Models as Fundamental Entities in Set Theory: A Naturalistic and Practice-based Approach

  • Original Research
  • Open access
  • Published: 19 August 2022
  • Volume 89 , pages 1683–1710, ( 2024 )

Cite this article

You have full access to this open access article

case study of set theory

  • Carolin Antos   ORCID: orcid.org/0000-0002-9998-4710 1  

1786 Accesses

1 Altmetric

Explore all metrics

This article addresses the question of fundamental entities in set theory. It takes up J. Hamkins’ claim that models of set theory are such fundamental entities and investigates it using the methodology of P. Maddy’s naturalism, Second Philosophy. In accordance with this methodology, I investigate the historical case study of the use of models in the introduction of forcing, compare this case to contemporary practice and give a systematic account of how set-theoretic practice can be said to introduce models as new entities. In conclusion, I argue for a view that takes both sets and models to be fundamental entities in set theory.

Similar content being viewed by others

case study of set theory

The role of syntactic representations in set theory

case study of set theory

On Set Theories and Modernism

case study of set theory

Interview With a Set Theorist

Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.

1 Introduction

The debate between a multiverse and universe conception of set theory has garnered a lot of attention in recent years. Footnote 1 This debate has its origins in the first independence results (Gödel, 1940 ; Cohen, 1963a ) and in the categoricity results for second-order set theory (Zermelo, 1930 ). These results show not only that important mathematical sentences can be undecidable in a chosen axiomatization of mathematics Footnote 2 but they also raise the fundamental question whether such sentences have determinate truth-values. The universe/multiverse debate provides a way to capture a fundamental disagreement on how to answer this question: very roughly, the universist view (universism, for short) claims that there is one intended model of set theory, the universe V , that decides the truth value of such statements. The multiversist view (multiversism, for short) denies this by claiming that we have to accept a multiplicity of models of set theory on equal footing.

One of the most frequently discussed multiverse views is the one of Hamkins ( 2012 ), who advocates a quite radical position. One of his central claims is that the development of set theory in the last decades has led to models becoming the fundamental objects of set theory. This stands in contrast to the classical account of set theory as being solely about sets. Hamkins sees this classical account, which focuses on set-related practices from a universe viewpoint, as not taking into consideration the modern model-practices of set theorists (Hamkins, 2012 , p. 418). The classical account can counter this by subsuming the model-related practices under the set-related ones, pointing out that, as models are themselves sets, they are already included in the study of sets. Footnote 3

In the last years this particular debate about fundamental entities seems to have stalled, branching out instead to other aspects of the universe/multiverse discussion. In this article I want to take up the question of fundamental entities in set theory yet again, using a methodological and practice-based approach. Footnote 4 Under this approach, methodology provides the basis for discussions about ontology; by analysing the former in detail, I hope to likewise provide the basis for further research in the latter, thus also delivering new input for the universe/multiverse debate.

In the article, I investigate Hamkins’ claim from the point of view of Second Philosophy. This is a naturalistic program developed by Penelope Maddy that targets mathematics in general and set theory in particular. Footnote 5 Both Hamkins and Maddy base their investigations on the underlying practice of set theory, but while Hamkins mostly reflects on it as a practicing set theorist, Maddy develops a general framework for investigating practice and drawing philosophical conclusions from methodologically informative parts of it.

Interestingly, despite the fact that both of them focus on practice, Maddy and Hamkins come to very different foundational conclusions: Hamkins endorses a radical multiverse, whereas Maddy argues for a universe view (Maddy, 2017 ). At the same time, both positions have been criticized with regards to their arguments from practice: Ternullo ( 2019 ) and Rittberg ( 2016 ) argue that Maddy neglects certain parts of set-theoretic practice in her study of set-theoretic methodology, in particular domains that are connected to multiverse-flavoured mathematics. And while Hamkins focuses on these kinds of model-related practices in set theory, a detailed methodological argument of why these practices are so fundamental as to be considered on a par with the set-related practices is missing. Footnote 6

With regards to these points, the present article has several aims: In investigating set-theoretic practice with the methods of Second Philosophy, I will strengthen Hamkins’ observations and provide a complete argument for considering models as fundamental entities. To do this, I investigate the model-building practice in set theory from a historical and systematic point of view. I will break down this practice to one of its underlying methods, namely, the method of introducing models as entities; and use the account provided by Second Philosophy to argue for the claim that this method is of justificatory value for the philosophy of set theory. At the same time, Maddy ( 2011 )’s argument for sets as fundamental entities still holds. Therefore the argument provided here will give support to a position that recognizes both sets and models as fundamental entities in modern set theory.

Furthermore, I also address the criticisms that both accounts face in the wake of the way they handle practice by supplying a more detailed argument for (a version of) Hamkins’ conclusions regarding a change in set-theoretic practice; and by broadening Maddy’s considerations to parts of the practice that seem to give rise to a multiverse view. Finally, this conclusion will show that both Hamkins’ and Maddy’s accounts of practice can interact in a fruitful manner when focusing on methodology, despite their main proponents’ disagreement on foundational issues. While a detailed discussion on how the methodological results of this paper inform the foundational and ontological debate has to be left to future research, I will point out some possible implications for Maddy’s and Hamkins’ positions at the end of the article.

The structure of the paper is as follows: I will start by introducing the question of models as fundamental entities and presenting the main methodology of my analysis in Sect.  2 : First, I outline the approach from Second Philosophy needed to carry out my investigation (Sect.  2.1 ); and, second, I discuss in detail what the method of introducing something as a new entity means for Second Philosophy (Sect.  2.2 ). Then, I discuss the concrete example from practice I will study, namely the use of models in set theory, in Sect.  3 . I give an overview of the model-related practices in set theory (Sect.  3.1 ) and analyse it in depth in the historical setting of the introduction of forcing (Sect.  3.2 ); compare this to its contemporary setting (Sect.  3.3 ); and, finally, argue from the perspective of Second Philosophy that we can accept the method of introducing models as fundamental entities as part of set-theoretic methodology (Sect.  3.4 ). Sect.  4 provides an outlook on how these results from methodology may affect foundational questions in the universe/multiverse debate and addresses some open questions for further research.

2 Investigating Models: How and Why?

Hamkins’ claim about models as fundamental entities has been voiced most explicitly in Hamkins ( 2012 ):

A large part of set theory over the past half-century has been about constructing as many different models of set theory as possible, often to exhibit precise features or to have specific relationships with other models. [...] As a result, the fundamental objects of study in set theory have become the models of set theory [...]. While group theorists study groups, ring theorists study rings and topologists study topological spaces, set theorists study the models of set theory. (Hamkins, 2012 , p. 417)

Hamkins bases his conclusions on his observations of set-theoretic practice: He refers to the development of set theory in the last decades to make the point that working with models has become one of the central practices of set theory. Hamkins also provides further evidence for his claim by pointing out the massive increase of set-theoretic work done not only within the models of set theory, but also about the models themselves, i. e. how they behave and relate to one another. Hamkins ( 2012 ) gives examples for such a way of using models in recent research programs, such as the modal logic of forcing (e.g. Hamkins & Löwe, 2005 ) and set-theoretic geology (e.g. Reitz, 2007 ).

However, Hamkins does not provide a full argument from set-theoretic practice. Footnote 7 Instead, he observes from practice that models are fundamental entities and takes this as evidence for his actual main claim, namely that each model that is set-theoretic enough “exists independently in [a] Platonic sense” (Hamkins, 2012 , p. 417). Consequently, the main discussions in the universe/multiverse debate mention the question of fundamental entities only as an aside and focus instead on other parts of Hamkins’ argument. Koellner ( 2013 ) for example only mentions the question of fundamental entities in passing, in the broader context of the discussion about set theory as a formal or abstract theory. Overall, Koellner’s article is devoted to raising problems for the broad multiverse view in general and Hamkins’ arguments for it in particular, discussing issues such as possible multiversist background theories, the ontology of different accounts of forcing and the (in)determinateness of truth values of independent sentences. Footnote 8 All of these are major points of discussion in the universe/multiverse debate.

In the present article, however, I want to come back to the claim that models are fundamental entities in set-theoretic practice. I want to provide a full argument of this claim by using the framework of Maddy’s Second Philosophy. This naturalistic account is particularly suited for the purposes of this article as it places a major emphasis on the analysis of mathematical practice and provides a detailed and tested tool for such an analysis, in particular with respect to set theory. For instance, Maddy ( 2011 , Ch.II.2) analyses the introduction of sets as fundamental entities and I will use this as a template for my analysis of models. In the following, I will therefore concentrate on a naturalistic investigation of set-theoretic practice; the foundational and ontological questions of the universe/multiverse debate will therefore not be discussed in detail. Yet I hope that the analysis of methodology can eventually be used to inform these broader debates.

To set-up my investigation into practice and methodology, I will first give an account of the naturalistic framework of Second Philosophy (Sect.  2.1 ) and then apply it to the question of models considered here (Sect.  2.2 ).

2.1 Set-Theoretic Practice and Second Philosophy

Penelope Maddy developed her account of Second Philosophy as a form of naturalism in the philosophy of mathematics, with a special focus on the philosophy of set theory. Footnote 9 Here the Second Philosopher is interested in two main questions: What is the right methodology for a certain area of pure mathematics; and why are these the proper methods, leading us to traditional philosophical questions in ontology, etc. Footnote 10

To answer the first question about methodology, Maddy bases her investigation on the practice of the discipline which she studies via means-ends relations: We isolate a practice of a certain area of mathematics and investigate whether it is an “effective means to particular desirable ends” (Maddy, 1997 , p. 194). Here one identifies a certain method in the practice of (some area of) mathematics and then examines if there are goals in the practice for which this method serves as an effective means. Considering the method and goal as a means-ends relation, one can finally judge if it is “rational” (in Maddy’s words) to accept the method to be part of the discipline’s methodology. Second Philosophy therefore ‘selects’ parts of the practice that can be argued to be part of its methodology.

Maddy also gives examples of which parts of the practice will not be part of methodology, such as “heuristics”. One such example is Dedekind’s famous remark about natural numbers as “free creations of the human mind”. Maddy posits that the Second Philosopher should treat such remarks “as colorful asides or heuristic aides, but not as part of the evidential structure of the subject” (Maddy, 2011 , pp. 52–53). Heuristics are still an important part of doing mathematics, e.g. by providing intuition for reasoning, but—according to Maddy—they have no justificatory value for broader philosophical questions. Footnote 11

After getting clear about methodology, the Second Philosopher aims to answer “the second group of questions—about the nature of set-theoretic activity, about its subject matter and the reliability of its methods—in a way that [...] respects the actual methods of set theory” (Maddy, 2011 , p. 59). For Maddy this leads to a rejection of what she calls “Robust Realism”, as this position does not arise in mathematical reasoning itself (Maddy, 2011 , p. 59). She then discusses a realist alternative, dubbed “Thin Realism”, which is “a version of realism that genuinely accounts for the nature of set-theoretic language and practice, that respects the actual structure of set-theoretic justifications” (Maddy, 2011 , p. 61); and a non-realist position called “Arealism”. As an Arealist, one focuses on the effectiveness and fruitfulness of set theory. As Maddy writes, an arealist Second Philosopher “would see no reason to think that sets exist or that set-theoretic claims are true [...], but she does regard set theory, and pure mathematics with it, as a spectacularly successful enterprise, unlike any other.” (Maddy, 2011 , p. 89). Footnote 12 One of the most interesting outcomes of this discussion is that a Second Philosopher endorsing Thin Realism and another endorsing Arealism do agree on set theoretic practice and methodology (see Maddy, 2011 , Ch.IV.4 and Ch.IV.5). From this Maddy concludes that Second Philosophy really supports what she calls a “post-metaphysical” form of objectivity (Maddy, 2011 , p. 116). So while the study of methodology is necessary for the investigation of further philosophical questions, metaphysical question do not have to be necessarily addressed. Instead, Maddy ( 2011 , p. 116) proposes “a form of objectivity in mathematics that doesn’t depend on the existence of mathematical objects or the truth of mathematical statements, or even on the non-existence of mathematical objects or the rejection of mathematical claims.” But no matter how and if one approaches these second type of questions, the study of the first type is essential to the Second Philosopher’s endeavour. Footnote 13

The investigation I aim at in this article is therefore firmly set in the first group of questions about the methodology of set theory. I want to show that introducing models as fundamental entities is part of set-theoretic methodology and not just a heuristic aid. Being about methodology, this claim then becomes eligible to inform further philosophical questions, namely the questions in the second group. Footnote 14 Showing that something is part of set-theoretic methodology is therefore of major significance for studying questions of e.g. truth and ontology of set theory. But before we can investigate what the introduction of models as fundamental entities might mean or imply for questions of this second type, we have to show that they are indeed relevant for these kinds of questions in the first place—and that means showing that they are part of set-theoretic methodology. In this article I therefore focus on questions of methodology; I will give an outlook on possible foundational implications of my methodological investigation in Sect.  4 .

Let us now look more closely at the method of means-ends relations as the deciding factor about which parts of practice count as methodology. Candidates for means comprise a variety of things that mathematicians use to aim at and eventually reach goals in their mathematical work. These can be their mathematical bread-and-butter, such as ‘using certain kinds of reasoning (proof types, but also analogies etc.)’, ‘using certain entities (e.g. in definitions)’ or larger-scale, such as ‘re-structuring parts of the subject area’. Maddy ( 2011 , Ch.II.2) gives several case studies for means such as ‘introducing new entities’ and ‘adding new axioms’.

Goals that serve as ends are typically ordinary mathematical goals such as ‘proving a certain theorem’, ‘developing a new technique’ or ‘give an appropriate definition’; but they can also be foundational goals such as ‘providing a court of final appeal for claims of existence and proof in classical mathematics’ (Maddy, 2007 , p. 354). Footnote 15 To give an example, the goal of “unifying diverse mathematical phenomena into one coherent theory” has foundational relevance for the introduction of a group as a new entity in modern algebra (Maddy, 2007 , pp. 352–353). For set theory, the pursuit of the foundational goal of a unified basis can be found in Dedekind’s work on the construction of the real numbers as well as later work by Cantor, Zermelo and others.

It is important to note that Maddy, working in the Second Philosophy framework, does not investigate such means as part of the philosophical debate about e.g. foundations, but as part of the mathematical practice in set theory. It is therefore crucial that also the foundational goals can be traced back to set-theoretic practice. Second Philosophy does not consider philosophical goals as proper foundational goals unless they were made mathematically tangible by the historical actors. Footnote 16

Let me exemplify this procedure by presenting one of Maddy’s case studies that lies very close to the heart of what I aim at in this article: Maddy ( 2011 , II.2.(i)) discusses the method of ‘introducing sets as new entities’, examining the method in the context of one of the first times it arose in the practice, namely when Cantor first uses sets as distinctive entities in his mathematical work on derived point sets (Cantor, 1872 ). In this context Cantor’s goal is to prove a general theorem on representing functions by trigonometric series. As a goal in the methodological perspective, Maddy positively evaluates the resulting means-ends relation: “a new entity—a set—has been introduced as an effective means toward an explicit and concrete mathematical goal: extending our understanding of trigonometric representations” (Maddy, 2011 , p. 42).

In this example (as well as in the others given in Maddy, 2011 ), historical case studies constitute the backbone of Second Philosophy’s investigation into methods. Such case studies provide the Second Philosopher with the method and goals to formulate the relevant means-ends relation and serve as evidence for the acceptance or rejection of the method under consideration. It is an essential part of Maddy’s philosophy that the Second Philosopher justifies her acceptance of means extrinsically , i.e. connected to the usefulness, fruitfulness and mathematical relevance of the method. Footnote 17 If this can be shown, the means can be accepted as a method and we are confronted with an instance of a practice that can now be considered to be an integral part of the methodology of the relevant mathematical field.

2.2 Introducing Models as Fundamental Entities

Each time a definition of the type “Call x the mathematical object that has the following properties ...” is given, we have prima facie evidence that a new entity was introduced and this is often done to serve a specific mathematical purpose, thus supplying the Second Philosopher with ends for a means-ends relation that she can then investigate. This kind of definition is, then, a marker for the introduction of a (new ) entity. However, in each mathematical subdiscipline, there are some such definitions that seem to be more fundamental to the practice of the discipline than others.

Maddy discusses one such a fundamental occurrence, namely the case of sets as new entities in the work of Cantor (Maddy, 2011 , Ch.II.2.(i)) and Dedekind (Maddy, 2011 , Ch.II.2.(ii)). Here Maddy employs several criteria that show that sets were indeed introduced as new entities, building on Cantor’s and Dedekind’s original work as well as drawing from historical studies, in particular (Ferreirós, 2007 ) and (Avigad, 2006 ). In the following, I discuss these criteria and collect them into two groups for the introduction of new entities. In Sect.  3.4 I will then check them against the case of models in set-theoretic practice.

The key phrase used in the case study of sets is that the new entities are treated as entities in their own right . Footnote 18 Maddy takes the following as criteria for such a treatment: they are susceptible to general mathematical operations (Maddy, 2011 , pp. 42, 43); one is encouraged to speak about ‘arbitrary’ such entities; Footnote 19 and the way in which they are used is independent of the way in which they are represented (see in particular the quotes of (Avigad, 2006 ) in Maddy ( 2011 , p. 43); also Maddy ( 2011 , p. 45)). For example, Cantor’s treatment of point sets as he operates on them by taking the derived set and generally employing the “language of sets” (Ferreirós (2007) as cited in Maddy, 2011 , p. 42) satisfies these criteria. Another example is Dedekind’s work that defines sets of numbers independent from the previously used construction via algorithms (Maddy, 2011 , p. 43).

In her discussion of Dedekind’s work, Maddy ( 2011 , pp. 44–45) also points at broader issues that accompany the introduction of new entities: Such an introduction can bring about new styles of reasoning; attempt new types of foundations; provide new kinds of explanations; and work towards a superior presentation of previously known facts or theories, where superiority can take on different forms such as improved generality, unification, rigor or simplicity. Footnote 20 These broader issues can be the explicit target of the mathematical work under consideration, such as in the case of Dedekind, who was aiming to give a “perfectly rigorous foundation for the principles of infinitesimal analysis” (Dedekind, as cited in Maddy ( 2011 , p. 44)), but they can also be part of later implications of the mathematical work, as in the case of Cantor (Maddy, 2011 , CH.II.2.(i)).

It important to note that these broader criteria do not point exclusively to foundational questions. Providing a coherent foundational theory certainly is a major goal, yet other questions also play a decisive role in the case of the introduction of fundamental entities: Finding new styles of reasoning or explanations in the practice provides evidence for new entities and the broader implications they can have; they also highlight how the means under consideration are functionally entrenched in the practice apart from giving rise to foundational theories. In the case studies of Maddy ( 2011 ) these criteria were already satisfied before Cantor (and later Zermelo, Fraenkel and others) provided a foundational theory of set theory. If these criteria are also fulfilled for the case of models, it supports the case of their introduction as new, fundamental entities.

For clarity’s sake, I will subdivide these criteria into two groups: The first group, concerned with questions of representation of and operation on entities, consists of methodological explications. They focus on the changes with regards to the entities themselves and I will call them specific criteria . The second group consists of consequences for the whole area of mathematics they appear in; and/or more widespread phenomena that go hand-in-hand with the introduction of these new entities. These focus on questions of reasoning, explanation, rigor and foundations and I will call them broad criteria .

As it is apparent from Maddy ( 2011 , Ch.II.2)’s discussion, the case of introducing sets as new entities satisfies all of these criteria. To this I would like to add an aspect that is not explicitly mentioned in Maddy’s work but, I think, is implicitly included: It seems reasonable to say that episodic uses of some means, as surfaced in the historical case studies, cannot be enough to concede them status as general methods of the discipline under consideration. The means under consideration should also be shown to have circulated and spread through sufficiently large parts of the community as to make them relevant to general practice. Footnote 21

To test this general relevance for methodology, I propose to consider contemporary practice in the discipline to see if the method analysed in the case study remains to be important. The reason why Maddy does not explicitly consider current research in the study of sets might be that the relevance and importance of sets for set-theoretic practice today is so obvious it does not need mentioning. This reason also suggests itself when comparing the case of sets to the case study of determinacy (also given by Maddy ( 2011 , Ch.ii.2.(iv))): Although there is a strong line of argument for the methodological and foundational relevance of projective determinacy, it is not as obvious and beyond dispute as the case of sets. Maddy therefore presents not only one case study of the use of projective determinacy, but gives a more extensive discussion following the historical development of (projective) determinacy until very recent work (e.g. Woodin, 2001 ). I therefore think that especially in controversial cases, such as the case of models as fundamental entities, contemporary practice should be considered carefully and I believe this to be in the spirit of Second Philosophy.

Taking this framework of specific and broader criteria for granted, it is natural to ask whether we cannot make the same case for other entities in the practice, such as functions, ordinals, etc. Footnote 22 If we want to make such a case, we have to provide detailed case studies for each of these entities along the same lines as we do here for models. Conducting such case studies is outside the purview of this article, but let me briefly give some prima facie considerations as to why we can expect these case studies to fail for the respective cases of functions and ordinals: Footnote 23 First, in the case of functions it might not be possible to find the appropriate means. Functions were present in set-theoretic practice from the beginning and have a rigorous definition as a certain kind of set. Differently from models, however, their treatment in set-theoretic practice has not changed since the beginning of set theory. There are simply no common, general practices in which means like “introducing functions as new, fundamental entities in set-theoretic methodolgy” could be investigated; their treatment and use in set theory has remained quite stable and unchanging. In particular, there is no comparable discussion Footnote 24 to what we have seen in the case of models at the beginning of Sect.  2 , at least not in set-theoretic practice. Footnote 25

Second, let us turn to the case of ordinals: Here, we can find the means relevant to build a case study, namely the introduction of ordinals by Cantor ( 1883 ). But problems present themselves when checking the specific and broad criteria. In particular, I submit that ordinals aren’t used independently of the way in which they are represented; instead, they are tied to their representation as specific kinds of sets. Also, I don’t know of attempts to provide foundations for set theory with ordinals as fundamental objects on par with sets (or perhaps instead of sets). Footnote 26 I hope that it becomes clear from these examples that the methodology of Second Philosophy for introducing new entities is not a dispensation to view all kinds of entities from the practice as fundamental. Even very useful concepts such as functions or ordinals in set theory can still not be regarded as fundamental entities according to the methodology presented here.

Taking this and last section’s discussion together, we can now see more clearly what it means to argue for models as fundamental entities: First, we have to show that the corresponding method of introducing models as new entities is an effective means to some mathematical or foundational end by checking the specific and broad criteria given above. Furthermore, we have to confirm the stability of the entities in question, the lasting effect of its introduction in contemporary practice. Only if we succeed on both accounts, we have shown that this method is part of set-theoretic methodology. This closes the gap between what we have observed in set-theoretic practice and what is in the purview of methodological consideration (and therefore is not only part of heuristics).

In the next section I will therefore first investigate the historical case study of the introduction of forcing (Sect.  3.2 ), compare the findings of the case study against contemporary practice (Sect.  3.3 ) and then show that the criteria given in this section are fulfilled for the case of models (Sect.  3.4 ).

3 The Case Study of Models and Forcing

To conduct our investigation into the model-building practice in accordance with the approach described in Sect.  2.1 , in this section I will investigate the means of introducing models of set theory as a new type of fundamental entity in set-theoretic practice. I will analyse if this means is effective in achieving a mathematical end to be found in the practice, namely, the goal of proving various independence and consistency results . Footnote 27

I conduct this investigation in four steps: First, I provide an outline of how and why the practice with models changed in the last decades and how this is connected to the forcing technique (Sect.  3.1 ). Then I give an detailed study of in the historical development of forcing by Paul Cohen in Sect.  3.2 as forcing is one of the most productive model-building tools set theorists ever developed, leading to far-reaching changes within the discipline. Footnote 28 In a third step, I will give a systematic account of how models are used in forcing, incorporating the relevant contemporary practice (Sect.  3.3 ). To conclude, I will give a measure of its fundamentality in methodology by discussing the criteria developed in Sect.  2.2 and show that the use of models satisfies them (Sect.  3.4 ).

3.1 The Rise of Models as Fundamental Entities

The construction of different set-theoretic models originally developed when set theorists began to investigate statements likely to be independent. To prove whether a mathematical statement A is independent from some axiomatization (usually ZF or ZFC ), one has to show that the statement as well as its negation are consistent with the chosen axiomatization. This is usually done by building a model for each scenario, i.e. a model for \(ZFC+A\) and another for \(ZFC+\lnot A\) .

Up to the late 1950s, model-building was carried out mostly at a local level, meaning that specific models were built for specific purposes, yet the methods by which they were built was tied to very specific outcomes. Examples are the construction of the constructible universe, Gödel’s L ( 1940 ); von Neumann’s model of well-founded sets ( 1925 ); and models with urelements (Zermelo, 1930 ; Mirimanoff, 1917 ; Fraenkel, 1922 ). During this time, important partial independence results were achieved, in particular showing that the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis are consistent with ZF through the construction of Gödel’s model L . Footnote 29 However, most of these model-building methods were so specialized as to give rise only to specific consistency results and could not be generalized to tackle different mathematical statements or provide full independence results.

As an example, consider the construction method for Gödel’s model L : Gödel’s construction is based on the idea that instead of building a model that consists of all the arbitrary sets that are usually considered, we only allow sets that are definable via formulas. The model L is then built up by transfinite induction: We start with the empty set and then add step-by-step the sets that are definable over the model already built. Footnote 30 Gödel proved that L is a model of ZF plus an additional axiom, the Axiom of Constructibility. This axiom states that every set is constructible, i.e. \(V=L\) . L is an important model in set theory, leading to much mathematical research (see for example Jensen, 1972 ; Devlin, 2017 ). However, the construction method itself is in a certain sense limited when it comes to model building, because it does not give rise to a more general procedure allowing to construct other models of set theory. If we build up a model via definable sets, we simply get L (or with a similar construction we can produce L [ A ] for some parameter A ). We can use this way of building a model to show that CH is consistent with ZF (and indeed CH follows from the axiom \(V=L\) ), but we cannot vary the construction in a way that shows the same for not-CH. Therefore, with regards to CH, the method of building a model via definable sets can only show us one part of the independence of CH. Footnote 31

This state of affairs changed drastically in the 1960s, when more general model-building techniques were developed, most important among them Paul Cohen’s forcing technique (Cohen, 1963a , 1964 ). Footnote 32 A major strength of forcing is its wide applicability, which is due to the general setup of the technique: with forcing, one is able to start from some model of (a fragment of) ZF ( C ), Footnote 33 the so-called ground model, and produce a different model, called the extension, that satisfies additional statements (such as not-CH). Forcing takes care of all the problematic issues involved in such a construction by making sure that the extension will again be a model of ZF ( C ) and that truth in it can be “seen” up to a certain point in the ground model Footnote 34 . Forcing allows a lot of variations regarding the kind of additional statements which hold in the extension, making this a matter of precise mathematical choices in the ground model. One major possibility of variance lies in the choice of the partial order considered in the ground model: For example, in Cohen forcing it consists of the finite partial functions from \(\omega\) to 2 ordered by reverse inclusion. The new model produced by this forcing then contains a partial function from \(\omega\) to 2 that was not an element of the ground model and therefore gives rise to a subset of the natural numbers (or a real) that does not belong to the ground model. In this way we can add “new” reals to ground models, which can lead to a failure of CH . However we can choose the partial order quite differently: In Sacks forcing its elements are certain perfect trees, where the extension model produced is minimal in the sense that no smaller extension of the ground model can be produced. In a yet different form of forcing, called the Lévy collapse, the elements can be finite sequences of ordinals less than some cardinal \(\kappa\) , resulting in a model where \(\kappa\) is collapsed to \(\omega\) ; and there are many other forms of forcing.

In this way we can use forcing to both produce models that satisfy not-CH as well as models that satisfy CH. Indeed, with forcing and other techniques like inner models, a wide range of statements were shown to be independent. Of note is also that independence results come up not only in the area of set theory, but in other areas of mathematics as well, such as algebra (e.g. Whitehead’s Problem in group theory, which was shown to be undecidable by Shelah ( 1974 )), or analysis (e.g. Kaplansky’s conjecture, see (Solovay, 1976) Footnote 35 , and one can even find applications of forcing in mathematical physics (see e.g. Benioff, 1976 ).

Nowadays independence results are one of the core areas in set theory; furthermore, model-building techniques like forcing turned out to be useful for much more than merely proving independence results. Forcing is used in very different areas of set theory as a tool for theorem-proving (see for example Todorčecić and Farah ( 1995 ) and Miller ( 1995 )) and even gives rise to classes of axioms, the so-called forcing axioms. Footnote 36 Because of these wide range of applications, building a variety of set-theoretic models has become an integral part of regular set-theoretic practice.

This development of set-theoretic practice is the basis for Hamkins’ conclusions about the change of fundamental entities of set theory that we encountered in the introductory quote of Sect.  2 : He rejects the view that the fundamental entities of set theory are the sets of one specific universe V of set theory. Instead he perceives this development to be evidence for the claim that there is no unique concept of set associated with such a universe, but a multiplicity of them—and the way in which set-theorists study these different conceptions is by studying the models that give rise to these conceptions of set (Hamkins, 2012 , p. 417). Models are therefore fundamental for the study of set theory as they provide the specific contexts that one needs to study sets. In turn, one studies models through the set theory that arises in them. Footnote 37 The consideration of the model-related practices in set theory therefore seem to lead Hamkins to a position where both sets and models have the status of fundamental entities.

This stands in contrast to the classical view of fundamental entities in set theory, which considers them to be the sets. A very clear expression of this view is given by Koellner ( 2013 , pp. 12–13): Footnote 38

To [the claim that models have become the fundamental objects of set theory] one is bound to protest that the fundamental objects are still what they always were, namely, sets. Some of those sets happen to be models of certain theories. At certain times set theorists focus on sets that are models [...]. At other times set theorists focus on sets in general [...]. But in all cases they are studying sets.

Under this view, models are just some other specific kind of set that is investigated in set theory. However, this does not cover all appearances of models in set theoretic practice, as reference to proper class-sized models frequently occur. This can be taken as evidence that considering sets as the only fundamental entities might not be sufficient for a faithful representation of set-theoretic practice. Footnote 39 Note that this observation does not necessarily provide us with an argument for considering models as fundamental entities. Instead, we could argue that class-sized models provide a reason to view classes as fundamental entities in addition to sets. This can then be made explicit by choosing a class theory as foundation; examples of this are the von Neumann-Bernays-Gödel axiomatization ( NBG ), or perhaps Kelley-Morse class theory ( KM ) if we want to include non-definable classes as well. From this point of view, one could argue that models simply are not only sets but also classes in the same way in which Koellner argues for models as sets, therefore making the inclusion of models as fundamental entities redundant.

The reason why I do not take this line of argument is that in my view both the models-as-sets and the models-as-sets-or-classes argument do not really address the question of fundamental entities of the practice. While both arguments provide a way to address the occurrence of models in the practice, they do not deal with the way in which the models are used in, and the significance models have for, set-theoretic practice. To incorporate these latter viewpoints, criteria for what fundamental entities in the practice are should include not only foundational, but also epistemological and methodological aspects, like the issue whether the entities are flexible and general tools in the practice; whether they provide explanations; and whether they improve generality or rigor. This accords with the criteria for the introduction of new entities that I collected together from Maddy ( 2011 )’s account of the introduction of sets in Sect.  2.2 .

To clarify my point: Assume that all models considered in the practice actually are set-sized. Even in this case I think that an argument can be made for models as fundamental entities, because the fact that models are sets is only one (namely the foundational) aspect of the question of fundamental entities. But this aspect alone does not do justice to the way models are used in the practice, as it represents only one aspect of what fundamental entities are. So the existence of class-sized models in set-theoretic practice certainly serves as a motivation for looking into the question of models as fundamental entities and perhaps also as evidence that models are indeed special, but it does not answer the question by itself.

Let us briefly consider the possible objection that there are areas of set theory where set-practices are much more prevalent than model-practices and that it therefore is not true that models are fundamental entities for these areas. In response to this, let’s note that for models to be fundamental entities does not imply that every part of set theory has to study models directly. If, for example, parts of set theory take place in a certain model, e.g. a standard model of ZFC and we study the behaviour of sets in this model, without considering any other model (such as forcing extensions, inner models, etc.), this is still compatible with the view of models as fundamental entities. This is because also in this area the study of the sets proceeds under the assumption that they are the sets in a certain model, meaning that considering models is part of the fundamental set-up for the practice of studying sets. Therefore, the focus on set-related practices in some areas of set theory does not refute the importance of models as fundamental entities. In the same way the focus on model-related practices in some areas of set theory does not refute the importance of sets as fundamental entities.

We have now seen an overview of how the practice of models developed in set theory. Footnote 40 In particular, we saw that the introduction of large-scale model building techniques massively increased the use of models in the practice. In the following, I want to study the influence of these techniques in more detail, as they seem to have contributed in an essential manner to the use of models as fundamental entities. I will therefore present the case study of the introduction of forcing by Paul Cohen in the next section. This also serves as the historical case study the Second-Philosophical investigation can be based on.

3.2 Cohen’s Use of Models in the Introduction of Forcing

At the beginning of the 1960s, Paul Cohen was working on proving the independence of AC from ZF and CH from ZF ( C ), two questions that had been open since the axiomatization of set theory. Being aware of the results by Gödel regarding the consistency of AC with ZF and CH with ZF ( C ), he took on the difficult task of showing the consistency of their respective negations. Footnote 41 Cohen’s first concrete result towards developing forcing was a rather essential fact about minimal models of ZF , which showed that it is impossible to construct an inner model that will satisfy \(ZF + \text {not-}AC\) and \(ZFC +\text {not-} GCH\) (Cohen, 1963b ). Footnote 42 To overcome the problem of the existence of suitable models, Cohen assumed the additional axiom SM that states that there is a standard model of ZF . In his earliest presentation of forcing, he only mentions this fact in passing (Cohen, 1963a , pp. 1143–1144) and refers to an alternative way in which forcing can be set up that does not rely on SM (Cohen, 1964 , p. 109). These different set-ups of forcing produce the same mathematical outcome, meaning that the desired consistency results can be achieved in both ways. However they differ on their meta-mathematical assumptions with the main difference that Cohen added the axiom SM to the usual axiomatization of ZFC . The alternative syntactical approach outlined in (Cohen, 1964 ) does not require this additional assumption. In his later, much more comprehensive presentation of forcing and the independence phenomenon, Cohen ( 1966 ) emphasises that he regards the approach by assuming SM as the more natural one. He would go on to use this as the main set-up when presenting forcing in 1966 and also include an informal argument relying on the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems for why SM should be assumed (Cohen, 1966 , pp. 78–79). He includes outlines for alternative approaches, but only after his presentation of forcing and all the results are concluded (see Cohen, 1966 , pp. 147–148).

So, in Cohen’s published presentations of forcing, he chose an approach that uses models in a central way, namely, assuming their existence in an additional axiom, although he was aware that alternative approaches to forcing existed. This preference might be connected to a revealing change in Cohen’s original approach in the development of forcing. Cohen first thought about forcing in a syntactic way: “The question I faced was this: How to perform any kind of induction on the length of a proof. [...] It was at this point that I realized the connection with the models, specifically standard models. Instead of thinking about proofs, I would think about the formulas that defined sets [...]” (Cohen, 2002 , p. 1089). Interestingly, Cohen describes the work with models as the more “mathematical” of the two approaches: “[...] the feeling of elation was that I had eliminated many wrong possibilities by totally deserting the proof-theoretic approach. I was back in mathematics, not in philosophy” (Cohen, 2002 , p. 1089).

In his last publication shortly before his death, (Cohen, 2011 , p. 436) reinforces the importance of models for his development of forcing, positioning himself in the tradition of Skolem as well as Gödel. Here he calls his assumption of SM “most natural” and claims that “its truth would intuitively be accepted by everyone”. Such statements may seem surprising when compared to Cohen’s strong leaning towards formalism. Footnote 43 A similar observation has been made by Giaquinto ( 1983 , p. 130), who detects “an inner tension, if not a self-contradiction, in Cohen’s philosophical view”. Footnote 44 So, what can we take away from this? Second Philosophy actually allows us quite clearly to tell which parts of Cohen’s work and thoughts count in an analysis of means-ends relations. Similar to how (Maddy, 2011 , Ch.ii.2.(i)) relies upon everything anchored in Dedekind’s mathematical work, including his foundational pursuits, but rejects his philosophical thinking as heuristics (Maddy, 2011 , pp. 52–53), we can take under consideration everything that can be found in Cohen’s mathematical work as well as comments by Cohen on it. For example, it is significant that the approach via models was ultimately mathematically successful and led to the development of forcing, whereas Cohen’s initial syntactical approach was not. It is further a fact of mathematical practice that forcing was developed within the model-approach and not the alternative syntactical approach. Footnote 45 In contrast, wider questions asking whether models are just formal tools, really existing or similar, count as heuristic aids. Footnote 46

To further judge the importance of models for forcing, let us look at historical accounts. Here we find that they support Cohen’s own recollections: In his historical reconstruction of the discovery of forcing, Moore ( 1987 , p. 156) remarks on the fact that Cohen’s turn towards models enabled him to recognize the key ideas of forcing, while Cohen was not able to do this under his syntactic approach. Similarly, the mathematician and historian Akihiro Kanamori regards Cohen’s turn towards a semantic approach as an important step towards forcing: “[The] view of forcing as a way of actually extending models with conditions held the reservoir of mathematical sense and the promise of new discovery” (Kanamori, 2008 , p. 370).

He ties this in with a larger development towards model-theoretic methods in the research in logic done at UC Berkeley starting in the 1950s (cf. Kanamori, 2008 , p. 356). In a way similar to Cohen’s, Kanamori also perceives this as part of a development of set theory away from philosophical considerations and towards a mathematical approach: “With Cohen there was an infusion of mathematical thinking and of method and a proliferation of models, much as in other modern, sophisticated fields of mathematics” (Kanamori, 2008 , pp. 370–371).

So in both historical accounts, the use of models in Cohen’s mathematical work on forcing is judged to be relevant and fruitful for the mathematical outcome. This is exactly the kind of evidence the Second Philosopher is searching for when evaluating means-ends relations: The success and mathematical effectiveness of the model-related approach of forcing is the deciding factor, which is made even more significant when considering that approaches that don’t rely on models were not effective in practice. Also, Cohen’s work with models is not only relevant to the specific area of forcing, it is also judged to have been formative to set theory in general, contributing to the full mathematization of set-theoretic practice. All in all, we can conclude that in the case of forcing the means of introducing models as entities into set theory was an effective means towards reaching the goal of proving consistency and independence results.

3.3 Forcing Approaches and Contemporary Practice

Let us now turn to the investigation of contemporary practice. After all, we not only want to show the effectiveness of the means of introducing models as entities for the historical development, but we also want to show that models have retained this relevance until this day.

As we saw in the last section, Cohen was successfully able to develop forcing within an approach based on models. In particular, he assumed the additional axiom SM , claiming that a standard model of ZFC exists. When analysing contemporary forcing practice, we do not find such an assumption any more. Footnote 47 Neither are syntactical approaches, such as the one comprised in (Cohen, 1964 ), in use today. Footnote 48 Instead, the forcing practice quite quickly focused on the use of two approaches, the countable transitive model approach (CTM) and the Boolean valued models approach (BVM). Footnote 49

The CTM approach is close to Cohen’s original work. Footnote 50 However, instead of adding SM , one considers countable transitive models that satisfy some finite parts of ZFC to circumvent the problem that we are not able to show that a full model of ZFC exists in ZFC . Footnote 51 In practice this restriction to fragments of ZF ( C ) is not problematic; one simply assumes that the fragment is sufficiently large to conduct all of the necessary mathematics in it. This leads to a practice where set theorists operate with these models as if they were models of full ZF ( C ), even if they are not when carefully spelling out the set-up. It is essential to note that the CTM approach gives rise to the same mathematical results as the other approaches, in particular all of the independence and consistency results can be obtained as well. So it is a fully satisfactory set-up for forcing is used extensively in modern practice.

Like Cohen’s approach, the CTM approach relies in essence on the use of models. It is mathematically highly fruitful, being used constantly and successfully in set theory. Still, it has been criticised from a philosophical point of view as unsatisfactory. For example Hamkins ( 2012 , p. 421) remarks, that it “provides an understanding of forcing over only some models of set theory, whereas other accounts of forcing allow one to make sense of forcing over any model of set theory”. Just like in the case of Cohen’s view, such criticisms are not relevant for the Second Philosophers investigations into methodology. What counts is that the CTM provides a mathematically satisfactory account for the practice of forcing, that it is extensively used as such and therefore produces mathematical results. Furthermore, to make our case it is important to highlight that the use of models is essential for CTM and therefore also for its mathematical practice. With the above quote Hamkins makes a judgement about what is the “right” type of model to consider for his foundational and ontological purposes, but as we have seen in Sect.  2.1 , this does not figure into the methodological investigation of the Second Philosopher.

Let us turn to the second approach used in contemporary set theory: The Boolean valued models (BVM) approach was developed shortly after Cohen’s introduction of forcing by Dana Scott and Robert Solovay. Footnote 52 In this approach, truth values from a complete Boolean algebra \(\mathbb {B}\) are assigned to formulas, therefore producing a Boolean-valued model \(V^{\mathbb {B}}\) of ZFC . Footnote 53 Here we do not have to restrict ourselves to countable transitive models; we can see this as forcing over general models of ZFC , with the only caveat that the model produced will not be two-valued. However, as for the CTM approach, this does not influence the mathematical results provided by forcing via BVM; we still arrive at the same independence and consistency results as with the other approaches. So we can see that the use of models is essential for the BVM account as it relies on the ZFC models \(V^{\mathbb {B}}\) .

Analogously to our conclusions for the CTM approach, the BVM approach can be seen to be mathematically highly successful and fruitful. It produces the desired consistency and independence results and has the added advantage that forcing can be expressed in algebraic terms, therefore connecting it more closely to other areas of mathematics. Its philosophical significance can either be praised Footnote 54 or criticised. Footnote 55 Yet these criticisms are aimed at their ability to solve metaphysical questions, such as the discussions if and how these models can be said to be “universes” of set theory. These discussions do not diminish the relevance of these model-based approaches to set-theoretic practice and their usefulness in getting mathematical results.

Let’s take stock: In the last section I have shown that the use of models was essential to the development of forcing. In this section I have investigated the contemporary uses of forcing and shown that both of the ways of doing forcing still employ models in this manner. In contrast, approaches to forcing not based on models never had the same importance for the practice, nor were they particularly fruitful. Footnote 56

I have also shown that it does not matter mathematically whether the models employed in the set-up of forcing are countable transitive ones, standard models or Boolean-valued ones. In each of these cases we arrive at the same mathematical results: the approaches are mathematically equivalent. The forcing practice itself is not even restricted to only use models of ZF or ZFC ; sometimes models of weaker theories such as \(ZF^-\) are used and sometimes models of ZFC plus additional axioms such as large cardinal axioms are used—indeed, a broad variety of models is used in the set-theoretic practice of forcing.

The conclusion about the variety of models in the practice can further be strengthened by the observations made in Sect.  3.1 : Forcing itself is not only used for independence results but for various other tasks as well, therefore being fruitful for set theory over and above independence results. And to add yet another aspect, forcing is not the only model-building technique used in set theory: there are models in use that are not produced by forcing. Last, there are important areas in set theory that study models themselves, such as inner model theory. This leads us to the conclusion that, while our main case study is forcing, not only the specific models built with forcing are essential to the practice, but models in general. From all of this we can judge the means of introducing models of set theory as new entities in the practice as a effective means towards a wide range of set-theoretic goals over decades of mathematical research.

3.4 Models as Fundamental Entities

In the last sections we have collected evidence from historical and contemporary practice about the use of models in set theory. We will now refer to this evidence when we check if the criteria for fundamental entities given in Sect.  2.2 are supported.

Let us first look at the specific criteria: we have to show that models are treated as entities in their own right . One marker for this is that models should be susceptible to general mathematical operations. In the case of sets this was ascertained in Cantor’s practice of taking the derived set over point sets. In the case of models a similar change can be detected: With forcing one studies how models can be extended, what operation techniques can be applied to models (for example different kinds of forcing such as set- or class-forcing) and how models behave under these operations. Moreover, research is now being conducted into the interrelations between models, such as in the modal logic of forcing, set-theoretic geology Footnote 57 or work on generic absoluteness (see e.g. Bagaria, 2006 ). Models are now operated on directly, therefore becoming the focus of attention, instead of just serving as vehicles for studying sets contained in them.

Turning to the marker of arbitrary entities and of independent representations , we have seen in Sect.  3.2 how building of models changed from using specific constructions to applying general and flexible model-building techniques such as forcing: Whereas models like L are very specifically tied to their construction, forcing models can vary greatly despite being built with the same technique. This is because forcing models are tied to very few specific constraints. From their construction we know that they retain the base axioms of the ground model (usually some fragment of ZFC ) and that they contain the generic. Other properties of the model however are not determined by the general method of forcing Footnote 58 but vary with the choices made in the ground model about the partial order under consideration. In this sense models are arbitrary as they are not tied to specific constraints and largely independent from the way in which they are built by forcing.

By satisfying the specific criteria of the case of introducing something as a new entity, we can conclude that models changed in a methodologically salient manner. This leaves us with the broad criteria, which show themselves in larger scale changes in foundations and reasoning.

First, let us consider if the use of models is tied to particularly fruitful new styles of reasoning. In Sect.  3.1 we saw how model-related reasoning led to the development of forcing when Cohen switched to a semantic approach in proving the independence of CH and AC, as the use of models was essential to Cohen’s mathematical reasoning. We also observed that this model-based reasoning is still prevalent in contemporary approaches to forcing. This also shows itself in general set-theoretic practice: “Let M be a model of set theory...” is a standard sentence for setting up definitions, theorems or proofs and is deeply ingrained in set-theoretic reasoning. Moreover, some parts of set-theoretic reasoning would simply not be possible without the consideration of models. This holds in particular for the study of the properties of sets under different axiomatizations or the behaviour of independent sentences. This shows that the reasoning with models is not only fruitful and relevant, it is essential for set-theoretic practice.

Next, we see from our investigation that models figure prominently into explanations and understanding of mathematical facts: For example, the way in which a number of large cardinals can be defined via model embeddings explains the connection and degrees of consistency strength between them in a unifying manner. Footnote 59 Also, forcing explains why large cardinal axioms cannot solve the Continuum Hypothesis (because we can change the value of the continuum via small forcings) and it provides a deep understanding of the independence phenomenon, Footnote 60 for example by tracing the behaviour of independent statements over forcing models (Hamkins and Löwe, 2005 ). From Cohen’s own and Moore’s account about the change in Cohen’s understanding once he switched to a semantic approach, one can also infer that the success of the semantic approach in forcing is at least partly related to its greater explanatory value than that of the syntactic approach. In turn, this offers an explanation for why the model-related approaches to forcing were so successfully used whereas the syntactic approaches were not.

Lastly, the marker for a superior presentation in terms of improved generality, unification, rigor or simplicity obtains: Forcing provides a well-defined methodological framework for studying independence. Before forcing, it was difficult to make independence approachable in general; each case of attempted consistency and independence proofs had to be handled individually and models had to be built “by hand” to fit the cases under consideration. In contrast, forcing provides a general and unified way of dealing with the phenomenon of independence. It also adds rigour because all of the mathematical and meta-mathematical requirements are laid out in a general and rigorous set-up. Interestingly, despite forcing being a quite difficult technique to master, it nonetheless adds simplicity to the question of independent statements: Once the set-up of forcing is done and proved, its complete meta-mathematical background as well as the main theorems about axiomatization and definability can be used as a black box. The set theorist who wants to use forcing only has to focus on choosing a partial order appropriate to her task without having to take care of actually building up a model by hand.

We have now seen that the use of models and the use of techniques based on models such as forcing have wide-spread consequences for set theory in questions of reasoning, explanations, rigour and generality. That leaves the last of the broad criteria, namely the attempts at new kinds of foundations. Such attempts have indeed been made. One example is (Gitman and Hamkins, 2010 ) where possible axioms for multiversism are discussed. Note that, though closely related to (Hamkins, 2012 ), the discussion in (Gitman and Hamkins, 2010 ) does not require metaphysical assumptions, such as the posit that all models are “real” universes of set theory. A more widely discussed non-metaphysical take at foundations for sets and models is provided by Steel ( 2014 ). He develops a theory that has sets and models as fundamental entities and then discusses several issues connected to foundations. Recently, Maddy and Meadows ( 2020 ) have revisited and expanded on this approach, emphasizing the compatibility of Steel’s program with the aims of Second Philosophy (see Maddy & Meadows, 2020 , p. 38). These theories can certainly count as attempts at foundations with sets and models as fundamental entities and these attempts occur in the practice of set theory. This is what counts for a Second-Philosophical investigation into methodology, even if it is open issue if these attempts will succeed and how they are assessed in the universe/multiverse debate. Footnote 61 So while the question remains largely open as how to deal with two such types of entities on a foundational level, on the level of practice we observe that attempts at foundations including models have been made and continue to be investigated. They have not yet succeeded, but they also have not yet been declared a failure.

Let me emphasize again, that it does not matter to the investigation we are carrying out into set-theoretic methodology what advantages or drawbacks such foundations might have for metaphysical theories such as universism or (Hamkins’) multiversism. For instance, many of the arguments provided in (Maddy, 2017 ) against multiversism are not aimed against foundations including models, but the “high metaphysics” (Maddy, 2017 , pp. 312) she detects in multiverse positions, such as Hamkins.

My takeaway from the current state of play is that models are being regarded as fundamental enough to initiate a discussion about new foundations, even if this discussion has not yet come to a conclusion.

Taking stock, we have seen that the case of models can indeed be shown to fulfill the criteria for the introduction of fundamental entities. The specific criteria are satisfied in full and the same holds for most of the broad criteria. With regard to foundations, the case is not resolved; however, clear evidence is available that models will play a part in further foundational discussions. Using the methodology of Second Philosophy we have therefore shown that the means of introducing models as new fundamental entities should be considered to be part of set-theoretic methodology.

4 Conclusion and Outlook

The main result of the present article is that there is a detailed and methodologically salient argument from set-theoretic practice for the existence of two fundamental entities in set theory: sets and models. This analysis shows that the classical position discussed in Sect.  3.1 stating that fundamental entities in set theory are only sets has to be revised to include models as well.

This opens up many more questions: How do these two entities interact? How does the fundamental status of models impact the current discussions about foundations and metaphysics of set theory? In particular, what does it mean for the positions of Hamkins and Maddy on which we based our investigation? I will have to leave many of these and related questions open in this article. Let me, however, sketch the significance of my investigation for Maddy’s and Hamkins’ projects and provide some outlook on possible further work in this area.

The present investigation shows that Hamkins’ claim about the fundamental status of models for set-theoretic practice can be justified from a naturalistic, Second Philosophy point of view. Considering models as fundamental entities is part of set-theoretic methodology. This provides an argument for Hamkins’ claim that has been missing until now. However, it does not, by itself, justify all the ontological conclusions Hamkins draws from it. Instead, when following Second Philosophy, a Robust Realism of the pluralistic kind cannot be supported. What could be supported, however, are multiverse views that are along the lines of Arealism or perhaps Thin Realism. Footnote 62

Regarding Second Philosophy, we have seen that the naturalist position can agree with multiversist positions on the level of practice and methodology. This means that the practice-related parts of multiversism cannot be disregarded as heuristics, but have to be factored in when making conclusions based on methodology. By including multiversist-flavored set theory into the investiagtion of Second Philosophy, we also address the criticisms by (Ternullo, 2019 ) and (Rittberg, 2016 ) pointed out in Sect.  1 . However, Second Philosophy can still disagree significantly with multiverse positions in questions of ontology. For example, even if the Maddian naturalist, who argues for a universist position (Maddy, 2017 ), accepts models as fundamental entities in set-theoretic methodology, she does not have to change her view to multiversism: models can be seen as fundamental entities under a universist picture if they are considered as models inside a larger model V . However, the analysis given in this paper may make it harder to argue for such a universist position, as it might weaken standard arguments in its favour.

Let us consider two such arguments, namely the argument from foundational goals and the argument from simplicity. In (Maddy, 2017 ), Maddy formulates foundational goals for set theory and uses them to test possible set-theoretic foundations, namely universism, multiversism and category theory. She argues that the consideration of foundational goals confirms universism as the most convincing foundation for set theory. Here, I conjecture that accepting the method of models as fundamental entities has the potential to change the foundational goals by adding a little more multiversist flavour. Interestingly, Maddy ( 2017 ) provides an example on how the acceptance of multiversist practice can change a foundational goal, namely her Final Court of Appeal . This goal “provides decisive answers to questions of ontology and proof: if you want to know whether or not a so-and-so exists, see whether one can be found in V ” (Maddy, 2017 , p. 296). But later on she notes that this may seem too restrictive: “Why does ‘final court’ insist that we restrict ourselves to exactly what happens in V ?” (Maddy, 2017 , p. 297) If one asks a mathematical question where the answer is dependent on the models under consideration, then the answer should reflect this richness and not only adhere to what holds in (or is independent from) ZFC alone. Maddy therefore changes the Final Court of Appeal criterion to the new goal of Generous Arena . Later she points out that, with this revised goal, “a strong prima facie case against a multiverse of any kind” (Maddy, 2017 , p. 310) is not available anymore. I hypothesize that the method of accepting models as fundamental entities could change the foundational goals even further, leading to a possible re-evaluation of which set-theoretic foundations best fit the resulting goals.

A more speculative conjecture is that the result about models presented here might influence the debate about the simplicity of universe or multiverse foundations: A common argument in the multiverse/universe debate is that the default position should be universism, because there already is a good foundational theory in universism and multiversism seems to require more assumptions (for example about the existence of various models). Maddy phrases this in the following manner:

[Given] that we could work with inner models and forcing extensions from within the simple confines of V , as described by our best universe theory, what mathematical motivation is there to move to a more complex multiverse theory? (Maddy, 2017 , p. 316)

But is V really ‘simple’ and the multiverse theory ‘more complex’? From a metaphysical point of view, this is certainly correct. Positing the existence of a not well-delineated number of models is more complex than simply stating that one universe exists. However, from a methodological point of view, the use of models of set theory as fundamental entities seems to suggest otherwise: Here multiversism offers a very natural interpretation for these models, namely as entities in their own right. Universism, instead, offers an interpretation for the models that requires an additional argumentative step by interpreting them as parts of an overall V . The universist would, for example, have to argue why V as a model of set theory itself has a different methodological status than the other models.

I think it is of interest for further work to explore in detail how the naturalist argument given here about the fundamental status of models in set-theoretic methodology can have wider implications for the core areas of the universe/multiverse debate.

See for example Woodin ( 2011 ), Hamkins ( 2012 ), Koellner ( 2013 ), Maddy ( 2017 ), Steel ( 2014 ).

The standard example is the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) and its independence from the axiom system ZFC .

This in turn raises the issue of how to deal with proper class-sized models; I discuss this problem in Sect.  3.1 .

This is the approach of Second philosophy that is discussed in detail in Sects.  2.1 and 2.2 .

See for example (Maddy, 2007 ) and (Maddy, 2011 ).

Hamkins ( 2012 ) indicates how such an argument could be made by many and varied references to recent results and practices, e.g. the importance of independence results and research programs such as set-theoretic geology. This provides a strong motivation for his multiverse view; however, it gives no clear argument on why the practices justify such a view.

He does discuss in detail two analogies between his observations about set-theoretic practice and the practices of algebra (especially group theory) and, more historically, of non-Euclidean geometries. These analogies—and the related question whether set theory might have become an algebraic or non-algebraic field of research in mathematics—have been discussed more broadly since the development of forcing in the 1960s. Because I aim to give an argument from set-theoretic practice itself, I will not go into detail about these discussions. For early discussions of analogies between the development of set theory and algebra, see the contributions of Mostowski ( 1967 ) and Kalmar ( 1967 ). The article (Körner, 1967 ) in the same volume is also of interest for the question of models as fundamental entities. The discussions about algebraic/non-algebraic (or abstract/concrete) field of mathematics is a broad one and set theory is only one of the fields discussed there. Shapiro ( 1997 ) introduced a first distinction, that he changed in Shapiro ( 2005 ), Hellman ( 2003 ) provides a different distinction on the basis of characteristics of axiomatic systems.

I would like to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for pressing me to clarify the context and main aim of Koellner’s criticism of Hamkins.

As a rough timeline, Maddy’s Naturalism was already presented in Maddy ( 1997 ); a broader philosophical investigation led to the formulation of Second Philosophy in Maddy ( 2007 ), which was in turn utilized to study set theory in Maddy ( 2011 ). As some parts of the framework changed between these presentations, I will focus on the newest presentation of Second Philosophy given for set theory in Maddy ( 2011 ).

See in particular the two parts of Maddy ( 2011 ) as outlined in Maddy ( 2011 , p. 41).

See for example the discussion in Maddy ( 2019 , pp. 75–76).

Note that Arealism is not the same as standard Nominalism, see Maddy ( 2011 , pp. 96–98).

I want to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for suggesting to clarify this point.

If, that is, one wants to tackle all of these questions. As we have seen in the last paragraph, Maddy does not consider the metaphysical issues to be of importance to the Second Philosophers project.

In this context, Maddy ( 2017 ) elaborates on foundational goals, proposing a list that a good foundation should adhere to.

See also the difference between methodology and heuristics discussed above.

This directive is embedded in a fundamental distinction between intrinsic vs. extrinsic justification, see for example Maddy ( 2011 , CH.V.4). For further discussion see Carolin and Kant ( forthcoming ) and in particular Maddy’s answer in the same volume.

See Maddy ( 2011 , pp. 42, 43).

Here the word ‘arbitrary’ is not meant in a technical sense, such as it is used in theories of arbitrary objects like (Horsten, 2019 ). Such an interpretation is quite interesting especially when certain types of set-theoretic models, the so-called Boolean valued models are investigated as arbitrary objects (see Horsten, 2020 ). However, this meaning is arguably not the one intended by Maddy ( 2011 ), nor does it fit the Second Philosopher’s methodology, as it is tied to a specific metaphysical interpretation of models of set theory. Therefore, there word ‘arbitrary’ is used here to simply mean that the entities are not tied to a specific criterion or constraint.

This last point collects together several remarks of Maddy ( 2011 , Ch.II.2) on rigour, simplicity and generality and Maddy ( 2007 , pp. 352–353)’s discussion of the introduction of groups in algebra.

I read this off Maddy’s comments on the relevance and force the means have in the practice of the discipline (see for example Maddy, 2011 , p. 53) and similar consideration connected to a consensus in the community concerning its methods that Maddy discusses in Maddy ( 1997 , p. 194).

I would like to thank both anonymous reviewers for insisting on discussing this question in more detail. I think it is an important point overall and I would be interested to see if the methodology of Second Philosophy as applied here can justify other cases of fundamental entities (although I don’t presently see an obvious candidate).

These conjectured failings can be taken to be exemplary for problems that arise with other entities as well.

We investigate the basis of this discussion further in Sect.  3.1 .

There were attempts at using functions as fundamental entities, such as (von Neumann, 1925 ). However despite being of theoretical significance, they never fundamentally influenced set-theoretic practice: usual renderings of the Gödel-Bernays-von Neumann axiomatization and variants thereof use sets as fundamental entities. Of course, one could still make the case that functions should play a bigger role in foundations because they are so fundamental for mathematics in general. From such a point of view, other foundations such as category theory may seem to be more appropriate than set theory. But this lies outside the scope of our investigation of set-theoretic practice.

Note that this discussion is targeted at set-theoretic practice. There are practices outside of set theory for which ordinals might be considered as fundamental entities, for example the way in which they are used in non-standard analysis (I want to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for pointing this out to me). This is another example where we can see that the notion of “fundamental entity of a practice” really is dependent on the practice under consideration. As we have seen in the previous Footnote about functions, considering these different practices within mathematics might then be used to provide arguments for or against different proposals for a foundation of mathematics.

Note, that it is not obvious that this is the case, as one might argue that a syntactical formulation of forcing is enough to do this. I will address this point in the following sections.

This does not imply that forcing is the only instance of such a use of models. The case of inner model theory could be investigated as well.

“Partial” in this context means that only one direction could be shown, for example a model had been produced for ZFC \(+A\) but not for ZFC \(+\neg A\) .

For a detailed definition see for example Jech ( 2003 , 175 ff.).

I want to emphasize that despite this “restrictiveness” of the construction method of L , the model L itself is used broadly in set theoretic research. For instance, it also contributes to model-centered research in set theory as can for example be seen in work about the covering lemma, which was initiated by Devlin and Jensen ( 1975 ) (I want to thank one of the anonymous reviewers for pointing this out to me). See Mitchell ( 2010b ) for a general account.

Another example for such more general techniques are Ultraproduct constructions and Scott’s Ultrafilter method (see for example Scott, 1961 ; Kunen, 1970 , Silver, 1971 ). This was groundbreaking work for the area of inner models theory. A very comprehensive introduction and advanced results can be found in Volume III of (Foreman and Kanamori, 2010 ), in particular (Mitchell, 2010a ) and (Steel, 2010 ) may be of interest.

There are some meta-mathematical problems one has to deal with here, however they can be overcome; see also Sect.  3.3 .

For general presentations of forcing see (Kunen, 1980 ) or (Jech, 2003 ).

Woodin and Dales ( 1987 ) dedicates a whole book to showing that there are interesting independence results in analysis.

One of the earliest is Martin’s Axiom, see (Martin and Solovay, 1970 ).

Hamkins expressed this position in private correspondence with the author (e-mail communication, September 13th, 2021).

As mentioned at the beginning of Sect.  2 , this is not the major thrust of Koellner’s overall argument. Nonetheless, I will discuss it here as representative for the most common argument the classical view provides against models as fundamental entities. Of course, even if we manage to reject this particular argument, we have not provided a counterargument to Koellner’s general criticism that is directed against Hamkins’ ontological position. See also Sect.  4 .

Interestingly, the same evidence exists for the case of functions and ordinals, as class-versions of both are used in set-theoretic practice. However, the misgivings I presented in Sect.  2.2 that speak against regarding functions and ordinals as fundamental entities in set-theoretic practice still hold. This might provide additional motivation for conducting a more thorough investigation for these cases.

A related issue is how model-based practices developed in other mathematical practices. The obvious candidate here is model theory that indeed has models as its primary fundamental entities. The development of model theory as a separate discipline began in the 1950s with work by Tarski and Robinson and it always had strong connections within set theoretic research (take for example the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). A detailed analysis of the interconnections of these practices would be too extensive for this article. However as a starting point let me mention Baldwin ( 2018 )’s “Model theory and the philosophy of mathematical practice” that might be of particular importance here. Baldwin not only gives detailed insight into the development of model theory, he also argues for a paradigmatic shift in model theory in the 1960s, around the same time I’m arguing that a shift happened in the treatment of models in set-theoretic practice. He also shows more generally what importance model considerations have for general mathematics. So it seems that making a connection to model theory can strengthen my arguments further.

See Moore ( 1987 ) and Kanamori ( 2008 ) for a detailed description of Cohen’s career until this point and his endeavour of proving the consistency of AC and CH.

The earlier proof of the same fact by Shepherdson ( 1953 ) seems not to have been well-known at the time, cf. (Moore, 1987 , p. 155).

I would like to thank one of the anonymous referees for pointing this out.

A close analysis of Cohen’s philosophical views and his practice in the development of forcing is given in (Wagner, forthcoming ).

This does not make the syntactic approach less mathematical. Quite the contrary, one could argue that not relying on the assumption of an additional axiom could be preferable. But this is simply not what happened in set-theoretic practice, and therefore cannot be the evidential basis for Second Philosophy. In the next section we discuss what approaches to forcing are used in contemporary practice and we will see that the syntactical approach has still not gained importance as of yet.

At least at this juncture of the Second Philosopher’s investigation; as pointed out in the last section, after getting clear about methodology, we can tackle questions of ontology. But for the methodological investigation we aim at here, this does not come into play.

Cohen has been criticised for the assumption of SM from very early on. For example, Moschovakis “wrote to Cohen, asking why Cohen had made such a ‘ridiculous assumption’ ”, i.e. that of the existence of a standard model. (Moore, 1987 , p. 159).

To be more precise, fully syntactical approaches are not used in the practice but sometimes syntatical set-ups are used to prove theorems about forcing when developing it in a textbook. One example for this is Kunen ( 1980 ), who introduces the syntactical notion of the \(\vdash _{*}\) -relation, but then latter drops it in favour of working with models. He mentions an alternative fully syntactical approach in his appendix (Kunen, 1980 , pp. 234–235) that is similar to what Cohen outlines in Cohen ( 1964 , p. 109) and Cohen ( 1966 , pp. 147–148).

The historical development of both approaches is quite interesting and involves many of the defining figures of set theory in the second half of the 21st century, such as Cohen, Scott, Shoenfield, Solovay and others. See (Moore, 1987 ) for a detailed historical account.

For an introduction to CTM, see Kunen ( 2011 ).

This impossibility is due to Gödel’s incompleteness results, see for example discussion in Kunen ( 1980 ).

For an introduction to BVM, see Jech ( 2003 ).

This problem of many truth values can be addressed by using an ultrafilter over \(\mathbb {B}\) to form the new model. Recently, this has been used to develop the so-called “naturalist account of forcing” (Hamkins, 2012 , p. 423); however, the approach used in the practice is most often the “simple” BVM approach.

As done in (Hamkins, 2012 ), especially when developed further towards the Naturalist approach.

As done in Koellner ( 2010 , p. 217) for not producing two-valued models.

For the sake of completeness, let me point out that there are variants of the approaches discussed in this article as well as some other approaches, that are theoretically possible but not really used in the practice. An overview can be found in Kunen ( 1980 , pp. 232–235).

See the Appendix to (Hamkins, 2012 ).

Although forcing provides us with the means to investigate what holds in the models via the forcing relation, it does not itself pre-determine what holds in them.

Unification is the basis for explanations in the account of Kitcher ( 1989 ); in this case I only assume that unification is one indicator (but maybe not the only one) for explanatory value.

As in the case of unification, one can take understanding to be the sole basis for explanation (see for example Inglis & Mejía-Ramos, 2019 ), but here I take understanding to be one indicator amongst others for explanatory value.

For example, (Maddy and Meadows, 2020 ) claims that Steel’s multiverse in the end comes down to a variant of universism, not multiversism.

Maddy ( 2019 , Footnote 6) hints at such a possibility for an arealist multiverse.

Antos, C., & Kant, D. (forthcoming). A general framework for a Second Philosophy analysis of set-theoretic methodology. In S. Arbeiter & J. Kennedy (Eds.), Outstanding contributions to logic: Penelope Maddy . Springer.

Avigad, J. (2006). Methodology and metaphysics in the development of Dedekind’s theory of ideals. In J. Ferreiros & J. Gray (Eds.), The architecture of modern mathematics (pp. 159–186). Oxford University Press.

Bagaria, J. (2006). Axioms of generic absoluteness. In Z. Chatzidakis, P. Koepke, & W. Pohlers (Eds.), Logic colloquium ’02: Lecture notes in logic. Assoc. Symbol. Logic (Vol. 27, pp. 28–47).

Baldwin, J. (2018). Model theory and the philosophy of mathematical practice: Formalization without foundationalism . Cambridge University Press.

Benioff, P. A. (1976). Models of Zermelo Frankel set theory as carriers for the mathematics of physics, I. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 17 (5), 618–628. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.522953 .

Article   Google Scholar  

Cantor, G. (1872). Über die Ausdehnung eines Satzes aus der Theorie der trigonometrischen Reihen. Mathematische Annalen, 5, 123–132.

Cantor, G. (1883). Über unendliche, lineare Punktmannichfaltigkeiten. Mathematische Annalen, 21 (4), 545–591.

Cohen, P. J. (1963). The independence of the continuum hypothesis. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 50 (6), 1143–1148.

Cohen, P. J. (1963). A minimal model for set theory. The Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 69 (4), 537–540.

Cohen, P. J. (1964). The independence of the continuum hypothesis, II. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 51 (1), 105–110.

Cohen, P. J. (1966). Set theory and the continuum hypothesis . W. A. Benjamin.

Cohen, P. J. (2002). The discovery of forcing. Rocky Mountain Journal of Mathematics, 32 (4), 1071–1100.

Cohen, P. J. (2011). My interaction with Kurt Gödel: The man and his work. In M. Baaz (Ed.), Kurt Gödel and the Foundations of Mathematics: Horizons of truth . Cambridge University Press.

Devlin, K. J. (2017). Constructibility. Perspectives in logic. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316717219 .

Devlin, K. J., & Jensen, R. B. (1975). Marginalia to a theorem of silver. In G. H. Müller, A. Oberschelp, & K. Potthoff (Eds.), \(\models\) ISILC logic conference (pp. 115–142). Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-38022-1.

Ferreirós, J. (2007). Labyrinth of thought: A history of set theory and its role in modern mathematics . Springer.

Foreman, M., & Kanamori, A. (Eds.). (2010). Handbook of set theory . Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5764-9 .

Fraenkel, A. (1922). Der Begriff “definit” und die Unabhängigkeit des Auswahlaxioms. Sitz. Pr. Ak. Wiss. Phys.-Math. Klasse 253–257.

Giaquinto, M. (1983). Hilbert’s philosophy of mathematics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34 (2), 119–132.

Gitman, V., & Hamkins, J. D. (2010). A natural model of the multiverse axioms. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51 (4), 475–484. https://doi.org/10.1215/00294527-2010-030 .

Gödel, K. (1940). The consistency of the axiom of choice and of the generalized continuum-hypothesis with the axioms of set theory . Princeton University Press.

Hamkins, J. D. (2012). The set-theoretic multiverse. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 416–449.

Hamkins, J. D., & Löwe, B. (2005). The modal logic of forcing. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 360, 10. https://doi.org/10.1090/S0002-9947-07-04297-3 .

Hellman, G. (2003). Does category theory provide a framework for mathematical structuralism? Philosophia Mathematica, 11, 129–157 ( ISSN 0031-8019 ).

Horsten, L. (2019). The metaphysics and mathematics of arbitrary objects . Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781139600293 .

Horsten, L. (2020). Boolean-valued sets as arbitrary objects. arXiv:2002.02181 .

Inglis, M., & Mejía-Ramos, J. P. (2019). Functional explanation in mathematics. Synthese . https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02234-5 .

Jech, T. (2003). Set theory. The third millennium edition, revised and expanded edition . Springer-Verlag.

Jensen, R. B. (1972). The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy. Annals of Mathematical Logic, 4 (3), 229–308. https://doi.org/10.1016/0003-4843(72)90001-0 .

Kalmar, L. (1967). Foundations of mathematics—Whither now? In I. Lakatos (Ed.), Problems in the philosophy of mathematics . Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 47, pp. 187–207). Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71526-X .

Kanamori, A. (2008). Cohen and set theory. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 14 (3), 351–378.

Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). University of Minnesota Press.

Koellner, P. (2010). On the question of absolute undecidability. In K. Gödel, S. Feferman, C. Parsons, & S. G. Simpson (Eds.), Philosophia mathematica (pp. 153–188). Association for Symbolic Logic.

Koellner, P. (2013). Hamkins on the multiverse. Unpublished.

Kunen, K. (1970). Some applications of iterated ultrapowers in set theory. Annals of Mathematical Logic, 1 (2), 179–227. https://doi.org/10.1016/0003-4843(70)90013-6 .

Kunen, K. (1980). Set theory: An introduction to independence proofs. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 102). Elsevier Science Publishers.

Kunen, K. (2011). Set theory. Studies in logic . College Publications.

Körner, S. (1967). On the relevance of post-Gödelian mathematics to philosophy. In I. Lakatos (Ed.), Problems in the philosophy of mathematics Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 47, pp. 118–137). Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71524-6 .

Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in mathematics . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method . Oxford University Press.

Maddy, P. (2011). Defending the axioms: On the philosophical foundations of set theory . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Maddy, P. (2017). Set-theoretic foundations. In A. E. Caicedo, J. Cummings, P. Koellner, & P. B. Larson (Eds.), Foundations of mathematics. Essays in honour of W. Hugh Woodin’s 60th birtsday (pp. 289–322). American Mathematical Society.

Maddy, P. (2019). Reply to Ternullo on the multiverse. In S. Centrone, D. Kant, & D. Sarikaya (Eds.), Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: Univalent Foundations, set theory and general thoughts (pp. 69–78). Springer International Publishing.

Maddy, P., & Meadows, T. (2020). A reconstruction of steel’s multiverse project. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 26 (2), 118–169. https://doi.org/10.1017/bsl.2020.5 .

Martin, D. A., & Solovay, R. M. (1970). Internal Cohen extensions. Annals of Mathematical Logic, 2 (2), 143–178. https://doi.org/10.1016/0003-4843(70)90009-4 .

Miller, A. W. (1995). Descriptive set theory and forcing: How to prove theorems about borel sets the hard way . Lecture notes in logic. Springer-Verlag.

Mirimanoff, D. (1917). Les antinomies de Russell et de Burali–Forti et le problème fondamental de la théorie des ensembles. Enseignement mathématique, 19 (1–2), 37–52.

Google Scholar  

Mitchell, W. J. (2010a). Beginning inner model theory. In M. Foreman & A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of set theory (pp. 1449–1495). Springer Netherlands.

Mitchell, W. J. (2010). The covering lemma. In M. Foreman & A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of set theory (pp. 1497–1594). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5764-9_19 .

Moore, G. (1987). The origins of forcing. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 124, 12.

Mostowski, A. (1967). Recent results in set theory. In I. Lakatos (Ed.), Problems in the philosophy of mathematics . Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 47, pp. 82–108). Elsevier. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71522-2

Reitz, J. (2007). The ground axiom. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 72 (4), 1299–1317 ( ISSN 00224812 ).

Rittberg, Colin Jakob. (2016). Methods, Goals and Metaphysics in Contemporary Set Theory. Dissertation, University of Hertfordshire.

Scott, D. (1961). Measurable cardinals and constructible sets. Bull. Acad. Pol. Sci., Sér. Sci. Math. Astron. Phys., 9, 521–524 ( ISSN 0001-4117 ).

Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology . Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509452-7.

Shapiro, S. (2005). Categories, structures, and the Frege–Hilbert controversy: The status of meta-mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 13 (1), 61–77. https://doi.org/10.1093/philmat/nki007 .

Shelah, S. (1974). Infinite abelian groups, whitehead problem and some constructions. Israel Journal of Mathematics, 18 (3), 243–256. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02757281 .

Shepherdson, J. C. (1953). Inner models for set theory–part III. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 18 (2), 145–167.

Silver, J. H. (1971). Some applications of model theory in set theory. Annals of Mathematical Logic, 3 (1), 45. https://doi.org/10.1016/0003-4843(71)90010-6 .

Steel, J. (2010). An outline of inner model theory. In M. Foreman & A. Kanamori (Eds.), Handbook of set theory (pp. 1595–1684). Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-5764-9_20 .

Steel, J. (2014). Gödel’s Program. In J. Kennedy (Ed.), Interpreting Gödel (pp. 153–179). Cambridge University Press.

Ternullo, C. (2019). Maddy on the multiverse. In S. Centrone, D. Kant, & D. Sarikaya (Eds.), Reflections on the foundations of mathematics: Univalent foundations. Set theory and general thoughts (pp. 43–78). Springer International Publishing.

Todorčecić, S., & Farah, I. (1995). Some applications of the method of forcing . Yenisei.

von Neumann, J. (1925). Eine Axiomatisierung der Mengenlehre. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 154, 219–240.

Wagner, R. (forthcoming). Paul Cohen’s philosophy of mathematics and its reflection in his mathematical practice.

Woodin, W. H. (2001). The continuum hypothesis, part II. Notices of the AMS, 48 (7), 681–690.

Woodin, W. H. (2011). The continuum hypothesis, the generic-multiverse of sets, and the \(\Omega\) -Conjecture. In J. Kennedy & R. Kossak (Eds.), Set theory, arithmetic, and foundations of mathematics (pp. 13–42). Cambridge University Press.

Woodin, W. H., & Dales, H. G. (1987). An introduction to independence for analysts. Number 115 in london mathematical society lecture note series . Cambridge University Press.

Zermelo, E. (1930). Über Grenzzahlen Und Mengenbereiche: Neue Untersuchungen Über Die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre. Fundamenta Mathematicæ, 16, 29–47.

Download references

Acknowledgment

I would like to thank Neil Barton, Hazel Brickhill, Joel D. Hamkins, Leon Horsten, Deborah Kant, Daniel Kuby, Penelope Maddy and Philip Welch for their helpful comments and discussions, as well as audiences of presentations in Oxford, Paris and Konstanz. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their thorough and thoughtful comments. I am grateful to the Zukunftskolleg at the University of Konstanz and the VolkswagenFoundation for their generous support within the Freigeist funding scheme.

Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Fachbereich Philosophie/Zukunftskolleg, University of Konstanz, Konstanz, Germany

Carolin Antos

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carolin Antos .

Additional information

Publisher's note.

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ .

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Antos, C. Models as Fundamental Entities in Set Theory: A Naturalistic and Practice-based Approach. Erkenn 89 , 1683–1710 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00600-3

Download citation

Received : 22 March 2021

Accepted : 10 July 2022

Published : 19 August 2022

Issue Date : April 2024

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00600-3

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

Search

www.springer.com The European Mathematical Society

  • StatProb Collection
  • Recent changes
  • Current events
  • Random page
  • Project talk
  • Request account
  • What links here
  • Related changes
  • Special pages
  • Printable version
  • Permanent link
  • Page information
  • View source

2020 Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary: 03Exx [ MSN ][ ZBL ]

Set theory is the study of the properties of sets (cf. Set ) by themselves, disregarding the properties of their elements. It is especially concerned with the study of sets with infinite elements. The idea of a set is one of the primitive mathematical ideas and can only be explained by means of examples or analogies. Intuitively, a set is just a collection of objects. One can speak of the set of people living on our planet at a given time, of the set of points of a given geometric figure and of the set of solutions of a given differential equation. A person living on the planet at the given time, a point of the given geometric figure, a solution of the given differential equation are elements of their respective sets.

A set $A$ is regarded as given if a characteristic property of the elements of the set is given, that is, a property which all the elements of the set, and only they, possess.

One of the fundamental ideas of set theory is that of membership of an element of a set. To denote that an object $a$ belongs to a set $A$ one writes $a \in A$ (if $a$ does not belong to $A$ one writes $a \not\in A$ or $a \overline{\in} A$). (It can happen that no object has the characteristic property defining $A$; it is then said that $A$ is empty and one writes $A = \empty$. For example, the set of real solutions of the equation $x^2 = -1$ is empty.) If each element of a set $A$ is at the same time an element of a set $B$, then $A$ is called a subset of $B$ and one writes $A \subset B$. If $A \subset B$ and $B \subset A$ simultaneously, then $A$ and $B$ are said to be equal and one writes $A = B$. The union $A \cup B$ of two sets $A$ and $B$ is the set comprising all the elements which belong to at least one of the sets $A$ or $B$. The intersection $A \cap B$ of $A$ and $B$ is the set comprising all the elements which belong to both $A$ and $B$. The operations of union and intersection are commutative, associative and mutually distributive. For example, $(A \cup B)\cap C=(A \cap C)\cup(B \cap C)$. Often one considers only sets which are contained in some fixed set $X$. If $A$ is a subset of $X$ and $P$ is a property characterizing the elements of $A$, then one writes $A=\{x \in X : P(x) \textrm{ is true }\}$. For example, if $X$ is the set of all real numbers and $A$ is the subset of positive numbers, then $A=\{x \in X: x > 0\}$. If $A\subset X$, then the set $X\setminus A=\{x \in X: x\not\in A\}$ is called the complement of the set $A$ (in $X$). The operations of union, intersection and taking the complement are connected by the so-called de Morgan laws . For example, $X\setminus(A\cap B)=(X\setminus A)\cup(X\setminus B)$. The branch of set theory concerned with the study of operations on sets (not only finite, but also infinite operations) is called the algebra of sets. The algebra of sets, in its turn, is a special case of the theory of Boolean algebras (cf. Boolean algebra ).

Set theory was created by the work of 19th century mathematicians, who posed the aim of a complete revision of the foundations of mathematical analysis. Already in the first papers in this area (B. Bolzano, P. du Bois-Reymond, R. Dedekind), which considered sets of numbers or functions, the question of a quantitative comparison of infinite sets was posed. Is infinity of a set purely a negative property, not admitting elaboration, or do there exist different levels of mathematical infinity; are there infinite sets of different quantitative strength, of different "power" ? The answer to this question was given by G. Cantor (1871–1883), who presented an almost modern exposition of the theory of cardinal and ordinal numbers (cf. Cardinal number ; Ordinal number ) and the theory of well-ordered sets (cf. Well-ordered set ). The possibility of a comparative quantitative estimation of sets was based on the idea of a one-to-one correspondence (or bijection ) between two sets. Associate to each element of a set $A$, by any rule whatever, a definite element of a set $B$. If each element of $B$ turns out to be in correspondence to one and only one element of $A$, then it is said that a one-to-one correspondence (or bijective mapping or bijection) has been established between $A$ and $B$. There is a bijection between two finite sets if and only if both sets have the same number of elements. Generalizing this fact, Cantor defined quantitative equivalence, or equipotence, as the possibility of establishing a one-to-one correspondence between them. If a set $A$ is equipotent to a set $B$, then $A$ and $B$ have the same cardinal number. The value of the notion of the power of a set is determined by the existence of non-equipotent infinite sets. For example, the set of all real numbers and the set of all natural numbers have different powers. The first has the power of the continuum, and the second is a countable set. In each infinite set $A$ there is a proper subset of $A$ equipotent to the whole of $A$, whereas in a finite set such a proper part cannot be found. Therefore the presence of a proper part equipotent to the whole can be taken as the definition of an infinite set.

The merit of Cantor is not just in the solution of the problem of the power of a set, but in the decisive step he made of considering sets with elements of an arbitrary nature. To testify that this step to generality was difficult, there are firstly the various inconsistencies (cf. Antinomy ), discoveries by various scholars at the beginning of the 20th century and leading to the creation of axiomatic set theory , and secondly, the emergence of various problems (for example, the continuum hypothesis ) which turned out to be undecidable.

A subsequent contribution to set theory was made by F. Hausdorff, who, after developing the theory of totally ordered sets and applying set theory to topology, completed the foundations of the theory of topological spaces (cf. Topological space ) (or, general topology). Later, the $\mathcal{A}$-operation, arising in the study of Borel sets, led to the creation of descriptive set theory . From a number of problems in combinatorial mathematics and graph theory, combinatorial set theory arose. Finally, the discoveries of K. Gödel and P. Cohen in axiomatic set theory significantly influenced the methods and development of set theory.

Cf. also Set .

  • Mathematical logic and foundations
  • This page was last edited on 30 November 2014, at 19:50.
  • Privacy policy
  • About Encyclopedia of Mathematics
  • Disclaimers
  • Impressum-Legal

Library homepage

  • school Campus Bookshelves
  • menu_book Bookshelves
  • perm_media Learning Objects
  • login Login
  • how_to_reg Request Instructor Account
  • hub Instructor Commons

Margin Size

  • Download Page (PDF)
  • Download Full Book (PDF)
  • Periodic Table
  • Physics Constants
  • Scientific Calculator
  • Reference & Cite
  • Tools expand_more
  • Readability

selected template will load here

This action is not available.

Mathematics LibreTexts

1.1.E: Problems in Set Theory (Exercises)

  • Last updated
  • Save as PDF
  • Page ID 22251

\( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)

\( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)

\( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)

( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)

\( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)

\( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)

\( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\)

\( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)

\( \newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\)

\( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\)

\( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\)

\( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\)

\( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\)

\( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\)

\( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\)

\( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

\( \newcommand{\vectorA}[1]{\vec{#1}}      % arrow\)

\( \newcommand{\vectorAt}[1]{\vec{\text{#1}}}      % arrow\)

\( \newcommand{\vectorB}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \)

\( \newcommand{\vectorC}[1]{\textbf{#1}} \)

\( \newcommand{\vectorD}[1]{\overrightarrow{#1}} \)

\( \newcommand{\vectorDt}[1]{\overrightarrow{\text{#1}}} \)

\( \newcommand{\vectE}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash{\mathbf {#1}}}} \)

Exercise \(\PageIndex{1}\)

Prove Theorem 1 (show that \(x\) is in the left-hand set iff it is in the right-hand set). For example, for \((\mathrm{d}),\) \[ \begin{aligned} x \in(A \cup B) \cap C & \Longleftrightarrow[x \in(A \cup B) \text { and } x \in C] \\ & \Longleftrightarrow[(x \in A \text { or } x \in B), \text { and } x \in C] \\ & \Longleftrightarrow[(x \in A, x \in C) \text { or }(x \in B, x \in C)]. \end{aligned} \]

Exercise \(\PageIndex{2}\)

Prove that (i) \(-(-A)=A\); (ii) \(A \subseteq B\) iff \(-B \subseteq-A\).

Exercise \(\PageIndex{3}\)

Prove that \[ A-B=A \cap(-B)=(-B)-(-A)=-[(-A) \cup B]. \] Also, give three expressions for \(A \cap B\) and \(A \cup B,\) in terms of complements.

Exercise \(\PageIndex{4}\)

Prove the second duality law (Theorem 2(ii)).

Exercise \(\PageIndex{5}\)

Describe geometrically the following sets on the real line: \[ \begin{array}{ll}{\text { (i) }\{x | x<0\} ;} & {\text { (ii) }\{x| | x |<1\}}; \\ {\text { (iii) }\{x| | x-a |<\varepsilon\} ;} & {\text { (iv) }\{x | a<x \leq b\}}; \\ {\text { (v) }\{x| | x |<0\}}. \end{array} \]

Exercise \(\PageIndex{6}\)

Let \((a, b)\) denote the set \[ \{\{a\},\{a, b\}\} \] (Kuratowski's definition of an ordered pair). (i) Which of the following statements are true? \[ \begin{array}{ll}{\text { (a) } a \in(a, b) ;} & {\text { (b) }\{a\} \in(a, b)}; \\ {\text { (c) }(a, a)=\{a\} ;} & {\text { (d) } b \in(a, b)}; \\ {\text { (e) }\{b\} \in(a, b) ;} & {\text { (f) }\{a, b\} \in(a, b)}. \end{array} \] (ii) Prove that \((a, b)=(u, v)\) if \(a=u\) and \(b=v\). [Hint: Consider separately the two cases \(a=b\) and \(a \neq b,\) noting that \(\{a, a\}=\) \(\{a\} .\) Also note that \(\{a\} \neq a . ]\)

Exercise \(\PageIndex{7}\)

Describe geometrically the following sets in the \(x y\)-plane. (i) \(\{(x, y) | x<y\}\); (ii) \(\left\{(x, y) | x^{2}+y^{2}<1\right\}\); (iii) \(\{(x, y)|\max (|x|,|y|)<1\}\); (iii) \(\left\{(x, y) | y>x^{2}\right\}\); (iv) \(\left\{(x, y) | y>x^{2}\right\}\); (vii) \(\{(x, y)| | x|+| y |<4\}\); (vii) \(\left\{(x, y) |(x-2)^{2}+(y+5)^{2} \leq 9\right\}\); (viii) \(\left\{(x, y) | x^{2}-2 x y+y^{2}<0\right\}\); (ix) \(\left\{(x, y) | x^{2}-2 x y+y^{2}=0\right\}\).

Exercise \(\PageIndex{8}\)

Prove that (i) \((A \cup B) \times C=(A \times C) \cup(B \times C)\); (ii) \((A \cap B) \times(C \cap D)=(A \times C) \cap(B \times D)\); (iii) \((X \times Y)-\left(X^{\prime} \times Y^{\prime}\right)=\left[\left(X \cap X^{\prime}\right) \times\left(Y-Y^{\prime}\right)\right] \cup\left[\left(X-X^{\prime}\right) \times Y\right]\); [Hint: In each case, show that an ordered pair \((x, y)\) is in the left-hand set iff it is in the right-hand set, treating \((x, y)\) as one element of the Cartesian product. \(]\)

Exercise \(\PageIndex{9}\)

Prove the distributive laws (i) \(A \cap \cup X_{i}=\bigcup\left(A \cap X_{i}\right)\); (ii) \(A \cup \cap X_{i}=\bigcap\left(A \cup X_{i}\right)\); (iii) \(\left(\cap X_{i}\right)-A=\cap\left(X_{i}-A\right)\); (iv) \((\cup X _{i} )-A=\cup\left(X_{i}-A\right)\); (v) \(\cap X_{i} \cup \cap Y_{j}=\cap_{i, j}\left(X_{i} \cup Y_{j}\right) ;\) (vi) \(\cup X_{i} \cap \cup Y_{j}=\cup_{i, j}\left(X_{i} \cap Y_{j}\right)\).

Exercise \(\PageIndex{10}\)

Prove that (i) \(\left(\cup A_{i}\right) \times B=\bigcup\left(A_{i} \times B\right)\); (ii) \(\left(\cap A_{i}\right) \times B=\cap\left(A_{i} \times B\right)\); (iii) \(\left(\cap_{i} A_{i}\right) \times\left(\cap_{j} B_{j}\right)=\bigcap_{i, j}\left(A_{i} \times B_{i}\right)\); (iv) \(\left(\cup_{i} A_{i}\right) \times\left(\bigcup_{j} B_{j}\right)=\bigcup_{i, j}\left(A_{i} \times B_{j}\right)\).

Level Up Academy

CBSE Case Study Questions for Class 11 Maths Sets Free PDF

Featured image website

Mere Bacchon, you must practice the CBSE Case Study Questions Class 11 Maths Sets in order to fully complete your preparation . They are very very important from exam point of view. These tricky Case Study Based Questions can act as a villain in your heroic exams!

I have made sure the questions (along with the solutions) prepare you fully for the upcoming exams. To download the latest CBSE Case Study Questions , just click ‘ Download PDF ’.

CBSE Case Study Questions for Class 11 Maths Sets PDF

Checkout our case study questions for other chapters.

  • Chapter 2 Relations and Functions Case Study Questions
  • Chapter 3 Trigonometric Functions Case Study Questions
  • Chapter 4 Principle of Mathematical Induction Case Study Questions
  • Chapter 5 Complex Numbers and Quadratic Equations Case Study Questions

How should I study for my upcoming exams?

First, learn to sit for at least 2 hours at a stretch

Solve every question of NCERT by hand, without looking at the solution.

Solve NCERT Exemplar (if available)

Sit through chapter wise FULLY INVIGILATED TESTS

Practice MCQ Questions (Very Important)

Practice Assertion Reason & Case Study Based Questions

Sit through FULLY INVIGILATED TESTS involving MCQs. Assertion reason & Case Study Based Questions

After Completing everything mentioned above, Sit for atleast 6 full syllabus TESTS.

Contact Form

Privacy Policy

BYJU'S Future School Blog

Home / Blog / Math / Real-world Examples of the Application of Sets in Everyday Life

Learn With Math Companion

Real-world Examples of the Application of Sets in Everyday Life

SETS

What is Set Theory? What are Sets?

“Set theory is the mathematical theory of well-determined collections, called sets, of objects that are called members, or elements, of the set.” 1

A set is, to put it simply, a collection of unsorted objects, and as such, a set is defined by the objects it contains. The concept of sets is fundamental to the study of math and statistics, and it has numerous practical uses. 2 For example: to represent, gather, and analyze comparable data, sets are frequently used.

Significance Of Sets

We frequently use math to help us think about issues that may not initially appear to be mathematical. One subject with surprisingly varied applications is set theory. Since every branch of math uses or refers to sets in some way, they are crucial in all areas of math. They are required for the creation of ever-more complex mathematical structures. Set theory also gets off to a very straightforward start; it only considers whether an object belongs or does not belong to a common set of objects that have been unambiguously described. Because they more formally encode the entirety of information of a particular type, sets are essential, and due to their focus on the invariance of sets, set theory is equally important. 2

Examples of Sets in Real Life

Most of us have collections of our favorite things, groups of objects, like our favorite clothes, favorite foods, favorite people and places, etc. These are all parts of sets, and we use them every day. Here are a few examples of sets that are frequently used in our daily lives: 2, 3

Bookcase

One of the best examples of sets is a bookcase. You keep your books arranged in a specific way, either by alphabetical order, by genre, or by your personal favorites. As a result, groups of related books are stored separately from one another.

  • Closet 

closet

You might also keep your clothes arranged in a manner where the dresses, trousers, pants, coats, shawls, socks, etc., are kept together as a set. These related clothing groups are separated and kept apart from other sets of clothing.

bags

Bags can be excellent examples of sets regardless of the kind of bag you use, including lunch bags, school bags, and everyday bags. Most bags have specific sections where you can organize necessities in a way that is easily accessible. Your notepads, pens, pencils, textbooks, accessories, cash, snacks, etc., could be included in the examples of sets.

  • Jewelry Box

Jewelry Box

Another common example that most people can relate to is a jewelry box. You may keep your jewelry in sorted sets, including rings, chains, necklaces, and earrings.

Kitchen

Depending on our cooking preferences, we arrange our kitchen utensils and groceries in a particular way. Dishware like bowls, glasses, cups, and saucers are kept separate from plates, and pans and cutlery are kept in their own compartments. Sets of cooking utensils and other collections are kept apart in storage.

As seen above, there can be infinite examples of sets in our daily life. In addition to these, applications of set theory are frequently used in science and math fields like physics, biology, chemistry, as well as in electrical engineering and computer engineering. 

If you found this article on sets interesting, you can further explore the real-life examples of the golden ratio , linear functions , congruent triangles and triangles . Check out BYJU’s FutureSchool Blog for more interesting articles on math and its intriguing applications.

References:

  • Set Theory (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) . (n.d.). Retrieved August 25, 2022, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ 
  • Mehta, A., & Student, V. Y. (2014). APPLICATIONS OF SETS . www.physicsforums.com 
  • 7 Daily Life Examples Of Sets – StudiousGuy . (n.d.). Retrieved August 25, 2022, from https://studiousguy.com/daily-life-examples-of-sets/ 

Share Article:

case study of set theory

You might also like

Josiah willard gibbs, the math genius behind gibbs free energy, a brief introduction to george dantzig, the father of linear programming, lotfi zadeh: the man behind fuzzy logic, how to create a mobile math game, how effective is high school math in solving real-life problems, what is the importance of math in computer science, what type of math is used in gaming, what are the uses of math in everyday life.

Byjus Future School Blogs

SEP thinker apres Rodin

Set Theory is the mathematical science of the infinite. It studies properties of sets, abstract objects that pervade the whole of modern mathematics. The language of set theory, in its simplicity, is sufficiently universal to formalize all mathematical concepts and thus set theory, along with Predicate Calculus, constitutes the true Foundations of Mathematics. As a mathematical theory, Set Theory possesses a rich internal structure, and its methods serve as a powerful tool for applications in many other fields of Mathematics. Set Theory, with its emphasis on consistency and independence proofs, provides a gauge for measuring the consistency strength of various mathematical statements. There are four main directions of current research in set theory, all intertwined and all aiming at the ultimate goal of the theory: to describe the structure of the mathematical universe. They are: inner models, independence proofs, large cardinals, and descriptive set theory. See the relevant sections in what follows.

1. The Essence of Set Theory

2. origins of set theory, 3. the continuum hypothesis, 4. axiomatic set theory, 5. the axiom of choice, 6. inner models, 7. independence proofs, 8. large cardinals, 9. descriptive set theory, bibliography, other internet resources, related entries.

The objects of study of Set Theory are sets . As sets are fundamental objects that can be used to define all other concepts in mathematics, they are not defined in terms of more fundamental concepts. Rather, sets are introduced either informally, and are understood as something self-evident, or, as is now standard in modern mathematics, axiomatically, and their properties are postulated by the appropriate formal axioms.

The language of set theory is based on a single fundamental relation, called membership . We say that A is a member of B (in symbols A ∈ B ), or that the set B contains A as its element. The understanding is that a set is determined by its elements; in other words, two sets are deemed equal if they have exactly the same elements. In practice, one considers sets of numbers, sets of points, sets of functions, sets of some other sets and so on. In theory, it is not necessary to distinguish between objects that are members and objects that contain members -- the only objects one needs for the theory are sets. See the supplement

Basic Set Theory

for further discussion.

Using the membership relation one can derive other concepts usually associated with sets, such as unions and intersections of sets. For example, a set C is the union of two sets A and B if its members are exactly those objects that are either members of A or members of B . The set C is uniquely determined, because we have specified what its elements are. There are more complicated operations on sets that can be defined in the language of set theory (i.e. using only the relation ∈), and we shall not concern ourselves with those. Let us mention another operation: the (unordered) pair { A , B } has as its elements exactly the sets A and B . (If it happens that A = B , then the “pair” has exactly one member, and is called a singleton { A }.) By combining the operations of union and pairing, one can produce from any finite list of sets the set that contains these sets as members: { A,B,C,D,...,K,L,M }. We also mention the empty set , the set that has no elements. (The empty set is uniquely determined by this property, as it is the only set that has no elements - this is a consequence of the understanding that sets are determined by their elements.)

When dealing with sets informally, such operations on sets are self-evident; with the axiomatic approach, it is postulated that such operations can be applied: for instance, one postulates that for any sets A and B , the set { A,B } exists. In order to endow set theory with sufficient expressive power one needs to postulate more general construction principles than those alluded to above. The guiding principle is that any objects that can be singled out by means of the language can be collected into a set. For instance, it is desirable to have the “set of all integers that are divisible by number 3,” the “set of all straight lines in the Euclidean plane that are parallel to a given line”, the “set of all continuous real functions of two real variables” etc. Thus one is tempted to postulate that given any property P , there exists a set whose members are exactly all the sets that have property P . As we shall see below, such an assumption is logically inconsistent, and the accepted construction principles are somewhat weaker than such a postulate.

One of the basic principles of set theory is the existence of an infinite set. The concept can be formulated precisely in the language of set theory, using only the membership relation, and the definition captures the accepted meaning of “infinite”. See the supplement on

for further discussion. Using the basic construction principles, and assuming the existence of infinite sets, one can define numbers, including integers, real numbers and complex numbers, as well as functions, functionals, geometric and topological concepts, and all objects studied in mathematics. In this sense, set theory serves as Foundations of Mathematics . The significance of this is that all questions of provability (or unprovability) of mathematical statements can be in principle reduced to formal questions of formal derivability from the generally accepted axioms of Set Theory.

While the fact that all of mathematics can be reduced to a formal system of set theory is significant, it would hardly be a justification for the study of set theory. It is the internal structure of the theory that makes it worthwhile, and it turns out that this internal structure is enormously complex and interesting. Moreover, the study of this structure leads to significant questions about the nature of the mathematical universe.

The fundamental concept in the theory of infinite sets is the cardinality of a set. Two sets A and B have the same cardinality if there exists a mapping from the set A onto the set B which is one-to-one , that is, it assigns each element of A exactly one element of B . It is clear that when two sets are finite, then they have the same cardinality if and only if they have the same number of elements. One can extend the concept of the “number of elements” to arbitrary, even infinite, sets. It is not apparent at first that there might be infinite sets of different cardinalities, but once this becomes clear, it follows quickly that the structure so described is rich indeed.

The birth of Set Theory dates to 1873 when Georg Cantor proved the uncountability of the real line. (One could even argue that the exact birthdate is December 7, 1873, the date of Cantor's letter to Dedekind informing him of his discovery.) Until then, no one envisioned the possibility that infinities come in different sizes, and moreover, mathematicians had no use for “actual infinity.” The arguments using infinity, including the Differential Calculus of Newton and Leibniz, do not require the use of infinite sets, and infinity appears only as “a manner of speaking”, to paraphrase Friedrich Gauss. The fact that the set of all positive integers has a proper subset, like the set of squares {1, 4, 9, 16, 25,...} of the same cardinality (using modern terminology) was considered somewhat paradoxical (this had been discussed at length by Galileo among others). Such apparent paradoxes prevented Bernhard Bolzano in 1840s from developing set theory, even though some of his ideas are precursors of Cantor's work. (It should be mentioned that Bolzano, an accomplished mathematician himself, coined the word Menge (= set) that Cantor used for objects of his theory.)

Motivation for Cantor's discovery of Set Theory came from his work on Fourier series (which led him to introduce ordinal numbers ) and on trancendental numbers. Real numbers that are solutions of polynomial equations with integer coefficients are called algebraic, and the search was on for numbers that are not algebraic. A handful of these, called transcendental numbers, was discovered around that time, and a question arose how rare such numbers are. What Cantor did was to settle this question in an unexpected way, showing in one fell swoop that transcendental numbers are plentiful indeed. His famous proof went as follows: Let us call an infinite set A countable , if its elements can be enumerated; in other words, arranged in a sequence indexed by positive integers: a (1), a (2), a (3), … , a ( n ), … . Cantor observed that many infinite sets of numbers are countable: the set of all integers, the set of all rational numbers, and also the set of all algebraic numbers. Then he gave his ingeneous diagonal argument that proves, by contradiction, that the set of all real numbers is not countable. A consequence of this is that there exists a multitude of transcendental numbers, even though the proof, by contradiction, does not produce a single specific example. See the supplement on

Cantor's discovery of uncountable sets led him to the subsequent development of ordinal and cardinal numbers, with their underlying order and arithmetic, as well as to a plethora of fundamental questions that begged to be answered (such as the Continuum Hypothesis). After Cantor, mathematics has never been the same.

As the Continuum Hypothesis has been the most famous problem in Set Theory, let me explain what it says. The smallest infinite cardinal is the cardinality of a countable set. The set of all integers is countable, and so is the set of all rational numbers. On the other hand, the set of all real numbers is uncountable, and its cardinal is greater than the least infinite cardinal. A natural question arises: is this cardinal ( the continuum ) the very next cardinal. In other words, is it the case that there are no cardinals between the countable and the continuum? As Cantor was unable to find any set of real numbers whose cardinal lies strictly between the countable and the continuum, he conjectured that the continuum is the next cardinal: the Continuum Hypothesis. Cantor himself spent most of the rest of his life trying to prove the Continuum Hypothesis and many other mathematicians have tried too. One of these was David Hilbert, the leading mathematician of the last decades of the 19th century. At the World Congress of Mathematicians in Paris in 1900 Hilbert presented a list of major unsolved problems of the time, and the Continuum Hypothesis was the very first problem on Hilbert's list.

Despite the effort of a number of mathematicians, the problem remained unsolved until 1963, and it can be argued that in some sense the problem is still unsolved. See Section 7 on Independence Proofs .

In the years following Cantor's discoveries, development of Set Theory proceeded with no particular concern about how exactly sets should be defined. Cantor's informal “definition” was sufficient for proofs in the new theory, and the understanding was that the theory can be formalized by rephrasing the informal definition as a system of axioms . In the early 1900s it became clear that one has to state precisely what basic assumptions are made in Set Theory; in other words, the need has arisen to axiomatize Set Theory. This was done by Ernst Zermelo, and the immediate reasons for his axioms were twofold. The first one was the discovery of a paradox in Set Theory. This paradox is referred to as Russell's Paradox. Consider the “set” S of all sets that are not an element of itself. If one accepts the principle that all such sets can be collected into a set, then S should be a set. It is easy to see however that this leads to a contradiction (is the set S an element of itself?)

Russell's Paradox can be avoided by a careful choice of construction principles, so that one has the expressive power needed for usual mathematical arguments while preventing the existence of paradoxical sets. See the supplement on

Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory

for further discussion. The price one has to pay for avoiding inconsistency is that some “sets” do not exist. For instance, there exists no “universal” set (the set of all sets), no set of all cardinal numbers, etc.

The other reason for axioms was more subtle. In the course of development of Cantor's theory of cardinal and ordinal numbers a question was raised whether every set can be provided with a certain structure, called well-ordering of the set. Zermelo proved that indeed every set can be well-ordered, but only after he introduced a new axiom that did not seem to follow from the other, more self-evident, principles. His Axiom of Choice has become a standard tool of modern mathematics, but not without numerous objections of some mathematicians and discussions in both mathematical and philosophical literature. The history of the Axiom of Choice bears strong resemblance to that of the other notorious axiom, Euclid's Fifth Postulate.

The Axiom of Choice states that for every set of mutually disjoint nonempty sets there exists a set that has exactly one member common with each of these sets. For instance, let S be a set whose members are mutually disjoint finite sets of real numbers. We can choose in each X ∈ S the smallest number, and thus form a set that has exactly one member in common with each X ∈ S . What is not self-evident is whether we can make a choice every time, simultaneously for infinitely many sets X , regardless what these abstract sets are. The Axiom of Choice, which postulates the existence of a certain set ( the choice set ) without giving specific instructions how to construct such a set, is of different nature than the other axioms, which all formulate certain construction principles for sets. It was this nonconstructive nature of the Axiom of Choice that fed the controversy for years to come.

An interesting application of the Axiom of Choice is the Banach-Tarski Paradox that states that the unit ball can be partitioned into a finite number of disjoint sets which then can be rearranged to form two unit balls. This is of course a paradox only when we insist on visualizing abstract sets as something that exists in the physical world. The sets used in the Banach-Tarski Paradox are not physical objects, even though they do exist in the sense that their existence is proved from the axioms of mathematics (including the Axiom of Choice).

The legitimate question is whether the Axiom of Choice is consistent, that is whether it cannot be refuted from the other axioms. (Notice the similarity with the non Euclidean geometry.) This question was answered by Gödel, and eventually the role of the Axiom of Choice has been completely clarified. See Section 7 on Independence Proofs .

In the 1930s, Gödel stunned the mathematical world by discovering that mathematics is incomplete. His Incompleteness Theorem states that every axiomatic system that purports to describe mathematics as we know it must be incomplete, in the sense that one can find a true statement expressible in the system that cannot be formally proved from the axioms. In view of this result one must consider the possibility that a mathematical conjecture that resists a proof might be an example of such an unprovable statement, and Gödel immediately embarked on the project of showing that the Continuum Hypothesis might be undecidable in the axiomatic set theory.

Several years after proving the Incompleteness Theorem, Gödel proved another groundbreaking result: he showed that both the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis are consistent with the axioms of set theory, that is that neither can be refuted by using those axioms. This he achieved by discovering a model of set theory in which both the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis are true.

Gödel's model L of “constructible sets” has since served as a blueprint for building so-called inner models . These models form a hierarchy, corresponding to the hierarchy of large cardinals (see Section 8 ), and provide a glimpse into the as yet hidden structure of the mathematical universe. The advances in Inner Model Theory that have been made in the recent past owe much to the work of Ronald Jensen who introduced the study of the fine structure of constructible sets.

In 1963, Paul Cohen proved independence of the Axiom of Choice and of the Continuum Hypothesis. This he did by applying the method of forcing that he invented and constructing first a model of set theory (with the axiom of choice) in which the Continuum Hypothesis fails, and then a model of set theory in which the Axiom of Choice fails. Together with Gödel's models, these models show that the Axiom of Choice can neither be proved nor refuted from the other axioms, and that the Continuum Hypothesis can neither be proved nor refuted from the axioms of set theory (including the Axiom of Choice).

Cohen's method proved extremely fruitful and led first to the solution of a number of outstanding problems (Suslin's Problem, the Lebesgue measurability Problem, Borel's Conjecture, Kaplansky's Conjecture, Whitehead's Problem and so on) and soon has become one of the cornerstones of modern set theory. The technique of forcing has to date been applied by hundreds of authors of numerous articles and has enormously advanced our knowledge of Foundations of Mathematics. Along with the theory of large cardinals it is used to gauge the consistency strength of mathematical statements.

In 1930, while working on the Measure Problem, Stanislaw Ulam discovered an important phenomenon: Assuming that a certain mathematical statement about “small sets” (such as sets of real numbers) is true, one can prove the existence of sets of enormous size ( inaccessible ). This phenomenon has become more apparent after Dana Scott's celebrated result (1961) that measurable cardinals do not exist in L . Suddenly, large cardinals such as inaccessible, measurable, supercompact etc. have become the main focus of attention of set theorists. What emerged is a hierarchy of properties of infinite sets, the Large Cardinal Theory, that appears to be the basis for the structure of the set theoretical universe. Large cardinal axioms (also referred to as axioms of strong infinity ) form a hierarchy whereby a stronger axiom not only implies a weaker axiom but also proves its consistency. To date there are scores of examples of mathematical statements whose consistency strength can be precisely calculated in terms of the hierarchy of large cardinals. (For instance, a negative solution of the Singular Cardinal Problem corresponds to a large cardinal axiom between measurabily and supercompactness.)

Since the pioneering work of Ronald Jensen, Large Cardinal Theory has been closely tied with Inner Model Theory. It turns out that for each large cardinal axiom at lower levels of the hierarchy one can find an appropriate inner model. These inner models shed additional light on the structure of the universe by employing methods of Descriptive Set Theory.

Descriptive Set Theory traces its origins to the theory of integration by Henri Lebesgue at the beginning of 20th century. Investigations into Borel sets of real numbers led to the theory of projective sets, and more generally, the theory of definable sets of real numbers. Following Gödel's work, it became apparent that many natural questions in Descriptive Set Theory are undecidable in axiomatic set theory. This was further confirmed by a proliferation of independence results following Cohen's invention of the forcing method.

Modern Descriptive Set Theory revolves mostly around the powerful method using infinite games. The branch of Descriptive Set Theory known as Determinateness , developed by D. A. Martin, Robert Solovay and others, brought together methods of, among others, Recursion Theory and Large Cardinal Theory and has been very successful in describing the structure of definable sets. More importantly, Descriptive Set Theory provides strong evidence for the large cardinal axioms.

  • Cantor, G., 1932, Gesammelte Abhandlungen , Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
  • Ulam, S., 1930, ‘Zur Masstheorie in der allgemeinen Mengenlehre’, Fund. Math. , 16, 140-150.
  • Gödel, K., 1940, ‘The consistency of the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis’, Ann. Math. Studies , 3.
  • Scott, D., 1961, ‘Measurable cardinals and constructible sets’, Bull. Acad. Pol. Sci. , 9, 521-524.
  • Cohen, P., 1966, Set theory and the continuum hypothesis , New York: Benjamin.
  • Jensen, R., 1972, ‘The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy’, Ann. Math. Logic , 4, 229-308.
  • Martin, D. and Steel, J., 1989, ‘A proof of projective determinacy’, J. Amer. Math. Soc. , 2, 71-125.
  • Hrbacek, K. and Jech, T., 1999, Introduction to Set Theory , New York: Marcel Dekker, Inc.
  • Set Theory , maintained by Jean Larson (Mathematics, University of Florida)
  • " A History of Set Theory "
  • " Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor "
  • " Paul Joseph Cohen "
  • " Kurt Gödel "
  • " Ernst Friedrich Ferdinand Zermelo "
  • " Bernard Placidus Johann Nepomuk Bolzano "
  • A Homepage for the Axiom of Choice , maintained by Eric Schechter (Mathematics, Vanderbilt University)
  • Gödel's Incompleteness Theorem , maintained by Dale Myers (Mathematics, University of Hawaii)

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Frege, Gottlob: logic, theorem, and foundations for arithmetic | logic: classical | -->proof theory --> | Russell's paradox

  • School Guide
  • Mathematics
  • Number System and Arithmetic
  • Trigonometry
  • Probability
  • Mensuration
  • Maths Formulas
  • Class 8 Maths Notes
  • Class 9 Maths Notes
  • Class 10 Maths Notes
  • Class 11 Maths Notes
  • Class 12 Maths Notes

Set Theory Questions

  • Applications of Set Theory
  • Set Theory Formulas
  • Set Operations
  • Automata Theory | Set 9
  • Automata Theory | Set 4
  • Automata Theory | Set 8
  • Types of Sets in Set Theory
  • Reasoning | set 4 - TCS | Question 3
  • Reasoning | set 2 - TCS | Question 8
  • Reasoning | set 9 - TCS | Question 3
  • Reasoning | set 7 - TCS | Question 7
  • Reasoning | set 5 - TCS | Question 7
  • Reasoning | set 4 - TCS | Question 5
  • Reasoning | set 4 - TCS | Question 8
  • Test | quiz | Question 1
  • Reasoning | set 2 - TCS | Question 6
  • Reasoning | set 3 - TCS | Question 3
  • Reasoning | set 2 - TCS | Question 12

Set Questions have been provided here to simplify the concept of sets and relations for the students of Class 11. These set questions have been designed according to the latest CBSE syllabus. From basic sets and relations to set functions and subsets, we’ve covered key areas to help you develop a good understanding of set theory .

Set Questions and Solutions

Question 1: In a class of 40 students, 22 play hockey, 26 play basketball, and 14 play both. How many students do not play either of the games?

Let H be the set of students playing hockey, and B be the set playing basketball. n(H) = 22, n(B) = 26, n(H ∩ B) = 14. n(H ∪ B) = n(H) + n(B) – n(H ∩ B) = 22 + 26 – 14 = 34. Students not playing either = Total students – n(H ∪ B) = 40 – 34 = 6.

Question 2: If set A = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9} and set B = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}, find A ∪ B and A ∩ B.

A ∪ B (union) is the set of elements that are in A, or B, or both. A ∪ B = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 7, 9}. A ∩ B (intersection) is the set of elements that are in both A and B. A ∩ B = {1, 3, 5}.

Question 3: In a survey of 60 people, 25 liked tea, 30 liked coffee, and 10 liked both. How many people liked only tea?

Number of people who liked only tea = Number who liked tea – Number who liked both. = 25 – 10 = 15 people liked only tea.

Question 4: For sets A = {x | x is an integer, 1 ≤ x ≤ 6} and B = {x | x is an even integer, 2 ≤ x ≤ 8}, find the set A – B.

A = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6}, B = {2, 4, 6, 8}. A – B (difference) is the set of elements in A that are not in B. A – B = {1, 3, 5}.

Question 5: Given sets X = {a, b, c, d} and Y = {b, d, e, f}, find the symmetric difference of X and Y (denoted as X Δ Y).

X Δ Y is the set of elements in either X or Y, but not in their intersection. Intersection X ∩ Y = {b, d}. X Δ Y = (X ∪ Y) – (X ∩ Y) = {a, b, c, d, e, f} – {b, d} = {a, c, e, f}.

Question 6: If set C = {2, 4, 6, 8} and set D = {6, 8, 10, 12}, what are the sets C ∩ D and C ∪ D?

C ∩ D (intersection) is the set of elements common to both C and D. C ∩ D = {6, 8}. C ∪ D (union) is the set of all elements in C, or D, or both. C ∪ D = {2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12}.

Question 7: A survey of 100 students found that 70 students like pizza, 75 like burgers, and 60 like both. How many students like neither pizza nor burgers?

Let P be the set of students who like pizza, and B be the set who like burgers. n(P ∪ B) = n(P) + n(B) – n(P ∩ B) = 70 + 75 – 60 = 85. Students who like neither = Total students – n(P ∪ B) = 100 – 85 = 15.

Question 8: For sets E = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9} and F = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4}, find the set E ∪ F and the set E – F.

E ∪ F (union) is the set of elements in E, or F, or both. E ∪ F = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 7, 9}. E – F (difference) is the set of elements in E that are not in F. E – F = {5, 7, 9}.

Question 9: Given set G = {a, e, i, o, u} and set H = {a, e, y}, find the symmetric difference G Δ H.

G Δ H is the set of elements in either G or H, but not in their intersection. Intersection G ∩ H = {a, e}. G Δ H = (G ∪ H) – (G ∩ H) = {a, e, i, o, u, y} – {a, e} = {i, o, u, y}.

Question 10: In a group of 50 people, 28 like tea, 26 like coffee, and 12 like both. Find the number of people who like only coffee.

Number of people who like only coffee = Number who like coffee – Number who like both. = 26 – 12 = 14 people like only coffee.

Related Links:

  • Representation of a Set
  • Types of Set

Question 11: A class has 60 students. 35 students play football, 40 play cricket, and 15 play both. How many students play only one sport?

Number of students playing only one sport = Number playing football only + Number playing cricket only. = (Number playing football – Number playing both) + (Number playing cricket – Number playing both). = (35 – 15) + (40 – 15) = 20 + 25 = 45 students.

Question 12: Sets J = {2, 4, 6, 8, 10} and K = {3, 6, 9, 12}. Find the Cartesian product J × K.

J × K is the set of all ordered pairs (j, k) where j is in J and k is in K. J × K = {(2, 3), (2, 6), (2, 9), (2, 12), (4, 3), (4, 6), (4, 9), (4, 12), (6, 3), (6, 6), (6, 9), (6, 12), (8, 3), (8, 6), (8, 9), (8, 12), (10, 3), (10, 6), (10, 9), (10, 12)}.

Question 13: If set M = {x | x is a prime number less than 20} and set N = {x | x is an odd number less than 10}, what is M ∩ N?

M = {2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19}, N = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9}. M ∩ N (intersection) is the set of elements that are in both M and N. M ∩ N = {3, 5, 7}.

Question 14: A survey of 200 people found that 120 read newspaper A, 150 read newspaper B, and 90 read both. How many read at least one of the newspapers?

Use the formula: n(A ∪ B) = n(A) + n(B) – n(A ∩ B). n(A ∪ B) = 120 + 150 – 90 = 180. 180 people read at least one of the newspapers.

Question 15: For sets P = {a, b, c, d} and Q = {c, d, e, f, g}, find P ∪ Q and P – Q.

P ∪ Q (union) is the set of elements in P, or Q, or both. P ∪ Q = {a, b, c, d, e, f, g}. P – Q (difference) is the set of elements in P that are not in Q. P – Q = {a, b}.

Question 16: In a group of 50 people, 28 have traveled to Europe, 31 have traveled to Asia, and 10 have traveled to both continents. How many people have not traveled to either continent?

Use the principle of inclusion-exclusion. Number of people who have traveled to either continent = (Number to Europe) + (Number to Asia) – (Number to both). = 28 + 31 – 10 = 49. Number of people who haven’t traveled to either continent = Total people – Number who have traveled to either continent. = 50 – 49 = 1.

Question 17: Set X contains all even numbers between 1 and 20, and Set Y contains all multiples of 3 between 1 and 20. Find X ∩ Y.

X = {2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 14, 16, 18, 20}, Y = {3, 6, 9, 12, 15, 18}. X ∩ Y (intersection) is the set of elements common to both X and Y. X ∩ Y = {6, 12, 18}.

Question 18: If Set A = {2, 4, 6, 8} and Set B = {1, 3, 5, 7, 9}, find the Cartesian product A × B and B × A.

A × B = {(2, 1), (2, 3), (2, 5), (2, 7), (2, 9), (4, 1), (4, 3), (4, 5), (4, 7), (4, 9), (6, 1), (6, 3), (6, 5), (6, 7), (6, 9), (8, 1), (8, 3), (8, 5), (8, 7), (8, 9)}. B × A = {(1, 2), (1, 4), (1, 6), (1, 8), (3, 2), (3, 4), (3, 6), (3, 8), (5, 2), (5, 4), (5, 6), (5, 8), (7, 2), (7, 4), (7, 6), (7, 8), (9, 2), (9, 4), (9, 6), (9, 8)}.

Question 19: In a survey of 150 people, 95 like apples, 70 like bananas, and 60 like both apples and bananas. Find the number of people who like only apples.

Number of people who like only apples = Number who like apples – Number who like both apples and bananas. = 95 – 60 = 35 people.

Question 20: Given sets L = {x | x is a positive integer less than 6} and M = {x | x is a positive integer and a multiple of 2}, find L ∪ M and L ∩ M.

L = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}, M = {2, 4, 6, 8, 10, …}. L ∪ M (union) = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 8, 10, …} (all positive integers less than 6 and all multiples of 2). L ∩ M (intersection) = {2, 4} (elements that are both less than 6 and multiples of 2).

To sum up, set theory is an important chapter for the students of Class 11. Through this article, we’ve explored a variety of set questions, offering clear solutions that follow the NCERT and CBSE guidelines. Practising these sets questions will help you develop a good foundation to solve more complex problems further.

Please Login to comment...

Similar reads.

  • Math-Queries
  • School Learning

Improve your Coding Skills with Practice

 alt=

What kind of Experience do you want to share?

  • Math Article
  • Basics Set Theory

Set Theory is a branch of mathematical logic where we learn sets and their properties. A set is a collection of objects or groups of objects. These objects are often called elements or members of a set. For example, a group of players in a cricket team is a set. 

Since the number of players in a cricket team could be only 11 at a time, thus we can say, this set is a finite set. Another example of a finite set is a set of English vowels. But there are many sets that have infinite members such as a set of natural numbers, a set of whole numbers, set of real numbers, set of imaginary numbers, etc. 

Set Theory Origin

Georg Cantor (1845-1918), a German mathematician, initiated the concept ‘Theory of sets’ or ‘Set Theory’. While working on “ Problems on Trigonometric Series ”,  he encountered sets, that have become one of the most fundamental concepts in mathematics. Without understanding sets, it will be difficult to explain the other concepts such as relations, functions, sequences, probability, geometry, etc.

Definition of Sets

As we have already learned in the introduction, set is a well-defined collection of objects or people. Sets can be related to many real-life examples, such as the number of rivers in India, number of colours in a rainbow, etc. 

To understand sets, consider a practical scenario. While going to school from home, Nivy decided to note down the names of restaurants which come in between. The list of the restaurants, in the order they came, was:

\(\begin{array}{l} List\ 1: R_A ~~~~~       R_B ~~~~~       R_C ~~~~~       R_D ~~~~~       R_E \end{array} \)

The above-mentioned list is a collection of objects. Also, it is well-defined. By well-defined, it is meant that anyone should be able to tell whether the object belongs to the particular collection or not. E. g. a stationary shop can’t come in the category of the restaurants. If the collection of objects is well-defined, it is known as a set.

The objects in a set are referred to as elements of the set. A set can have finite or infinite elements. While coming back from the school, Nivy wanted to confirm the list what she had made earlier. This time again, she wrote the list in the order in which restaurants came. The new list was:

\(\begin{array}{l}List\ 2: R_E ~~~~~        R_D~~~~~        R_C ~~~~~       R_B  ~~~~~      R_A \end{array} \)

Now, this is a different list. But is a different set? The answer is no. The order of elements has no significance in sets so it is still the same set.

Representation of Sets

Sets can be represented in two ways:

  • Roster Form or Tabular form

Set Builder Form

Roster form.

In roster form, all the elements of the set are listed, separated by commas and enclosed between curly braces { }. 

Example: If set represents all the leap years between the year 1995 and 2015, then it would be described using Roster form as:

A ={1996,2000,2004,2008,2012}

Now, the elements inside the braces are written in ascending order. This could be descending order or any random order. As discussed before, the order doesn’t matter for a set represented in the Roster Form. 

Also, multiplicity is ignored while representing the sets. E.g. If L represents a set that contains all the letters in the word ADDRESS, the proper Roster form representation would be

L ={A,D,R,E,S }= {S,E,D,A,R}  

L≠ {A,D,D,R,E,S,S}

In set builder form, all the elements have a common property. This property is not applicable to the objects that do not belong to the set. 

Example: If set S has all the elements which are even prime numbers, it is represented as:

S={ x: x is an even prime number}

where ‘x’ is a symbolic representation that is used to describe the element.

‘:’ means ‘such that’

‘{}’ means ‘the set of all’

So, S = { x:x is an even prime number } is read as ‘the set of all x such that x is an even prime number’. The roster form for this set S would be S = 2. This set contains only one element. Such sets are called singleton/unit sets.

Another Example:

F = {p: p is a set of two-digit perfect square numbers}

F = {16, 25, 36, 49, 64, 81}

We can see, in the above example, 16 is a square of 4, 25 is square of 5, 36 is square of 6, 49 is square of 7, 64 is square of 8 and 81 is a square of 9}. 

Even though, 4, 9, 121, etc., are also perfect squares, but they are not elements of the set F, because the it is limited to only two-digit perfect square.

Types of Sets

The sets are further categorised into different types, based on elements or types of elements. These different types of sets in basic set theory are:

  • Finite set: The number of elements is finite
  • Infinite set: The number of elements are infinite
  • Empty set: It has no elements
  • Singleton set: It has one only element
  • Equal set: Two sets are equal if they have same elements
  • Equivalent set: Two sets are equivalent if they have same number of elements
  • Power set: A set of every possible subset.
  • Universal set: Any set that contains all the sets under consideration.
  • Subset: When all the elements of set A belong to set B, then A is subset of B

Set Theory Symbols

There are several symbols that are adopted for common sets. They are given in the table below:

Table 1: Symbols denoting common sets

Other Notations

Set theory formulas.

  • n( A ∪ B ) = n(A) +n(B) – n (A ∩ B) 
  • n(A∪B)=n(A)+n(B)   {when A and B are disjoint sets}
  • n(U)=n(A)+n(B)–n(A∩B)+n((A∪B) c )
  • n(A∪B)=n(A−B)+n(B−A)+n(A∩B) 
  • n(A−B)=n(A∩B)−n(B) 
  • n(A−B)=n(A)−n(A∩B) 
  • n(A c )=n(U)−n(A)
  • n(PUQUR)=n(P)+n(Q)+n(R)–n(P⋂Q)–n(Q⋂R)–n(R⋂P)+n(P⋂Q⋂R) 

Set Operations

The four important set operations that are widely used are:

  • Union of sets
  • Intersection of sets
  • Complement of sets
  • Difference of sets

Fundamental Properties of Set operations:

Like addition and multiplication operation in algebra, the operations such as union and intersection in set theory obeys the properties of associativity and commutativity. Also, the intersection of sets distributes over the union of sets.

Sets are used to describe one of the most important concepts in mathematics i.e. functions. Everything that you observe around you, is achieved with mathematical models which are formulated, interpreted and solved by functions.

Problems and Solutions

Q.1: If U = {a, b, c, d, e, f}, A = {a, b, c}, B = {c, d, e, f}, C = {c, d, e}, find (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C).

Solution: A ∩ B = {a, b, c} ∩ {c, d, e, f}

A ∩ B = { c }

A ∩ C = { a, b, c } ∩ { c, d, e }

A ∩ C = { c }

∴ (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C) = { c }

Q.2: Give examples of finite sets.

Solution: The examples of finite sets are:

Set of months in a year

Set of days in a week

Set of natural numbers less than 20

Set of integers greater than -2 and less than 3

Q.3: If U = {2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11}, A = {3, 5, 7, 9, 11} and B = {7, 8, 9, 10, 11}, Then find (A – B)′.

Solution: A – B is a set of member which belong to A but do not belong to B

∴ A – B = {3, 5, 7, 9, 11} – {7, 8, 9, 10, 11}

A – B = {3, 5}

According to formula,

(A − B)′ = U – (A – B)

∴ (A − B)′ = {2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11} – {3, 5}

(A − B)′ = {2, 4, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11}.

Video Lessons

Introduction to sets.

case study of set theory

Principle of Inclusion and Exclusion

case study of set theory

For more set theory rules, formulas and examples, register with us. To watch videos and understand the concepts, download BYJU’S-The Learning App from Google Play Store.

Frequently Asked Questions – FAQs

What is the basic of set theory, what are the types of sets, what is the formula of set, how many elements does a singleton set have give an example., how can we represent the sets, leave a comment cancel reply.

Your Mobile number and Email id will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Request OTP on Voice Call

Post My Comment

case study of set theory

it is great but pls add a video

It is a great flashcard! definitely recommended!

case study of set theory

  • Share Share

Register with BYJU'S & Download Free PDFs

Register with byju's & watch live videos.

close

  • Privacy Policy
  • Terms and Conditions

Twitter

  • Web Stories

Friday, December 17, 2021

Class 11 maths case study based questions chapter 1 sets term 1 with answer key.

Class 11 Maths Case Study Based Questions Chapter 1 SETS Term 1 with Answer Key

Hello students, Welcome to Maths Easy Institute.  

Class 11 Maths Case Study Based Questions Chapter 1 SETS Term 1 with Answer Key

0 comments:

Post a comment.

Please do not enter any spam link in the comment box.

Warning: Do Not Copy!

  • Blog Archives

' border=

  • Best Books for IIT JEE
  • Best Colleges Of India
  • class 10 Case Study Based questions
  • Class 10 Maths MCQ
  • Class 11 Maths Case Study Questions
  • Class 11 Maths MCQ
  • Class 12 Math Case Study questions
  • Class 12 Maths MCQ
  • JEE MAIN MCQ
  • Maths Strategy JEE
  • News for Students

Blog Archive

  • ►  April (3)
  • ►  March (2)
  • ►  February (1)
  • ►  January (5)
  • JEE MAIN Maths MCQ Chapter Application Of Derivati...
  • JEE MAIN Maths MCQ Chapter Relations and Functions...
  • JEE MAIN Maths MCQ Chapter SETS with Answers
  • Class 11 Maths MCQ Chapter 11 Conic Section CBSE B...
  • Class 11 Maths Case Study Based Questions Chapter ...
  • Class 11 Maths MCQ Chapter 7 Permutation and Combi...
  • Class 12 Maths MCQ Chapter 7 Integration with Answ...
  • Class 10 Maths MCQ chapter 7 Coordinate Geometry C...
  • Class 10 Maths MCQ chapter 5 Arithmetic Progressio...
  • ►  November (5)
  • ►  October (6)
  • ►  September (5)
  • ►  April (4)
  • ►  March (3)
  • ►  October (2)
  • ►  September (7)
  • ►  August (2)
  • ►  July (4)

My photo

IMAGES

  1. (PDF) Introduction to Set Theory & Logic

    case study of set theory

  2. Set Theory Tutorial

    case study of set theory

  3. PPT

    case study of set theory

  4. Set Theory Sets

    case study of set theory

  5. PPT

    case study of set theory

  6. Set Theory Introduction and Basic Concepts Lec 01

    case study of set theory

VIDEO

  1. Set Theory IIT Questions No 12 (X Class)

  2. A Basic Introduction to Set Theory

  3. نظريه المجموعات

  4. EAAEA Chapter 4: Set Theory

  5. lec.6 set theory/practical problems on sets

  6. Concept of Set theory

COMMENTS

  1. PDF Set Theory

    Set Theory Sets A set is a collection of objects, called its elements. We write x2Ato mean that xis an element of a set A, we also say that xbelongs to Aor that xis in A. If Aand Bare sets, we say that Bis a subset of Aif every element of B is an element of A. In this case we also say that Acontains B, and we write BˆA.

  2. PDF AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY

    Set Theory is the true study of infinity. This alone assures the subject of a place prominent in human culture. But even more, Set Theory is the milieu in which mathematics takes place today. As such, it is expected to provide a firm foundation for the rest of mathematics. And it does—up to a point; we will prove theorems shedding light on ...

  3. PDF Lecture 7: Set Theory and Logic

    Pairing For any two sets, there exists a set which contains both sets. Property For any property, there exists a set for which each element has the property. Union Given a set of sets, there exists a set which is the union of these sets. Power Given a set, there exists the set of all subsets of this set. In nity There exists an in nite set.

  4. Set theory

    Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory — as a branch of mathematics — is mostly concerned with those that are relevant to mathematics as a whole. The modern study of set theory was ...

  5. Set Theory

    From Cantor and until about 1940, set theory developed mostly around the study of the continuum, that is, the real line \(\mathbb{R}\). The main topic was the study of the so-called regularity properties, as well as other structural properties, of simply-definable sets of real numbers, an area of mathematics that is known as Descriptive Set Theory.

  6. The Early Development of Set Theory

    It is not the case that actual infinity was universally rejected before Cantor. Set-theoretic views did not arise exclusively from analysis, but emerged also in algebra, number theory, and geometry. ... Descriptive set theory (DST) is the study of certain kinds of definable sets of real numbers, which are obtained from simple kinds (like the ...

  7. Models as Fundamental Entities in Set Theory: A Naturalistic and

    This article addresses the question of fundamental entities in set theory. It takes up J. Hamkins' claim that models of set theory are such fundamental entities and investigates it using the methodology of P. Maddy's naturalism, Second Philosophy. In accordance with this methodology, I investigate the historical case study of the use of models in the introduction of forcing, compare this ...

  8. 1.1: Basic Concepts of Set Theory

    1.1: Basic Concepts of Set Theory. Intuitively, a set is a collection of objects with certain properties. The objects in a set are called the elements or members of the set. We usually use uppercase letters to denote sets and lowercase letters to denote elements of sets. If a is an element of set A, we write a ∈ A.

  9. Set theory

    The branch of set theory concerned with the study of operations on sets (not only finite, but also infinite operations) is called the algebra of sets. The algebra of sets, in its turn, is a special case of the theory of Boolean algebras (cf. Boolean algebra ). Set theory was created by the work of 19th century mathematicians, who posed the aim ...

  10. 4.1: Basic Notions of Set Theory

    In Set theory, they are "set", "element" and "membership.". These concepts (more or less) correspond to one another. In most books, a set is denoted either using the letter M M (which stands for the German word "menge") or early alphabet capital roman letters - A A, B B, C C, et cetera. Here, we will often emphasize the ...

  11. Basic Set Theory

    Basic Set Theory. Sets are well-determined collections that are completely characterized by their elements. Thus, two sets are equal if and only if they have exactly the same elements. The basic relation in set theory is that of elementhood, or membership. We write \ (a\in A\) to indicate that the object \ (a\) is an element, or a member, of ...

  12. V = L and Intuitive Plausibility in set Theory. A Case Study

    At the same time, I present accounts of set theoretic axioms and theorems formulated in non-strictly mathematical terms, e.g., by appealing to the iterative concept of set and/or to overall methodological principles, like unify and maximize, and investigate the relation of the latter to success in mathematics.

  13. Set Theory

    Set Theory is a branch of logical mathematics that studies the collection of objects and operations based on it. A set is simply a collection of objects or a group of objects. For example, a group of players in a football team is a set and the players in the team are its objects. The words collection, aggregate, and class are synonymous with ...

  14. Set-Theoretic Methods for the Social Sciences

    Book description. Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) and other set-theoretic methods distinguish themselves from other approaches to the study of social phenomena by using sets and the search for set relations. In virtually all social science fields, statements about social phenomena can be framed in terms of set relations, and using set ...

  15. 1.1.E: Problems in Set Theory (Exercises)

    Exercise 1.1.E. 1 1.1. E. 1. Prove Theorem 1 (show that x x is in the left-hand set iff it is in the right-hand set). For example, for (d), ( d), x ∈ (A ∪ B) ∩ C [x ∈ (A ∪ B) and x ∈ C] [(x ∈ A or x ∈ B), and x ∈ C] [(x ∈ A, x ∈ C) or (x ∈ B, x ∈ C)]. x ∈ ( A ∪ B) ∩ C [ x ∈ ( A ∪ B) and x ∈ C] [ ( x ∈ A ...

  16. CBSE Case Study Questions for Class 11 Maths Sets Free PDF

    Mere Bacchon, you must practice the CBSE Case Study Questions Class 11 Maths Sets in order to fully complete your preparation.They are very very important from exam point of view. These tricky Case Study Based Questions can act as a villain in your heroic exams!. I have made sure the questions (along with the solutions) prepare you fully for the upcoming exams.

  17. Real-world Examples of the Application of Sets in Real Life

    "Set theory is the mathematical theory of well-determined collections, called sets, of objects that are called members, or elements, of the set." 1 The concept of sets is fundamental to the study of math and statistics, and it has numerous practical uses. 2 For example: to represent, gather, and analyze comparable data, sets are frequently ...

  18. Set Theory

    Set Theory is the mathematical science of the infinite. It studies properties of sets, abstract objects that pervade the whole of modern mathematics. The language of set theory, in its simplicity, is sufficiently universal to formalize all mathematical concepts and thus set theory, along with Predicate Calculus, constitutes the true Foundations ...

  19. Important Set Theory Questions with Solutions

    Set Questions have been provided here to simplify the concept of sets and relations for the students of Class 11. These set questions have been designed according to the latest CBSE syllabus. From basic sets and relations to set functions and subsets, we've covered key areas to help you develop a good understanding of set theory.. Set Questions and Solutions

  20. Set Theory (Basics, Definitions, Types of sets, Symbols & Examples)

    Set Theory is a branch of mathematical logic where we learn sets and their properties. A set is a collection of objects or groups of objects. These objects are often called elements or members of a set. For example, a group of players in a cricket team is a set. Since the number of players in a cricket team could be only 11 at a time, thus we ...

  21. A Necessary Dialogue: Theory in Case Study Research

    A theory of the case is perhaps a neglected aspect in discussions of case study and theory. The "case" does not just exist as a "case" in itself but has to be constructed as a case for study. This entails the researcher conceptualizing what the "bounded system" of the case is; what constitutes the case; what it includes and excludes ...

  22. Class 11 Maths Case Study Based Questions Chapter 1 SETS ...

    In set theory, the complement of a set A, often denoted by A c (or A′), are the elements not in A. let U be a set that contains all the elements under study; if there is no need to mention U, either because it has been previously specified, or it is obvious and unique, then the absolute complement of A is the relative complement of A in U: