic Movement , Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Vasiliou, Iakovos, 2008, Aiming at Virtue in Plato , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Vlastos, Gregory, 1991, Socrates: Ironist and Moral Philosopher , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1995, Studies in Greek Philosophy (Volume 2: Socrates, Plato, and Their Tradition), Daniel W. Graham (ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • White, Nicholas P., 1976, Plato on Knowledge and Reality , Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Young, Charles M., 1994, “Plato and Computer Dating,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , 12: 227–250.
  • Zuckert, Catherine H., 2009, Plato’s Philosophers: The Coherence of the Dialogues , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Links to Original texts of Plato’s Dialogues (maintained by Bernard Suzanne)
  • In Dialogue: the Life and Works of Plato , a short podcast by Peter Adamson (Philosophy, Kings College London).

abstract objects | Aristotle | education, philosophy of | epistemology | metaphysics | Plato: ethics and politics in The Republic | religion: and morality | Socrates | -->Socratic Dialogues -->

Copyright © 2022 by Richard Kraut < rkraut1 @ northwestern . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

GREAT THINKERS Plato

plato mathematician biography

Plato is one of the most brilliant and far-reaching writers to have ever lived. Our very conception of philosophy—of rigorous thinking concerning the true situation of man, the nature of the whole, and the perplexity of being—owes a great debt to his work. No area of inquiry seems foreign to him: his writings investigate ethics, politics, mathematics, metaphysics, logic, aesthetics, and epistemology in tremendous depth and breadth. In the words of Alfred North Whitehead, “The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.”

There are few contemporary sources for the life of Plato. According to Diogenes Laertius, who lived many centuries later than the philosophers about whom he was writing, Plato was born to Ariston, an Athenian aristocrat who traced his lineage to Codrus, the king of Athens, and to Melanthus, the king of Messina. The family of his mother, Perictione, boasted a relationship with the great Athenian legislator Solon. Diogenes Laertius also reports that the philosopher’s name was Aristocles, for his grandfather, but that his wrestling coach dubbed him “Platon,” meaning “broad,” either on account of his robust physique, or the width of his forehead, or eloquence of his speech. And yet modern scholars are in doubt, since the name “Plato” was not uncommon in the Athens of Plato’s day.

Well before his encounter with Socrates, Plato was known to accompany philosophers such as Cratylus, a disciple of Heraclitus. Later in life, after the death of Socrates, Plato traveled around Egypt, Italy, Sicily, and Cyrene, Libya. Upon his return to Athens at around 40 years of age, Plato founded the first known institution of higher learning in the West, the Academy, named for its location in the Grove of Academus. The Academy was open until its destruction by Sulla in 84 BCE. It counts among its illustrious alumni many fine minds, but none more renowned than Aristotle .

After founding the Academy, Plato became involved in the politics of Syracuse. According to Diogenes, Plato visited Syracuse while it was under the rule of Dionysius. While there, Dionysius’ brother-in-law, Dion, became Plato’s disciple. Dion, however, later turned against Plato, selling him into slavery. During this time, Plato nearly faced death in Cyrene. Fortunately, chancing upon an admirer who purchased his freedom, Plato was spared and found his way home.

Upon the death of Dionysius, according to Plato’s account in his Seventh Letter , Dion requested that Plato return to Syracuse to tutor young Dionysius II. In another reversal of fortune, Dionysius II expelled his uncle Dion, and compelled Plato to remain. Plato would eventually leave Syracuse, while Dion later returned to Syracuse and overthrew Dionysius II, only to be usurped by Callipus, another disciple of Plato.

Ancient sources offer differing accounts of Plato’s death. According to one source, Plato died peacefully in his bed listening to the sweet sounds of a Thracian flute girl. Another source reports that he died while attending a friend’s wedding feast. Still another account simply says he died in his sleep.

For further biographical reading, see also:

The Cambridge Companion to Plato , ed. Richard Kraut, Cambridge: 1992.

Crunch Learning Logo

Plato – Ancient Greek Philosopher: A Comprehensive Summary

  • Author: K.L. Woida
  • Last Updated: February 9, 2024
  • First Published: January 19, 2023
  • Publisher: Crunch Learning
  • Ancient Greece

Table of Contents

Plato

Plato was an ancient Greek philosopher and student of Socrates . He is considered one of the most important figures in the development of Western philosophy, and his ideas and writings have had a profound influence on Western culture and thought. He founded his famous Academy in Athens, which was one of the first institutions of higher learning in the Western world. As well, he was also a prolific writer, leaving behind a wealth of philosophical works that have influenced generations of thinkers. As such, historians consider him to be one of the most important philosophers from ancient Greece.

Plato ancient greece

Early Life and Education of Plato

Unfortunately, historians do not have a complete understanding of his early life due to the lack of reliable records or accounts from the time. As such, we do not fully understand Plato’s early life such as his date of birth. Regardless, historians believe that he was born into an aristocratic family in Athens in the 420s BCE. (428/427 or 424/423 BCE)

Furthermore, historians have identified that Plato was a student of Socrates, who was another influential philosopher from ancient Greece. He was deeply influenced by Socrates’ ideas and methods, and after Socrates’ death, he left Athens and traveled extensively in Greece and Italy, studying with various other philosophers and mathematicians.

It was during these travels that he was exposed to the ideas of Pythagoras, which greatly influenced his own philosophical beliefs. After returning to Athens, Plato founded the Academy, a school of higher learning, where he taught and developed his own philosophy. It was one of the first institutions of higher learning in the Western world.

Plato ancient greek philosopher

Plato’s Philosophy

He is most famous for his philosophical dialogues, which are a series of written conversations between characters discussing various philosophical topics. Some of his most famous dialogues include “The Republic,” “The Symposium,” and “The Timaeus.” In these dialogues, he discusses a wide range of philosophical topics, including ethics, metaphysics, politics, and epistemology.

Plato also made significant contributions to the field of mathematics. He is credited with the discovery of the five Platonic solids and is known for his definition of a right angle. In addition, he made important contributions to the study of ethics and political philosophy, proposing the idea of a philosopher-king, a ruler who is guided by wisdom and virtue.

Significance of Plato

As stated above, Plato was one of the most important philosophers in ancient Greece. His ideas, theories and contributions had a profound impact on the culture of ancient Greece .

Furthermore, his ideas have had a profound influence on Western philosophy, science, and mathematics. His political ideas have had an impact on the development of political theory. His dialogues have also had a lasting influence on literature, and his writing is considered to be some of the finest in the Western tradition.

Also, Plato’s Academy was also highly influential, serving as a model for later institutions of higher learning, including modern universities and colleges. Today, the Academy is remembered as one of the first institutions of higher learning in the Western world and is considered an important moment in the history of Western education.

Picture of K.L. Woida

RELATED ARTICLES

Poseidon Ancient Greek God

Poseidon – Ancient Greek God: A Comprehensive Summary

Poseidon was one of the main gods of ancient Greek mythology and played an important role in Greek culture.

12 Main Gods and Goddess of Ancient Greece

12 Main Gods and Goddesses of Ancient Greece: A Comprehensive Summary

There were 12 main gods and goddesses of ancient Greece, which were referred to as the ‘Olympians’. These gods and goddesses were important to ancient Greek mythology.

Titans of Ancient Greece

Titans of Ancient Greece: A Comprehensive Summary

The Titans of ancient Greece were an important part of ancient Greek mythology. They were said to be the gods that existed before Zeus and the other ancient Greek Olympians.

Ancient Greece Social Classes

Social Classes of Ancient Greece: A Comprehensive Summary

The Social classes of ancient Greece were divided into three main sections: the upper class, the middle class, and the lower class.

Archaic Greece

History of Archaic Greece: A Comprehensive Summary

Archaic Greece refers to the period of ancient Greek history that lasted from the 8th century BCE to the 5th century BCE.

Economy of Ancient Greece

The Economy of Ancient Greece: A Comprehensive Summary

The economy of ancient Greece centered on aspects such as: agriculture, trade, and manufacturing. Learn how the economy shaped the society and influenced the daily life of the ancient Greeks.

plato mathematician biography

Server Costs Fundraiser 2024

Joshua J. Mark

Plato (l. 424/423 to 348/347 BCE) is the pre-eminent Greek philosopher, known for his Dialogues and for founding his Academy in Athens , traditionally considered the first university in the Western world. Plato was a student of Socrates and featured his former teacher in almost all of his dialogues which form the basis of Western philosophy .

The son of Ariston of the deme Colytus, Plato had two older brothers (Adeimantus and Glaucon), who both feature famously in Plato's dialogue Republic , and a sister Potone. According to the later writer Diogenes Laertius (l. c. 180 to c. 240, and considered often unreliable), his birth name was Aristocles, and "Plato" was a nickname given him by his wrestling coach because of his broad shoulders (in Greek, Platon means broad).

This claim has been challenged by scholar Robin Waterfield who also places Plato's birth date at 424/423 BCE, rejecting the traditional birth date of 428/427 BCE. Waterfield writes:

There are several factors that point to a birth date later than 428/7. The most important is that there is no evidence that he fought in any of the last battles of the Peloponnesian War in 406 and 405, so he was probably still under the age of twenty. Athens was critically short of manpower at the time, so he would certainly have been called up. ( Plato of Athens , 3)

Waterfield also notes Plato's Letter 7 , regarded as authentic, in which he mentions his plans to take part in the public life of Athens once he comes of age, placing him under the age of 20 in 405 BCE (3). The traditional birth date of 428/427 BCE assigned to Plato, therefore, must be regarded as inaccurate.

Plato's family was aristocratic and well-connected politically and it seems he was expected to pursue a career in politics. His interests, however, though they included politics, also tended toward the arts, and in his youth, he wrote plays and, perhaps, poetry.

After abandoning his political and literary pursuits and devoting himself to Socrates, even throughout his trial and execution, Plato wrote the foundational philosophic works of the ancient world, which would go on to influence world culture . The three great monotheistic religions of the world owe much to Platonic thought whether directly or through the works of his student and friend Aristotle (l. 384-322 BCE), whose teachings remained consistent with Plato's vision of the importance of caring for one's soul and maintaining a virtuous lifestyle even though Aristotle would depart from some of the specifics of Plato's philosophy.

Socrates & Plato

When he was in his late teens or early twenties, Plato heard Socrates teaching in the market and abandoned his plans to pursue a political or literary career; he burned his early work and devoted himself to philosophy.

It is likely that Plato had known Socrates, at least by reputation, since youth. The Athenian politician, Critias (l. c. 460-403 BCE), was Plato's mother's cousin and studied with Socrates as a young man. It has been suggested, therefore, that Socrates was a regular visitor to Plato's family home. However this may be, nothing is suggested by the ancient writers to indicate Socrates' influence over Plato until the latter was about 20 years old.

Diogenes Laertius writes that Plato was about to compete for the prize in tragedies in the theatre of Bacchus when "he heard the discourse of Socrates and burnt his poems saying, ' Vulcan , come here; for Plato wants your aid' and from henceforth, as they say, being now twenty years old, he became a pupil of Socrates." Nothing is clearly known of Plato's activities for the next eight years save that he studied under the elder philosopher until the latter's trial and execution on the charge of impiety in 399 BCE.

Socrates' execution impacted Plato significantly, and he left Athens to travel, visiting Egypt and Italy among other places, before returning to his homeland to write his dialogues and set up the Academy. His Dialogues almost all feature Socrates as the main character, but whether this is an accurate portrayal of Socrates' actions and beliefs has long been contested.

Greek Philosophers

Plato's contemporary, Phaedo, also one of Socrates' students (and best known for Plato's dialogue named after him) is said by Laertius to have contended that Plato placed his own ideas in Socrates' mouth and made up the dramatic situations of his dialogues. Other philosophers and writers of the time have also questioned the accuracy of Plato's depiction of Socrates but seem in agreement that Plato was a very serious man with lofty ideas which were difficult for many to grasp.

Critics of Plato

Though he was respected as a philosopher of enormous talent in his lifetime (he was at least twice kidnapped and ransomed for a high price), he was by no means universally acclaimed. The value of Plato's philosophy was said to have been questioned most strenuously by the Cynic philosopher Diogenes of Sinope who considered Plato an 'elitist snob' and a 'phony'.

Again, according to Laertius, when Plato defined a human being as a bi-ped without feathers, Diogenes is said to have plucked a chicken and presented it in Plato's classroom, crying, "Behold, Plato's human being." Plato allegedly replied that his definition would now need to be revised, but this concession to a critic seems to have been an exception rather than the rule. Criticisms aside, however, Plato's work exerted an enormous impact on his contemporaries and those who followed.

Plato's Dialogues

Plato's Dialogues of the Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, and Phaedo are commonly collected under the title The Last Days of Socrates, and this four-act drama shows Socrates before, during, and after his trial in the Athenian court. Scholar I. F. Stone praises Plato's Apology as "a masterpiece of world literature , a model of courtroom pleading; and the greatest single piece of Greek prose that has come down to us. It rises to a climax which never fails to touch one deeply" (210), and Stone is certainly not alone in his estimation of the work.

The Apology is considered universally as the beginning of western philosophy. Plato's Euthyphro , however often overlooked, sets the stage for Apology while also providing the reader with another glimpse into the values Socrates may have held and the way in which he went about teaching these values. Perhaps it was Plato's intention to show why Socrates would have been put on trial in the first place, since the young fundamentalist, Euthyphro, is hardly hurting anyone with his beliefs and, no doubt, the case he brings against his own father would have been thrown out of court. As Euthyphro clearly and ardently believes in the gods of Greece , and as Socrates soundly shows him that his beliefs are inconsistent and incomplete, the dialogue illustrates what could have been meant by the charge leveled against Socrates of "corrupting the youth".

In the Apology , Plato recounts the foundational speech of Socrates (whether factual or his own creation) in defending the importance of the philosopher's - or anyone's - right to stand up for their personal convictions against the opinion of society. In defending himself against the unjust charges of his accusers, Socrates says:

Men of Athens, I honor and love you; but I shall obey God rather than you and, while I have life and strength, I shall never cease from the practice and teaching of philosophy, exhorting anyone whom I meet after my manner, and convincing him saying: O my friend, why do you who are a citizen of the great and mighty and wise city of Athens care so much about laying up the greatest amount of money and honor and reputation and so little about wisdom and truth and the greatest improvement of the soul, which you never regard or heed at all? Are you not Ashamed of this? And if the person with whom I am arguing says: Yes, but I do care; I do not depart or let him go at once; I interrogate and examine and cross-examine him, and if I think that he has no virtue, but only says that he has, I reproach him with undervaluing the greater, and overvaluing the less. And this I should say to everyone whom I meet, young and old, citizen and alien, but especially to the citizens, inasmuch as they are my brethren. For this is the command of God, as I would have you know: and I believe that to this day no greater good has ever happened in the state than my service to the God. For I do nothing but go about persuading you all, old and young alike, not to take thought for your persons and your properties, but first and chiefly to care about the greatest improvement of the soul. I tell you that virtue is not given by money, but that from virtue come money and every other good of man, public as well as private. This is my teaching, and if this is the doctrine which corrupts the youth, my influence is ruinous indeed. But if anyone says that this is not my teaching, he is speaking an untruth. Wherefore, O men of Athens, I say to you, do as Anytus bids or not as Anytus bids, and either acquit me or not; but whatever you do, know that I shall never alter my ways, not even if I have to die many times. (29d-30c)

This speech has continued to inspire activists, revolutionaries, and many others for the past two thousand years but would be meaningless if Socrates had not chosen to place his life on the line to stand behind his words. The dialogue of the Crito shows Socrates doing just that as it is a discussion of the law and how, as a citizen of the state, one should obey the law even if one disagrees with it.

Dialouges of Plato

Socrates' friend Crito suggests he escape, and offers him the means to do so, but Socrates rejects the offer, pointing out that his life's work would mean nothing were he to attempt dodging the consequences of his words and actions. This dialogue, set in Socrates' prison cell as he awaits execution, prepares a reader for the final act of the drama, Plato's Phaedo , in which Socrates attempts to prove the immortality of the soul.

Sign up for our free weekly email newsletter!

Plato very purposefully states in the dialogue that he himself was not present that day and leaves it to his main character, the narrator Phaedo, to relate the events of Socrates' last hours which were devoted entirely to philosophical discourse with his students. Plato has the character of Socrates say, at one point:

I will go back to what we have so often spoken of, and begin with the assumption that there exists an absolute beauty, and an absolute good, and an absolute greatness, and so on. If you grant me this, and agree that they exist, I hope to be able to show you what my cause is, and to discover that the soul is immortal (100b)

If the reader does grant this to Socrates then, indeed, the soul is proven immortal; if one does not grant the assumption, however, it is not. The assumption that there exists "an absolute good and an absolute greatness" is quite a large one, and Plato's dialogues, no matter the subject they treat, may be read as a life's work to prove the truth of what Socrates asks an audience to grant him.

The Death of Socrates

The Quest for Truth

The Dialogues of Plato universally concern themselves with the quest for Truth and the understanding of what is Good. Plato contended that there was one universal truth, which a human being needed to recognize and strive to live in accordance with. This truth, he claimed, was embodied in the realm of Forms. Plato's Theory of Forms states, simply put, that there exists a higher realm of truth and that our perceived world of the senses is merely a reflection of the greater one.

When one looks at a horse, then, and values that horse as 'beautiful', one is responding to how closely that particular horse on earth corresponds to the 'Form of Beauty' in the realm of Forms. In order to recognize the 'Form of Beauty', one needs first be able to recognize that this perceived world is merely an illusion or a reflection and that what one calls 'beautiful' on earth is not beautiful in itself but is only 'beautiful' in as much as it participates in the 'Form of Beauty' (a concept further explored in Plato's famous 'Allegory of the Cave' in Book VII of Republic ). This central concept of Platonic thought is a refutation of the sophist Protagoras ' claim that "Of all things, a man is the measure", meaning that reality is subject to individual interpretation. Plato completely rejected this claim and spent his life trying to refute it through his work.

Statue of Plato

The old saying, "Beauty is in the eye of the beholder" would be completely unacceptable to Plato. If Person A claims a horse is beautiful and Person B claims that the horse is not, one of them needs to be right and one wrong in their claim; they cannot both be correct. According to Plato, the one who is right will be the one who understands and recognizes the Form of Beauty as it is expressed in that particular horse. This claim, of course, stands in direct opposition to Protagoras' assertion that "Man is the measure of all things", and, it seems, it was supposed to. Plato devoted most of his life to trying to prove the reality of the realm of Forms and to disprove Protagoras' relativism, even to the last dialogue he wrote, the Laws .

In all of Plato's work, the one constant is that there is a Truth which it is the duty of a human being to recognize and strive for, and that one cannot just believe whatever one wants to (again, a direct challenge to Protagoras). Even though he never conclusively proved the existence of the Forms, his standard inspired later philosophers and writers, notably Plotinus , who is credited with founding the Neo-Platonic school, which exerted significant influence on early Christianity .

Plato's Influence

The enormity of Plato's influence was recorded by Diogenes Laertius who, though often considered unreliable, as noted above, seems to provide an accurate assessment in this case:

He was the first author who wrote treatises in the form of dialogues, as Favorinus tells us in the eighth book of his Universal History. And he was also the first person who introduced the analytical method of investigation, which he taught to Leodamus of Thasos. He was also the first person in philosophy who spoke of antipodes, and elements, and dialectics, and actions ( poiêmata ) and oblong numbers, and plane surfaces, and the providence of God. He was likewise the first of the philosophers who contradicted the assertion of Lysias, the son of Cephalus, setting it out word for word in his Phaedrus. And he was also the first person who examined the subject of grammatical knowledge scientifically. And as he argued against almost every one who had lived before his time, it is often asked why he has never mentioned Democritus . ( Lives , XIX)

In this passage, Laertius is essentially claiming that Plato contradicted or significantly improved upon all of the accepted theories which came before him, and an important recognition of his influence on the world to the present day is summed up by the 20th-century philosopher Alfred North Whitehead who stated, "The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato" (Baird, 67).

This influence is perhaps best represented by Plato's most famous dialogue, Republic . Professor Forrest E. Baird writes, "There are few books in Western civilization that have had the impact of Plato's Republic - aside from the Bible , perhaps none" ( Ancient Philosophy , 68). Republic has been denounced as a treatise on fascism (by Karl Popper, among others) and praised as an eloquent and elevating work by scholars such as Bloom and Cornford. The dialogue begins with a consideration of what Justice means and goes on to develop the ideal, perfect State. Throughout the piece, Plato's ideas of Truth, Beauty, Goodness, and Justice are developed as they are explored by Socrates and his interlocutors.

Plato's Republic in ancient Greek

While the work has traditionally been understood as Plato's attempt to outline his model for the perfectly just and efficient society, an important point is often overlooked: the character of Socrates very clearly states in Book II. 369 that they are creating this 'city' as a means to better understand the function of the perfect 'soul'. The society which the men discuss, then, is not intended to reflect an actual physical political-social entity but rather to serve symbolically as a means by which a reader may recognize strengths and weaknesses in his or her own constitution.

The young poet and playwright Plato had been is always present in crafting the mature works of the philosopher Plato, and, in all the dialogues, a reader is expected to consider the work as carefully as one would a poem. Unlike his famous student Aristotle, Plato never clearly spells out the meaning of a dialogue for a reader. The reader is supposed to confront the truths which the dialogue presents individually. It is this combination of artistic talent with philosophical abstractions which has assured Plato's enduring value as a philosopher and artist.

Aristotle & Plato's Legacy

While Aristotle disagreed with Plato's Theory of Forms and many other aspects of his philosophy, he was profoundly affected by his teacher; most notably in his insistence on a right way of living and a proper way to pursue one's path in life (as outlined most clearly in Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics ). Aristotle would go on to tutor Alexander the Great and, in so doing, would help spread the brand of philosophy Plato had established to the known world.

Plato died at the age of 80 in 348/7 BCE, and leadership of the Academy passed to his nephew Speusippus. Tradition holds that the Academy endured for nearly 1,000 years as a beacon of higher learning until it was closed by the Christian Emperor Justinian in 529 in an effort to suppress pagan thought. Ancient sources, however, claim that the Academy was severely damaged in the First Mithridatic War in 88 BCE and almost completely destroyed in the Roman dictator Sulla 's sack of Athens in 86 BCE. Even so, some version of the Academy seems to have survived until it was closed by the adherents of the new religion of Christianity .

The School of Athens by Raphael

Plato's Academy was a wooded garden located near to one of his homes and not a university as one would picture such an institution today, and so the area underwent many changes both before and after Plato's school was established there and seems to have been a center of learning for centuries.

The Roman writer Cicero claims that Plato was not even the first to have a school in the gardens of Academia, but that Democritus (c. 460 BCE) was the original founder and leader of a philosophical school in the locale. It is also established that Simplicius was the head of a school in the gardens, which was still known as the Academy, as late as 560. Even so, in the present day, the site is known, and honored, as that of Plato's Academy, reflecting the importance of the philosopher's influence and respect for his legacy.

Subscribe to topic Related Content Books Cite This Work License

Bibliography

  • Academy of Plato , accessed 1 Dec 2016.
  • Baird, F.E. Philosophic Classics, Volume I Ancient Philosophy. Pearson, 2010.
  • Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, from Lives of the Philosophers, translated by C.D. Yonge , accessed 1 Dec 2016.
  • Plato and his dialogues : home , accessed 1 Dec 2016.
  • Plato. The Dialogues of Plato. Oxford University Press, 2000.
  • Robinson, J. M. An Introduction to Early Greek Philosophy. Houghton Mifflin School, 2000.
  • Stone, I.F. The Trial of Socrates. Anchor, 1989.
  • Waterfield, R. Plato of Athens: A Life in Philosophy. Oxford University Press, 2023.
  • Waterfield, R. The First Philosophers: The Presocratics and the Sophists. Oxford University Press, 2009.
  • Xenophon. Conversations of Socrates. Penguin Classics, 2000.

About the Author

Joshua J. Mark

Translations

We want people all over the world to learn about history. Help us and translate this definition into another language!

Questions & Answers

Who was plato, what was plato's main philosophy, what was plato's most famous theory, what was plato's central belief, related content.

Atlantis

Plato's Greater, Better World in The Last Days of Socrates

Plato: The Name and The Poet

Plato: The Name and The Poet

Greek Philosophy

Greek Philosophy

Plato's Euthyphro: An Overlooked Comedy

Plato's Euthyphro: An Overlooked Comedy

Free for the world, supported by you.

World History Encyclopedia is a non-profit organization. For only $5 per month you can become a member and support our mission to engage people with cultural heritage and to improve history education worldwide.

Recommended Books

     . He founded the Academy school in Athens. His works consisted of "dialogs" between and others. Like , he was interested in moral, not natural philosophy. He believed that the heads of government should be "philosopher kings" and developed a course of study stressing abstract thought for their education in the Plato advocated the "quadrivium" (the four math fields of study in the liberal arts), which starts with arithmetic, then progresses to plane geometry, solid geometry, and finally astronomy and harmonics. Plato believed that knowledge was "forgotten" at birth, and could be remembered. He saw the search for understanding as an attempt to gain pure knowledge, or "forms." In ), he said that he presented his , , , , , , . , ,

External Links

Cite this work.

Mark, J. J. (2023, April 03). Plato . World History Encyclopedia . Retrieved from https://www.worldhistory.org/plato/

Chicago Style

Mark, Joshua J.. " Plato ." World History Encyclopedia . Last modified April 03, 2023. https://www.worldhistory.org/plato/.

Mark, Joshua J.. " Plato ." World History Encyclopedia . World History Encyclopedia, 03 Apr 2023. Web. 15 Sep 2024.

License & Copyright

Submitted by Joshua J. Mark , published on 03 April 2023. The copyright holder has published this content under the following license: Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike . This license lets others remix, tweak, and build upon this content non-commercially, as long as they credit the author and license their new creations under the identical terms. When republishing on the web a hyperlink back to the original content source URL must be included. Please note that content linked from this page may have different licensing terms.

 MacTutor

Euclid of alexandria.

Not much younger than these [ pupils of Plato ] is Euclid, who put together the "Elements", arranging in order many of Eudoxus 's theorems, perfecting many of Theaetetus 's, and also bringing to irrefutable demonstration the things which had been only loosely proved by his predecessors. This man lived in the time of the first Ptolemy; for Archimedes , who followed closely upon the first Ptolemy makes mention of Euclid, and further they say that Ptolemy once asked him if there were a shorted way to study geometry than the Elements, to which he replied that there was no royal road to geometry. He is therefore younger than Plato 's circle, but older than Eratosthenes and Archimedes ; for these were contemporaries, as Eratosthenes somewhere says. In his aim he was a Platonist, being in sympathy with this philosophy, whence he made the end of the whole "Elements" the construction of the so-called Platonic figures.
Although it is no longer possible to rely on this reference, a general consideration of Euclid's works ... still shows that he must have written after such pupils of Plato as Eudoxus and before Archimedes .
.... Euclid did not work out the syntheses of the locus with respect to three and four lines, but only a chance portion of it ...
... most fair and well disposed towards all who were able in any measure to advance mathematics, careful in no way to give offence, and although an exact scholar not vaunting himself.
... someone who had begun to learn geometry with Euclid, when he had learnt the first theorem, asked Euclid "What shall I get by learning these things?" Euclid called his slave and said "Give him threepence since he must make gain out of what he learns".
Things which are equal to the same thing are equal to each other.
Greek mathematics can boast no finer discovery than this theory, which put on a sound footing so much of geometry as depended on the use of proportion.
... cumbersome enunciations, needless repetitions, and even logical fallacies. Apparently Euclid's exposition excelled only in those parts in which he had excellent sources at his disposal.
This wonderful book, with all its imperfections, which are indeed slight enough when account is taken of the date it appeared, is and will doubtless remain the greatest mathematical textbook of all time. ... Even in Greek times the most accomplished mathematicians occupied themselves with it: Heron , Pappus , Porphyry , Proclus and Simplicius wrote commentaries; Theon of Alexandria re-edited it, altering the language here and there, mostly with a view to greater clearness and consistency...
Our earliest glimpse of Euclidean material will be the most remarkable for a thousand years, six fragmentary ostraca containing text and a figure ... found on Elephantine Island in 1906 / 07 and 1907 / 08 ... These texts are early, though still more than 100 years after the death of Plato ( they are dated on palaeographic grounds to the third quarter of the third century BC ) ; advanced ( they deal with the results found in the "Elements" [ book thirteen ] ... on the pentagon, hexagon, decagon, and icosahedron ) ; and they do not follow the text of the Elements. ... So they give evidence of someone in the third century BC, located more than 500 miles south of Alexandria, working through this difficult material... this may be an attempt to understand the mathematics, and not a slavish copying ...
Almost from the time of its writing and lasting almost to the present, the Elements has exerted a continuous and major influence on human affairs. It was the primary source of geometric reasoning, theorems, and methods at least until the advent of non-Euclidean geometry in the 19 th century. It is sometimes said that, next to the Bible, the "Elements" may be the most translated, published, and studied of all the books produced in the Western world.
Since many things seem to conform with the truth and to follow from scientific principles, but lead astray from the principles and deceive the more superficial, [ Euclid ] has handed down methods for the clear-sighted understanding of these matters also ... The treatise in which he gave this machinery to us is entitled Fallacies, enumerating in order the various kinds, exercising our intelligence in each case by theorems of all sorts, setting the true side by side with the false, and combining the refutation of the error with practical illustration.

References ( show )

  • I Bulmer-Thomas, J E Murdoch, Biography in Dictionary of Scientific Biography ( New York 1970 - 1990) . See THIS LINK .
  • Biography in Encyclopaedia Britannica. http://www.britannica.com/biography/Euclid-Greek-mathematician
  • J L Berggren and R S D Thomas, Euclid's 'Phaenomena' : A translation and study of a Hellenistic treatise in spherical astronomy ( Princeton, NJ, 1996) .
  • H L L Busard, The Latin translation of the Arabic version of Euclid's 'Elements' commonly ascribed to Gerard of Cremona ( Leiden, 1984) .
  • H L L Busard ( ed. ) , The Mediaeval Latin translation of Euclid's 'Elements' : Made directly from the Greek ( Wiesbaden, 1987) .
  • C B Glavas, The place of Euclid in ancient and modern mathematics ( Athens, 1994) .
  • D H Fowler, The mathematics of Plato's academy : a new reconstruction ( Oxford, 1987) .
  • P M Fraser, Ptolemaic Alexandria (3 vols. ) ( Oxford, 1972) .
  • T L Heath, A history of Greek mathematics 1 ( Oxford, 1931) .
  • T L Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements (3 Volumes ) ( New York, 1956) .
  • J Itard, Les livres arithmétique d'Euclide ( Paris, 1962) .
  • S Ito, The medieval Latin translation of the 'Data' of Euclid ( Boston, Mass., 1980) .
  • C V Jones, The influence of Aristotle in the foundation of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Spanish ) , Mathesis. Mathesis 3 (4) (1987) , 375 - 387 (1988) .
  • G R Morrow ( ed. ) , A commentary on the first book of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Princeton, NJ, 1992) .
  • I Mueller, Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's 'Elements' ( Cambridge, Mass.-London, 1981) .
  • P Schreiber, Euklid : Biographien Hervorragender Naturwissenschaftler, Techniker und Mediziner ( Leipzig, 1987) .
  • H Wussing, Euclid, in H Wussing and W Arnold, Biographien bedeutender Mathematiker ( Berlin, 1983) .
  • R C Archibald, The first translation of Euclid's elements into English and its source, Amer. Math. Monthly 57 (1950) , 443 - 452 .
  • G Arrighi, Some indirect Latin versions of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Italian ) , Rend. Accad. Naz. Sci. XL Mem. Mat. (5) 11 (1) (1987) , 155 - 159 .
  • G Arrighi, Notes on Euclid's 'Elements' ( Italian ) , in Proceedings of the Study Meeting in Memory of Giuseppe Gemignani ( Modena, 1995) , 87 - 91 .
  • B Artmann, Euclid's 'Elements' and its prehistory, in On mathematics ( Edmonton, AB, 1992) , 1 - 47 .
  • G Aujac, Le rapport 'di isou' ( Euclide V, définition 17) : Définition, utilisation, transmission, Historia Math. 13 (4) (1986) , 370 - 386 .
  • N G Bashmakova, The arithmetical books of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Russian ) , Trudy Sem. MGU Istor. Mat. Istor.-Mat. Issledov. (1) (1948) , 296 - 328 .
  • J L Berggren and R S D Thomas, Mathematical astronomy in the fourth century B.C. as found in Euclid's 'Phaenomena', Physis Riv. Internaz. Storia Sci. ( N.S. ) 29 (1) (1992) , 7 - 33 .
  • A C Bowen, Euclid's 'Sectio canonis' and the history of Pythagoreanism, in Science and philosophy in classical Greece ( New York, 1991) , 167 - 187 .
  • C D Brownson, Euclid's 'Optics' and its compatibility with linear perspective, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 24 (3) (1981) , 165 - 194 .
  • M K Bucel', Rational numbers and quadratic irrationalities in Euclid's 'Elements' ( Russian ) , in History and methodology of the natural sciences XIV : Mathematics, mechanics ( Moscow, 1973) , 60 - 64 .
  • H E Burton, The optics of Euclid, J. Opt. Soc. Amer. 35 (1945) , 357 - 372 .
  • H L L Busard, The translation of the 'Elements' of Euclid from the Arabic into Latin by Hermann of Carinthia ( ? ) , Janus 54 (1967) , 1 - 140 .
  • J Cassinet, La relation d'ordre entre rapports dans les 'éléments' d'Euclide : développements au XVIIe siècle, in Histoire de fractions, fractions d'histoire ( Basel, 1992) , 341 - 350 .
  • G de Young, The Arabic textual traditions of Euclid's 'Elements', Historia Math. 11 (2) (1984) , 147 - 160 .
  • V M Eremina, Aristotle on transitional unprovable propositions and five general concepts of Euclid ( Russian ) , Istor.-Mat. Issled. 32 - 33 (1990) , 290 - 300 .
  • M Federspiel, Sur la définition euclidienne de la droite, in Mathématiques et philosophie de l'antiquité à l'âge classique ( Paris, 1991) , 115 - 130 .
  • E Filloy, Geometry and the axiomatic method. IV : Euclid ( Spanish ) , Mat. Ense nanza 9 (1977) , 14 - 21 .
  • R Fischler, A remark on Euclid II, 11 , Historia Math. 6 (4) (1979) , 418 - 422 .
  • M Folkerts, Adelard's versions of Euclid's 'Elements', in Adelard of Bath ( London, 1987) , 55 - 68 .
  • D H Fowler, An invitation to read Book X of Euclid's 'Elements', Historia Math. 19 (3) (1992) , 233 - 264 .
  • D H Fowler, Book II of Euclid's 'Elements' and a pre-Eudoxan theory of ratio. II, Sides and diameters, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 26 (3) (1982) , 193 - 209 .
  • D H Fowler, Book II of Euclid's 'Elements' and a pre-Eudoxan theory of ratio, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 22 (1 - 2) (1980) , 5 - 36 .
  • D H Fowler, Investigating Euclid's Elements, British J. Philos. Sci. 34 (1983) , 57 - 70 .
  • J-L Gardies, L'organisation du livre XII des 'éléments' d'Euclide et ses anomalies, Rev. Histoire Sci. 47 (2) (1994) , 189 - 208 .
  • J-L Gardies, La proposition 14 du livre V dans l'économie des 'éléments' d'Euclide, Rev. Histoire Sci. 44 (3 - 4) (1991) , 457 - 467 .
  • I Grattan-Guinness, Numbers, magnitudes, ratios, and proportions in Euclid's 'Elements' : how did he handle them?, Historia Math. 23 (4) (1996) , 355 - 375 .
  • A W Grootendorst, Geometrical algebra in Euclid ( Dutch ) , in Summer course 1991 : geometrical structures ( Amsterdam, 1991) , 1 - 26 .
  • H Guggenheimer, The axioms of betweenness in Euclid, Dialectica 31 (1 - 2) (1977) , 187 - 192 .
  • M D Hendy, Euclid and the fundamental theorem of arithmetic, Historia Math. 2 (1975) , 189 - 191 .
  • R Herz-Fischler, What are propositions 84 and 85 of Euclid's 'Data' all about?, Historia Math. 11 (1) (1984) , 86 - 91 .
  • J Hjelmslev, Über Archimedes' Grössenlehre, Danske Vid. Selsk. Mat.-Fys. Medd. 25 (15) (1950) .
  • J P Hogendijk, The Arabic version of Euclid's 'On divisions', in Vestigia mathematica ( Amsterdam, 1993) , 143 - 162 .
  • J P Hogendijk, Observations on the icosahedron in Euclid's 'Elements', Historia Math. 14 (2) (1987) , 175 - 177 .
  • J P Hogendijk, On Euclid's lost 'Porisms' and its Arabic traces, Boll. Storia Sci. Mat. 7 (1) (1987) , 93 - 115 .
  • W R Knorr, When circles don't look like circles : an optical theorem in Euclid and Pappus, Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 44 (4) (1992) , 287 - 329 .
  • W R Knorr, On the principle of linear perspective in Euclid's 'Optics', Centaurus 34 (3) (1991) , 193 - 210 .
  • W R Knorr, Euclid's tenth book : an analytic survey, Historia Sci. 29 (1985) , 17 - 35 .
  • W Knorr, Problems in the interpretation of Greek number theory : Euclid and the 'fundamental theorem of arithmetic', Studies in Hist. and Philos. Sci. 7 (4) (1976) , 353 - 368 .
  • W R Knorr, What Euclid meant : on the use of evidence in studying ancient mathematics, in Science and philosophy in classical Greece ( New York, 1991) , 119 - 163 .
  • K Kreith, Euclid turns to probability, Internat. J. Math. Ed. Sci. Tech. 20 (3) (1989) , 345 - 351 .
  • P Kunitzsch, 'The peacock's tail' : on the names of some theorems of Euclid's 'Elements', in Vestigia mathematica ( Amsterdam, 1993) , 205 - 214 .
  • T Lévy, Les 'éléments' d'Euclide : le texte et son histoire, in Mathématiques- philosophie et enseignement ( Yamoussoukro, 1995) , 10 - 13 .
  • Y Z Liang and C F Yao, Tracing the origins of Euclid's 'Elements of geometry' ( Chinese ) , Natur. Sci. J. Harbin Normal Univ. 3 (1) (1987) , 94 - 100 .
  • D E Loomis, Euclid : rhetoric in mathematics, Philos. Math. (2) 5 (1 - 2) (1990) , 56 - 72 .
  • R Lorch, Some remarks on the Arabic-Latin Euclid, in Adelard of Bath ( London, 1987) , 45 - 54 .
  • A I Markusevic, On the classification of irrationalities in Book X of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Russian ) , Trudy Sem. MGU Istor. Mat. Istor.-Mat. Issledov. (1) (1948) , 329 - 342 .
  • F A Medvedev, Corniform angles in Euclid's 'Elements' and Proclus's 'Commentaries' ( Russian ) , Istor.-Mat. Issled. 32 - 33 (1990) , 20 - 34 .
  • V N Molodsii, Was Euclid a follower of Plato? ( Russian ) , Trudy Sem. MGU Istor. Mat. Istor.-Mat. Issledov. (2) (1949) , 499 - 504 .
  • I Mueller, Euclid's 'Elements' and the axiomatic method, British J. Philos. Sci. 20 (1969) , 289 - 309 .
  • I Mueller, Sur les principes des mathématiques chez Aristote et Euclide, in Mathématiques et philosophie de l'antiquité à l'âge classique ( Paris, 1991) , 101 - 113 .
  • I Mueller, On the notion of a mathematical starting point in Plato, Aristotle, and Euclid, in Science and philosophy in classical Greece ( New York, 1991) , 59 - 97 .
  • T Murata, Quelques remarques sur le Livre X des 'Eléments' d'Euclide, Historia Sci. (2) 2 (1) (1992) , 51 - 60 .
  • T Murata, A tentative reconstruction of the formation process of Book XIII of Euclid's 'Elements', Comment. Math. Univ. St. Paul. 38 (1) (1989) , 101 - 127 .
  • V A Ogannisjan, Euclid ( Russian ) , Armjan. Gos. Ped. Inst. Sb. Naucn. Trud. Ser. Fiz.-Mat. Vyp. 3 (1966) , 69 - 80 .
  • S R Palmquist, Kant on Euclid : geometry in perspective, Philos. Math. (2) 5 (1 - 2) (1990) , 88 - 113 .
  • A E Raik, The tenth book of Euclid's 'Elements' ( Russian ) , Trudy Sem. MGU Istor. Mat. Istor.-Mat. Issledov. (1) (1948) , 343 - 384 .
  • K Saito, Debate : Proposition 14 of Book V of the 'Elements'---a proposition that remained a local lemma. Comment on : 'Proposition 14 of Book V in the organization of Euclid's 'Elements'', Rev. Histoire Sci. 47 (2) (1994) , 273 - 284 .
  • K Saito, Duplicate ratio in Book VI of Euclid's 'Elements', Historia Sci. (2) 3 (2) (1993) , 115 - 135 .
  • K Saito, Compounded ratio in Euclid and Apollonius, Historia Sci. 31 (1986) , 25 - 59 .
  • K Saito, Book II of Euclid's 'Elements' in the light of the theory of conic sections, Historia Sci. 28 (1985) , 31 - 60 .
  • P Schreiber,Euklid und die 'Elemente' aus heutiger Sicht, Mitt. Math. Ges. DDR 1 (1984) , 71 - 82 .
  • A Seidenberg, Did Euclid's 'Elements, Book I,' develop geometry axiomatically?, Arch. History Exact Sci. 14 (4) (1975) , 263 - 295 .
  • G Simon, Aux origines de la théorie des miroirs : sur l'authenticité de la 'Catoptrique' d'Euclide, Rev. Histoire Sci. 47 (2) (1994) , 259 - 272 .
  • E I Slavutin, Euclid's 'Data' ( Russian ) , Istor.-Mat. Issled. Vyp. 22 (1977) , 229 - 236 , 303 .
  • A Szab, The origins of Euclid's terminology. I ( Hungarian ) , Magyar Tud. Akad. Mat. Fiz. Oszt. Közl. 10 (1960) , 441 - 468 .
  • A Szabo, Ein Satz über die mittlere Proportionale bei Euklid ( Elem. III 36) , Comment. Math. Univ. St. Paul. 39 (1) (1990) , 41 - 51 .
  • A Szabo, Euclid's terms in the foundations of mathematics. II ( Hungarian ) , Magyar Tud. Akad. Mat. Fiz. Oszt. Közl. 11 (1961) , 1 - 46 .
  • C M Taisbak, Zeuthen and Euclid's 'Data' 86 algebra - or A lemma about intersecting hyperbolas?, Centaurus 38 (2 - 3) (1996) , 122 - 139 .
  • C M Taisbak, Elements of Euclid's 'Data', in On mathematics ( Edmonton, AB, 1992) , 135 - 171 .
  • W Theisen, Euclid, relativity, and sailing, Historia Math. 11 (1) (1984) , 81 - 85 .
  • W Theisen, A note on John of Beaumont's version of Euclid's 'De visu', British J. Hist. Sci. 11 (38 , 2) (1978) , 151 - 155 .
  • R Tobin, Ancient perspective and Euclid's 'Optics', J. Warburg Courtauld Inst. 53 (1990) , 14 - 41 .
  • G Toussaint, A new glance at Euclid's second proposition ( Spanish ) , Mathesis 9 (3) (1993) , 265 - 294 .
  • G Toussaint, A new look at Euclid's second proposition, Math. Intelligencer 15 (3) (1993) , 12 - 23 .
  • B Vahabzadeh, Two commentaries on Euclid's definition of proportional magnitudes, Arabic Sci. Philos. 4 (1) (1994) , 181 - 198 .
  • G Valabrega Elda, A hypothesis on the origin of Euclid's geometric algebra ( Italian ) , Boll. Un. Mat. Ital. A (5) 16 (1) (1979) , 190 - 200 .
  • B Vitrac, La Définition V. 8 des 'éléments' d'Euclide, Centaurus 38 (2 - 3) (1996) , 97 - 121 .
  • R J Wagner, Euclid's intended interpretation of superposition, Historia Math. 10 (1) (1983) , 63 - 70 .
  • A Weil, Who betrayed Euclid? : Extract from a letter to the editor, Arch. History Exact Sci. 19 (2) (1978 / 79) , 91 - 93 .
  • M Ya Vygodskii, Euclid's 'Elements' ( Russian ) , Trudy Sem. MGU Istor. Mat. Istor.-Mat. Issledov. (1) (1948) , 217 - 295 .

Additional Resources ( show )

Other pages about Euclid:

  • See Euclid on a timeline
  • Euclid on elementary astronomy
  • Bertrand Russell on Euclid
  • Micaiah John Muller Hill on Euclid
  • Euclid's geometric solution of a quadratic equation
  • The five regular polyhedra
  • The first page of The Elements in the translation by Campanus. ( This edition was published in 1482)
  • The five postulates ( taken from this edition )
  • Another page from this edition.
  • The first page of The Elements published in 1505 ( This was the first Latin translation directly from the Greek. )
  • Propositions 1 and 2 from The Elements Book I (1536)
  • Propositions 2 and 3 from The Elements Book I (1536)
  • Propositions 6 and 7 from The Elements Book I ( The Campanus translation 1482)
  • Propositions 27 and 28 from The Elements Book I ( The Campanus translation 1482)
  • A page from Optics ( an edition of 1557)
  • Proposition 2 of Elements ( Campani edition of 1482)
  • ... and its continuation,
  • Herbert Jennings Rose's Greek mathematical literature
  • Miller's postage stamps
  • Heinz Klaus Strick biography

Other websites about Euclid:

  • Dictionary of Scientific Biography
  • Encyclopaedia Britannica
  • J Poole ( Books I to IV of the Elements )
  • David Joyce ( The Elements )
  • Vatican exhibition,
  • G Don Allen ( An introduction to The Elements )
  • Kevin Brown ( A discussion of which propositions depend on which axioms )
  • Tufts University ( An on-line version of The Elements )
  • Euclides.org
  • Google books
  • Sci Hi blog
  • MathSciNet Author profile

Honours ( show )

Honours awarded to Euclid

  • Lunar features Crater Euclides
  • Popular biographies list Number 8

Cross-references ( show )

  • History Topics: A "Mary Somerville" visit to Burntisland
  • History Topics: A chronology of π
  • History Topics: A history of Zero
  • History Topics: A mathematical walk around Bologna
  • History Topics: Arabic mathematics : forgotten brilliance?
  • History Topics: Archimedes: Numerical Analyst
  • History Topics: Doubling the cube
  • History Topics: Euclid's definitions
  • History Topics: Greek astronomy
  • History Topics: How do we know about Greek mathematicians?
  • History Topics: How do we know about Greek mathematics?
  • History Topics: Infinity
  • History Topics: Light through the ages: Ancient Greece to Maxwell
  • History Topics: Mathematics and art - perspective
  • History Topics: Mathematics and the physical world
  • History Topics: Nine Chapters on the Mathematical Art
  • History Topics: Non-Euclidean geometry
  • History Topics: Paris Latin Quarter Walk
  • History Topics: Perfect numbers
  • History Topics: Prime numbers
  • History Topics: Quadratic, cubic and quartic equations
  • History Topics: The Golden ratio
  • History Topics: The real numbers: Pythagoras to Stevin
  • History Topics: The real numbers: Stevin to Hilbert
  • Famous Curves: Circle
  • Famous Curves: Ellipse
  • Famous Curves: Hyperbola
  • Famous Curves: Hyperbolic Spiral
  • Famous Curves: Parabola
  • Famous Curves: Straight Line
  • Societies: Hamburg Mathematical Society
  • Societies: Hungarian Academy
  • Societies: Mathematical Association
  • Student Projects: Indian Mathematics - Redressing the balance: Chapter 15
  • Other: 1924 ICM - Toronto
  • Other: 2009 Most popular biographies
  • Other: 4th April
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (A)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (B)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (C)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (D)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (E)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (F)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (G)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (H)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (I)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (L)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (M)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (O)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (P)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (Q)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (R)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (S)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (T)
  • Other: Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (V)
  • Other: Jeff Miller's postage stamps
  • Other: London Museums
  • Other: London individuals A-C
  • Other: Most popular biographies – 2024
  • Other: Other Institutions in central London
  • Other: Oxford Institutions and Colleges
  • Other: Oxford individuals
  • Other: Popular biographies 2018

IMAGES

  1. Plato

    plato mathematician biography

  2. Plato: Biography, Greek Philosopher, Quotes, Platonic Academy

    plato mathematician biography

  3. The Ancient Greek Philosopher Plato: His Life and Works

    plato mathematician biography

  4. Plato

    plato mathematician biography

  5. Plato Biography, Life, Interesting Facts

    plato mathematician biography

  6. Biography of Plato (ebook), Philip W. Ellison

    plato mathematician biography

VIDEO

  1. Plato biography

  2. #biography note of #plato #philosophyofeducation #philosophy

  3. Plato's Biography

  4. The Role of Mathematics in Philosophy

  5. Greek Philosopher Plato Detailed Description Part 1

  6. Brief History of Plato in English || Semester 2 English Major Course || Biography of Plato

COMMENTS

  1. Plato

    Plato (born 428/427 bce, Athens, Greece—died 348/347, Athens) was an ancient Greek philosopher, student of Socrates (c. 470-399 bce), teacher of Aristotle (384-322 bce), and founder of the Academy. He is best known as the author of philosophical works of unparalleled influence and is one of the major figures of Classical antiquity.

  2. Plato (427 BC

    D H Fowler, The mathematics of Plato's Academy : A new reconstruction (New York, 1990). W K C Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy 4 (1975), 5 (1978). F Lasserre, The birth of mathematics in the age of Plato (London, 1964). J Moravcsik, Plato and Platonism : Plato's conception of appearance and reality in ontology, epistemology, and ethics ...

  3. Plato

    Plato (Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, from Ancient Greek: πλατύς, romanized: platys, lit. 'broad') is actually a nickname.Although it is a fact that the philosopher called himself Platon in his maturity, the origin of this name remains mysterious.Platon was a fairly common name (31 instances are known from Athens alone), [8] but the name does not occur in Plato's known family line.

  4. PLATO

    Biography: What was Plato Known for. Plato (c.428-348 BCE) Although usually remembered today as a philosopher, Plato was also one of ancient Greece's most important patrons of mathematics. Inspired by Pythagoras, he founded his Academy in Athens in 387 BCE, where he stressed mathematics as a way of understanding more about reality.

  5. Plato: Biography, Greek Philosopher, Quotes, Platonic Academy

    Plato's impact on philosophy and the nature of humans has had a lasting impact far beyond his homeland of Greece. His work covered a broad spectrum of interests and ideas: mathematics, science and ...

  6. Plato Biography

    Plato was a classical Greek philosopher &mathematician who was one of the founders of Western philosophy. This biography profiles his childhood, life, works, achievements, ideas, contributions and some interesting facts.

  7. Plato on Mathematics

    Plato wrote The Republic in around 375 BC, so about 75 years before Euclid wrote The Elements. In this work Plato sets out his ideas about education. For this, he believes, one must study the five mathematical disciplines, namely arithmetic, plane geometry, solid geometry, astronomy, and harmonics. After mastering mathematics, then one can ...

  8. Plato

    Plato was a classical Greek philosopher and mathematician, influencing the realm of Western philosophy. He remained a diligent disciple of Socrates, and along with Socrates and his renowned student Aristotle, he found the first higher learning academy in Athens.Plato's philosophy is heavily influenced by Socrates, Parmenides, Heraclitus and Pythagoras.

  9. Plato Biography

    Plato Biography. Plato (423 BC - 348 BC) was a Classical Greek philosopher, mathematician, student of Socrates, writer of philosophical dialogues, and founder of the Academy in Athens - the first institution of higher learning in the Western world. Along with his mentor, Socrates and his student, Aristotle, Plato helped to lay the ...

  10. Plato Biography

    History >> Ancient Greece >> Biography. Occupation: Philosopher and Mathematician Born: 427 BC in Athens, Greece Died: 347 BC in Athens, Greece Best known for: Greek philosopher who helped form the foundation of Western philosophy and founded the Academy in Athens. Biography: Growing Up in Athens Plato grew up in the Greek city-state of Athens during the Classical Period of Ancient Greece.

  11. Life of Plato of Athens

    Subscribe to topic Subscribe to author. Plato of Athens (424 or 423 to 347 BCE) was an ancient Greek philosopher whose work is considered so important that he may be called the inventor of philosophy as we understand the term today. Some people would want to reserve that honor for his teacher, Socrates, but since Socrates wrote nothing himself ...

  12. Plato Biography

    Plato's early ambition to be a statesman was encouraged by Charmides and his friends, but when Plato observed that the thirty rulers of Athens, among them his relatives and associates, were even ...

  13. Plato ‑ Life, Philosophy & Quotes

    The Athenian philosopher Plato (c.428‑347 B.C.) is one of the most important figures of the Ancient Greek world and the entire history of Western thought. In his written dialogues he conveyed ...

  14. Life of Plato

    Plato (Ancient Greek: Πλάτων, Plátōn, "wide, broad-shouldered"; c. 428/427 - c. 348/347 BC) was an ancient Greek philosopher, the second of the trio of ancient Greeks including Socrates and Aristotle said to have laid the philosophical foundations of Western culture. [1]Little can be known about Plato's early life and education due to the very limited accounts.

  15. Plato (ca. 427-ca. 347 BC) -- from Eric Weisstein's World of ...

    Plato (ca. 427-ca. 347 BC) Greek philosopher who was a student and follower of Socrates. He founded the Academy school in Athens. His works consisted of "dialogs" between Socrates and others. Like Socrates, he was interested in moral, not natural philosophy. He believed that the heads of government should be "philosopher kings" and developed a ...

  16. Plato

    1. Plato's central doctrines. Many people associate Plato with a few central doctrines that are advocated in his writings: The world that appears to our senses is in some way defective and filled with error, but there is a more real and perfect realm, populated by entities (called "forms" or "ideas") that are eternal, changeless, and in some sense paradigmatic for the structure and ...

  17. Plato

    Plato (427—347 B.C.E.) Plato is one of the world's best known and most widely read and studied philosophers. He was the student of Socrates and the teacher of Aristotle, and he wrote in the middle of the fourth century B.C.E. in ancient Greece.Though influenced primarily by Socrates, to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato's writings, he was also ...

  18. Philosophy of mathematics

    Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of mathematics and its relationship with other human activities.. Major themes that are dealt with in philosophy of mathematics include: Reality: The question is whether mathematics is a pure product of human mind or whether it has some reality by itself.; Logic and rigor ...

  19. Biography of Plato

    Biography. Plato is one of the most brilliant and far-reaching writers to have ever lived. Our very conception of philosophy—of rigorous thinking concerning the true situation of man, the nature of the whole, and the perplexity of being—owes a great debt to his work. No area of inquiry seems foreign to him: his writings investigate ethics ...

  20. Plato

    Plato also made significant contributions to the field of mathematics. He is credited with the discovery of the five Platonic solids and is known for his definition of a right angle. In addition, he made important contributions to the study of ethics and political philosophy, proposing the idea of a philosopher-king, a ruler who is guided by ...

  21. Plato

    Plato (l. 424/423 to 348/347 BCE) is the pre-eminent Greek philosopher, known for his Dialogues and for founding his Academy in Athens, traditionally considered the first university in the Western world.Plato was a student of Socrates and featured his former teacher in almost all of his dialogues which form the basis of Western philosophy.. The son of Ariston of the deme Colytus, Plato had two ...

  22. Plato: The Academy

    While it is probable that Plato associated with other philosophers, including the Athenian mathematician Theaetetus, in the Academy as early as the late 390s (see Nails 2009: 5-6; Nails 2002: 277; Thesleff 2009: 509-518 with Proclus's Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements, Book 2, Chapter IV for more details on Theaetetus's ...

  23. Plato Tiburtinus

    Plato Tiburtinus (Latin: Plato Tiburtinus, "Plato of Tivoli"; fl. 12th century) was a 12th-century Italian mathematician, astronomer and translator who lived in Barcelona from 1116 to 1138. [1] He is best known for translating Hebrew and Arabic documents into Latin, and was apparently the first to translate information on the astrolabe (an astronomical instrument) from Arabic.

  24. Euclid (325 BC

    Biography. Euclid of Alexandria is the most prominent mathematician of antiquity best known for his treatise on mathematics The Elements. The long lasting nature of The Elements must make Euclid the leading mathematics teacher of all time. However little is known of Euclid's life except that he taught at Alexandria in Egypt.